DERRIDA’S DECONSTRUCTION
AS A METHOD OF ANALYSIS OF
LANGUAGE
Thesis submitted to the University of Calicut
for the award of the Degree of
DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY
in Philosophy
By
DEVADASAN. P. (PAROL)
Supervised by
Dr. A. KANTHAMANI
Professor
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY
UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT
2008
Chapter I
'I am touched by Deconstruction'
– Gayatri Chakravorty Sipvak
THE LINGUISTIC TURN
IN PHILOSOPHY
CHAPTER I
THE LINGUISTIC TURN IN PHILOSOPHY
1.1 The Linguistic Turn and the Deconstructive Turn: The
Entente Cordiale
The objective of the thesis is to widen the scope of the Derridean
rigours of deconstruction to cover the logic of the entire analytic traditions
found within the analytic traditions (Frege, Russell and early Wittgenstein), as
well as in the post-analytic traditions (Quine, Davidson and Dummett).
Before such an enquiry, it becomes necessary to unpack some of the leading
definitions of deconstruction at the outset, so as to take it in the ‘maximalist’
sense than the ‘minimalist’ construal of analysis as envisaged by Christopher
Norris.#
In his attempt to deconstruct logocentrism – the ‘ phonocentric’
suspicion of writing as a parasite upon the authenticity of speech – Derrida
translated and adapted the German words ‘destruktion’ or ‘Abbau’
#
The author of fifteen books. Dr. A Kanthamani construes the entire corpus as
analytical, post-analytical, hermeneutic and the cognitive turns. Norris seriously
believe that the last three phases are symptomatic of ‘dead-end predicament’.(6)
along with non-rigorous literary portrayals of deconstruction. For Norris, any
‘alliance’ between post-analytic and ‘depth-ontological’ (‘Heideggerian depth-
hermeneutics’ is an ‘improbable’ one (21). Again, the rapprochement between the
post-analytic and depth-analytical projects (40) emphasis in the original) have
nothing whatsoever in common (39). Contra Norris, my aim is to vindicate a thesis
according to which the combinatorial game (deconstruction, post-modernism and
critical theory) has a higher pay-off in the climate of naturalism.
1
(unbuilding) for his own convenience. How the word first occurred to him in
the ‘Littre/’, and the meaning it conveys, Derrida writes in the following way
in a letter to his Japanese friend Professor Izutzu.1
The grammatical linguistic or rhetorical senses [porte /es] were found
bound up with a ‘Mechanical’ sense [Porte /es ‘Machnique’]. Derrida explains
some of the entries from the ‘Littre/’, according to which deconstruction is:
‘Disarranging the construction words in a sentence’.*
‘ To disassemble the parts of a whole. To deconstruct verse, rendering it by
the suppression of meter, similar to prose'.+2
‘A language reaching its own state of perfection is deconstructed [se’st
deconstruive] and altered from within itself according to the single law of
change, natural to human mind’.3
According to Derrida, ‘deconstruction is not simply the decomposition
of an architectural structure; it is also a question about the foundation, about
the relation between foundation and what is founded; it is also a question
about the closure of the structure about the whole structure of philosophy’. 4
‘Any attempt to define ‘deconstruction’ must soon run up against the many
and varied obstacles that Derrida has shrewdly placed in its path’. 5 However
*
Of deconstruction, Derrida further explains, a common way of saying construction,
Lemare, De la maniere da/pprendre les langues, chap. 17, in Cours de Langue
Latine.
+
In the system of prenotional sentences, one also starts with translation and one of
its advantages is never needing to deconstruction, Lemare, Ibid.
2
interpreters of Derrida have attempted to define deconstruction and some of
them are given here.
Christopher Norris defines deconstruction as “the vigilant seeking out
of those ‘aporias’ blindspots or moments of self- contradiction where a text
involuntarily betrays the tension between rhetoric and logic, between what it
manifestly means to say and what it is nonetheless constrained to mean.” 6
And so, it is the “dismantling of conceptual oppositions, the taking apart of
hierarchical systems of thought which can then be reinscribed within a
different order of textual signification.”
Geoffrey Bennington is ready to give up it as “not as a theory or a
project”. It does not prescribe a practice more or less faithful to it nor project
an image of a desirable state to be brought about. All of Derrida’s texts are
already applications, so there is no separate ‘Derrida’ in the form of theory
who might then be applied to something else. ……… we cannot simply be
content to claim that Derrida (sometimes) applies his own theory or unites
theory and practice, or performs theoretical practice.7
Barbara Johnson admits that the word “deconstruction” is closely
related not to the word “destruction” but to the word “analysis”, which
etymologically means “to undo” – a virtual synonym for “to deconstruct”
…….8
3
According to John D. Caputo the very meaning and mission of
deconstruction is to show that things, texts, institutions, traditions, societies,
beliefs and practices of whatever size and sort you need – do not have
definable meanings and determinable missions, that they are always more
than any mission would impose, that they exceed the boundaries they
currently occupy……….. A ‘meaning’ of a ‘mission’ is a way to contain and
compact things, like a nutshell, gathering them into a unity whereas
deconstruction bends all its efforts to stretch beyond these
boundaries………… Whenever deconstruction finds a nutshell – a secure
axion or a pithy maxim – the very idea is to crack it open and disturb this
tranquility….. cracking nutshells is what deconstruction is.9
Deconstruction tries “to undo” the structural significations by means of
analysis of language and reinscribe them in a different order of textual
signification. How do deconstruction undo the structural significations? What
type of analysis is involved in it?
Before making an assessment of the interface between deconstruction
and the analysis, we shall give a quick review of both analytical and post-
analytical traditions so as to keep them at the backdrop. Norris is an exemplar
because he borrows rigour from analytic philosophy and foists deconstruction,
thereby making it inseparably bound and non-distinct. To him, deconstruction
is not textual ‘free play’ but symbolizes the very notions of rigorous thinking
4
or conceptual critique. He is of the opinion that the central issues of
deconstruction can be set forth and defended in such a way as to engage the
serious interest of philosophers in the ‘other’, Anglo-American or analytical
tradition.10 Norris wants to expound a novel thesis which is stated as
Thesis I: Deconstruction is a sub-branch of philosophy (analytical
philosophy, to be more precise). To demonstrate the above thesis, Norris
conflates the post-analytical with post-modernism (sub-thesis). Both are not
in his good books. It is an open question whether his thesis and sub-thesis can
be sustained. We shall review his position Motif 3 after covering the post-
analytical motif (Motif 1 & 2) as dealt separately with two leading thinkers.
We shall review his position as motif 3 after covering the past-analytical
Motif (1 & 2) as they are dealt separately in chapters 2 and 3. Motif 3
(Derridean ‘Rigour of Analysis’) is subserved by the following
considerations:
1) There is a logic of deconstruction;
2) This logic has a certain argumentative rigour;
3) This is demonstrated by ‘close reading’ of the texts from ‘Plato-Nato’
(Plato, Aristotle, Rousseau, Kant, Hegal and Husserl; Nato we shall see
in ‘late’ Derrida).
4) This subscribes to the Kantian enlightenment ideals (e.g rationality in
science);
5
5) This requires the thematic closure from two key notions such as the
‘condition of possibility’ (Norris) and the ‘condition of impossibility’
(Rudolph Gasche).
6) This makes full use of resources of (minimal) realism/naturalism
(contra anti-realism/scepticism).
We can as well as counterpose the early part with the later which is
purported to be a short review of Norris to maintain the status-quo of the
combinatorial game. But it is not necessary as the lines of distinction between
modernism and post-modernism (unfinished project of modernity) as well as
the distinction between analytical and post-analytical tradition are only thinly
drawn. We shall take up issues with Glock for the broadside criticism on the
post-analytical ‘naturalism’. Norris’s ‘resources’ of realism is an option to be
reckoned with, but its efficacy is far from influential even in the recent
developments of cognitive science. Norris opts for a more narrower construal
given as
Thesis 2: Deconstruction is a sub-branch of ethics (Socio-political and ethico-
juridical claims) as it is true of ‘late’ Derrida.
Now Thesis 2 is fully potent enough to counter the derogatory reading of
Thesis 3: Deconstruction is a sub-branch of literary theory. (a la Rorty)
6
There is more politics of deconstruction than of analysis, that will
resemble post-modernist thinking let loose by Francis Fukuyma (‘end of
history’) or Habermas, in his ‘unfinished project of modernity’. So Norris is
after all blows hot and cold against the reading of post-analytical seriousness.
That bids us to move to Thesis 4.
Motif 1 (Quine’s ‘Deconstructivist Logic’) is subserved by Samuel
Wheeler’s reading which seeks out parallelism or analogism between Quine,
Davidson and Derrida and of course, Paul de Man as well. They nonetheless
reach similar positions on the basis of analogous considerations indicates that
from their different traditions in the exact sense that a common problem has
emerged that transcends the particularities of those traditions. The parallelism
also implies a sort of ‘competitiveness’ as evidenced in the way Philosophical
Investigations of Wittgenstein replies to Logical Investigations of Husserl.
Competitiveness apart, this motif moves the logic of post-analytical
philosophy towards the logic of deconstruction that is very similar to the
motif 2 which is placed next in the line.
Motif 2 (‘Structural Affinity Thesis’) is subserved by Henry Staten’s
direct comparison between Wittgenstein and Derrida tries to bring
“Derrida’s” project into relation with Wittgenstein and strongly suggests the
Anglo-American context of ‘ordinary language’ as an operational concept.
7
It states that, “Wittgenstein’s Tractatus bears close affinities to
Husserl’s Logical Investigations” and that “Derrida’s penetrating
consideration and ultimate rejection of the basic principles of Husserl’s
philosophy of language is the historical analogue of Wittgenstein’s later
consideration and rejection of his own earlier work, the Tractatus-Logico-
Philosophicus. With a microscopic fidelity Staten observes the different areas
where Wittgenstein and Derrida’s philosophies come across and states that
‘there is a filation between the texts, and the new threads must be twisted onto
the old ones with the tightness appropriate to philosophical textuality’.
Staten chooses Husserl’s ‘Origin of Geometry’, as a “perspicuous
area” of “deconstructive reading of Wittgenstein’s work” taking this as the
historical analogue of Wittgenstein’s later considerations and rejection of his
own earlier work, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Hence Staten says
that the more one reads the Logical Investigations next to the Philosophical
Investigations, the more striking the relation between the two becomes, taking
the cue from Blue Book which, on his reading consistently deconstructive,
which acts as a bridge between the early and later Wittgenstein.
It is in this context ‘the linguistic turn’ in philosophy suggests certain
deconstructive motifs. Although this Rortian expression first occurs in 1967,
there are difference of opinions on the question of when did the linguistic turn
occur in the history of philosophy. While P.M.S Hacker traces the origin of
8
this turn with Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, a writer like Antony Kenny, following
Dummett, is of the opinion that if analytic philosophy was born when ‘the
linguistic turn’, was taken, its birthday must be dated to the publication of The
Foundations of Arithmetic in 1884 – when Frege decided that the way to
investigate the nature of number was to analyse sentences in which numerals
occured.11 Taking the term ‘analysis’ au pied de la lettre, twentieth century
analytic philosophy is distinguished in its origins by its non-psychological
orientation. One (Russellian) root of this new school might be denominated
‘logico-analytic philosophy’, in as much as its central tenet was the new logic,
introduced by Frege, Russell and Whitehead, provided an instrument for the
logical analysis of objective phenomena. 12 However, Motif 3 sponsors a
‘divide-and-rule’ strategy by aligning Derrida with the analytical tradition of
Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein and at the expense of the post-analytical
tradition of Quine, Davidson and Dummett. Such a strategy enables him to
overlook what is very likely to ‘survive’ the ‘crisis’ of analytic philosophy.
(see the remarks of Hintikka and Putnam on page 40)
Norris proposes the following counter-theses to support his
perspective:
[A] against Quine
(a) The two dogmas of empiricism:
9
(b) The case of the field-linguist theory which holds that there is an
indeterminacy of radical translation; that is the anthropologist is not
sure whether
gavagai = rabbit
is the exact translation.
(c) Ontological relativity which holds that there is no way of individuating
objects or belief-contents except in relation to the entire ‘web’ or
‘fabric’;
(d) The meaning-holism which lacks any appeal to intermediary entities
(propositions/statements/sentences).
From (a) – (d), it follows that the Human predicament is not the Humean
predicament; realism wins hands down.
[B] against Davidson
(a) His dualism of scheme and content;
(b) His dualism or prior and passing theory;
(c) His principle of charity at maximizing truth-content;
(d) His throwaway pronouncement: ‘there is no such think as language’;
(e) His account of malapropism in interpretations;
10
[C] against Dummett
(a) His founding of analytic philosophy on the ‘foundation’ of a theory of
meaning; systematizing analytic philosophy into a coherent set of
beliefs.
(b) His using of Fregean doctrine of sense for an upbeat anti-realism;
(c) His using of Wittgenstein’s doctrine of ‘meaning-as-use’ to
counterpose the later Wittgenstein to the early Wittgenstein;
(d) His way of sustaining the anti-realistic tenure by holding that there
could not be any truth beyond what is verifiable (verification-
transcendent truth).
Does Norris using the above [A], [B] and [C], succeed to counterpose anti-
realism with a tenable realism (minimal realism), notwithstanding the inner
fissures? The question is answered negatively in the course of the thesis.
Together with their positives might, they extend Thesis (1).
FØllesdal has a definite answer with his ‘genetic affiliation thesis’
(Thesis 5). To him, the label ‘analytic philosophy’ is inappropriate even for
survey purposes, that the whole division of contemporary philosophy into
‘continental’ and ‘analytic’ is fundamentally flawed.13 The thesis states that
there is a genetic affiliation between the continental and analytic philosophy
(A.W Moore calls this as a ‘clumsy’ distinction). F Øllesdal looks at the
11
standard classification model of dividing philosophy between the analytic and
the continental with the following diagramme.
ANALYTIC
CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY
PHILOSOPHY
logical Ordinary phenome existe herm structur deconstru Neo Neo
Language nology ntiali eneut alism ctivism Thom Marxi
sm ics ism sm
FØllesdal’s ‘genetic affiliation thesis’ used the terms argument and
‘justification’ in a broader sense. The term ‘argument’ does not mean just
deductive argument, but something more than that. The types of argument we
find in philosophy and other areas, according to F Øllesdal are usually variants
of non-monotonic (not logical enough as per canons) arguments, that is, the
type of arguments in which adding new premises may cast doubt on a
conclusion that would follow without these premises.
Regarding the term ‘justification’, FØllesdal says that philosophy also
has to alternate between general connection and details. The details provided
by the theory of general connection must be proper and it must find a place in
a more general theory. It is through this kind of ‘reflective equilibrium’ that
we arrive at justification of our philosophical insights, of the general insights
as well as of the detailed specific ones, says FØllesdal.
12
According to FØllesdal, it is the particular way of approaching
philosophical problems that make analytic philosophy distinct and this
method cannot even be identified with a specific method of analyzing
philosophical concepts. FØllesdal finds no unity between the three strands of
thinking namely (1) doctrines (2) problems and (3) ways of approaching
them. The way of treating the main currents of philosophy as philosophical
schools, according to FØllesdal is unsatisfactory. On FØllesdal’s view, the
‘genetic affiliation thesis’ (Thesis 5) implies a sub-thesis which can be called
the ‘continuum thesis’, where FØllesdal traces the genealogy of analytic
philosophy.
The ‘genetic affiliation thesis’, begins with argumentators opinion on
the origin of analytic philosophy. It has often been considered that the logical
branch of analytic philosophy begins with Frege and Russell and the ordinary
language branch with G.E. Moore. Likewise in connection with the
publication of Russell’s ‘Principles of Mathematics’ and Moore’s ‘Refutation
of Idealism’, the year 1903 is taken as the year of birth of analytic philosophy.
But 20 years earlier than this, Frege was engaged in analytic philosophy in
that sense, the date of birth of analytic philosophy is shifted back to 1879, the
year in which Beggriffschrift was published. But history tells us that even
before Frege, Bolzano anticipated many of the ideas of Frege, Carnap, Tarski,
Quine and others. The ‘continuum thesis’, therefore, supports that Bolzano
13
as the ‘Great grandfather of analytic philosophy’ and Frege the great
grandfather.
FØllesdal raises similar argument in the case of Von Wright’s finding
incompatibility between hermeneutics and analytic philosophy. The former
Von Wright claims, emphasizes the differences between Social Science and
Humanities and the latter speaks of the differences between naturalism and
Historical/Cultural Sciences. FØllesdal refutes Von Wright’s former claim
stating that not all analytic philosophers speak of unity of Science. Further,
we cannot say that Social Sciences and Humanities conduct experiments of
the kind common to natural sciences. F Øllesdal takes Wolfgang Stegmuller’s
article ‘The So-called Circle of Understanding’, as a best example for his
argument since it deals with analytic approach to hermeneutics and calls it
analytic hermeneutics. The latter claim of Von Wright is refuted by F Øllesdal
taking Dasenbrock’s work ‘Literary Theory After Davidson’, as a model for
his argument. Davidson’s efforts have aroused the interest of literary critics
and now a days literary theorists are looking for philosophical foundations of
literary criticism. FØllesdal’s arguments therefore comes to the conclusion
that the traditional classification of contemporary philosophy as one trend
among others, is misleading since the analytical/non-analytic distinction runs
across other divisions. One can be an analytic philosopher and also a
phenomenologist, existentialist, hermeneuticist, thomist etc. Whether one is
an analytic philosopher depends on what importance one ascribes to argument
14
and justification. FØllesdal expressed the classification in the following
revised way.
Pheno Exist herme structu deconstr Neo- Neo- ethics natur Etc.
meno entia neutics ralism uctivism Tho Mar alism
logy lism Heideggor mism xism
Husserl
MORE
ANAL
YTIC
LESS
ANAL
YTIC
The takehome lesson is that deconstruction cannot be singled out for
privileging the ‘argument’ at the expense of the continental philosophy. That
is, the line of apparent distinction between analytical and post-analytical
tradition cannot provide any strong case against the latter.
1.2 Argument, Arguer, Explication: Tools for Derrida’s ‘Conceptual
Philosophy’
One major evidence for calling ‘analysis’ as ‘argument’ comes from
the important 1999 Ratio conference on Derrida, which was published under
the title ‘Arguing with Derrida’ (2001). The major focus of the volume is to
side-step the hear-say reception of Derrida’s work and to concentrate on the
‘argumentative strategies’ at two levels. One at the level of revisit of Derrida-
Austin debate and the other includes Derrida’s own responses to the ‘Reading
15
Affairs’*. Defining an argument “a sequence of propositions”, Geoffrey
Bennington notes that “it is largely mistaken to suppose that Derrida’s theses
(such as for example, ‘There is nothing outside the text’, ‘Perception does not
exist’, ‘Everything that is, is in deconstruction’, ‘In the beginning was the
telephone’, and so on), are not properly backed up by argument”. It means
only that deconstruction is not allergic to arguments but uses them up to a
point.
The only good argument – for Derrida’s being a philosopher,
being taken to be taken for a philosopher, at any rate, or being
accepted as a philosopher by those who are confident they
really are philosophers would be the presence of arguments – in
his texts.14
He suggests ‘transcription’ as a method, presentation of the relation of
Derrida’s thought to analytical philosophy, not as a relation of critique,
conflict or warfare but non-oppositional and non-conflictual way.
In this context, it would be worthwhile to look at how argument about
the concept of sign goes upto a certain point in ‘Structure Sign and Play’ or
Of Grammatology. It says that ‘sign’ is a metaphysical concept; this
metaphysical concept of ‘sign’ is the concept of its own teleological reduction
or disappearance in the presence of the thing signified; so we can do
something to metaphysics by maintaining (now: en maintenant –
16
deconstruction happens each time now)- by maintaining the sign short of that
reduction or disappearance).
The argument goes in a similar way at the end of ‘The White
Mythology’ regarding the remarks about metaphor. There it occurs, ‘the
concept of metaphor is metaphysical in that it is the concept of metaphor’s
‘death’ or effacement, its ending in the presence of proper meaning; but by
maintaining metaphor short of that telos (i.e. its death as prescribed by
philosophy) may be we provoke the death of philosophy in a quasi-
metaphorical textuality that never quite comes back down to proper meaning
at all (whence ‘dissemination’, which philosophy will never get on top of).
Quoting Derrida’s best known texts, ‘Differance’ and ‘Signature’,
Event, Context’, A.W Moore goes further to present a brief argument to
justify his calling it as conceptual philosophy (a term suggested by Simon
Glendinning).
Thesis 4: Conceptual philosophy is the staple of analytic philosophy.
Conceptual philosophy with a clear purport to argue. That is, if conceptual
philosophy is a staple of analytic philosophy, and deconstruction is a species
of analysis (in the wider sense), then conceptual philosophy is a special case
of analytical philosophy. He wants us to note the following features for his
argument.
1. It is a label – a better one than many others – (‘analytic’ (argument).
17
2. ‘The practice of conceptual philosophy’ is not to be identified with the
practice of science but it can be more narrowly defined in terms of two
features.
a. It is natural to disassociate it from the pursuit of knowledge or
truth, but concepts.
b. It makes claim about reality to demonstrate how these concepts
are put to work.
3. Following the above distinction, conceptual philosophy has a
commitment to the truth (so, it is analogous to science). That is, in
Derrida’s words, analytical philosophy has a commitment to truth.
Here Derrida says, ‘I too have such a commitment to the truth of only
to question the possibility of the truth, to the history of the truth, the
differances in the concept of truth, and not taking for granted the
definition of truth as tied to declarative sentences.15
4. It has some point of contact between conceptual (analytical)
philosophy and the works of Derrida.
5. This is illustrated by Frege’s analysis of the concept of horse as lying
in the following question.
‘Is the ‘concept of horse’ a concept’?
18
Here Moore makes use of Kerry’s analysis according to which the
concept of horse is both an object as well as a concept, thus leading to a
‘paradox’ and Frege denies Kerry’s argument. Frege’s denial led to some sort
of confusion. This is an obvious ‘tangle’: how to justify whether it is a name
(object) or a predicate (concept)?
So Moore concludes that conceptual philosophy fails even in its own
terms. Moore wants to explore the points of contact in the light of the above
citing ineffable as an example (Ineffable = that which cannot be expressed (it
is expressed as ‘ineffable’). This case against conceptual philosophy has
certain clear echoes in Derrida’s remarkable essay ‘Differance’. Likewise,
‘diffe’rance’ = ‘differance is not’. So one can derive many such links
Derrida with Frege and Wittgenstein. The neologism ‘diffe’rance’, which is
the central characteristic of meaning in Derrida, is an echo of Frege. Just as
analytical philosophy can tolerate paradoxes, deconstruction can tolerate
falsehood and nonsense. It is not the same idea, but there is a common
predicament (even in Quine and paradoxes abound) in analytic philosophy.
The French word equivalent of arguing is ‘arguer’. But there is
another word ‘explication’ which carries some of the same connotations as
argument. ‘S’ expliquer arec queiqu’un means ‘to have it out with them’
(combative). But ‘Explication de texte” is also French which stands for
‘close’ (sensitive) reading incidentally, it may be noted that for Carnap’s
19
Explication (explicandum-explicans relation) bears on philosophical queries
in science. Heidegger’s ‘Auseinandersetzung’ is an expression which stands
for both to argue and to explain, as well as ‘a kind of arguing’. What is to be
noted is that the word ‘explication’ contains the combative sense of having an
argument. In one sense, it gives the meaning of what we outlined as one side
of the debate and in the other sense, it explains what somebody else saying –
the other side of the debate. Both meaning are implicit in each other. This is
important in the discussion of deconstruction.
At this point let us turn our attention to Derrida’s text ‘Signature,
Event, Context’ in which Moore explains the Austin – Derrida debate.
Derrida raised the complaint against saying that Austin is over-sanitized, in
his rough and ready distinction between normal/abnormal or parasitic/deviant
expression. This second category suggests that by extension and analogy, we
can clearly separate the contexts in which it is possible to use any given word
with its (standard) meaning from those in which it is not. Quite contrary to
this, Derrida adopted a much more fluid method to explain the relationship
between how words are used and how they mean what they do. For Derrida,
meaning is its infinite potential for iterability in new contexts to new effects,
for new purposes, in playing new games. Derrida says that
‘every sign …….. can be cited, put between quotation marks;
thereby it can break with every given context, and engender
20
infinitely new contexts in an absolutely nonsaturable
fashion……… This citationality, duplication, or duplicity, this
iterability of the mark is not an accident or an anomaly, but is
that (normal/abnormal) without which a mark could no longer
even have a so-called ‘normal’ functioning.’16
According to this, may be
1. ‘a’ is the correct usage (primary)
2. ‘a’ is the deviant usage (secondary: The Indian Dhvani is an echo of
this).
In the above, 1 and 2 (even with quotation) may roughly correspond to ‘use-
mention’ distinction of Carnap. The secondary (incidentally, if may be noted
that for Carnap, explication is defined as follows: explicandum = df.
explicans) may be non-serious in Austin’s sense; it may not have ‘uptake’.
Still one can claim that conceptual philosophy can eschew deviant expression.
Moore’s overall conclusion is that, ‘there is a curious and unexpected
convergence of Derrida’s style of philosophy with what he has been calling
conceptual philosophy.17
Derrida’s response is positive. He is doing ‘conceptual philosophy’ in
Moore’s sense. But Derrida terms it as ‘massive’ or ‘huge’ issue what is
conveyed by the quote:
21
‘Although I am professionally a philosopher, everything I do is
something else than philosophy. No doubt it is about
philosophy, but it is not simply ‘philosophical’ ‘through and
through’.18
Derrida concludes by saying,
‘I am an analytical philosopher – a conceptual philosopher’,
‘my ‘style’ has something essential to do with a motivation that
one also finds in analytic philosophy, in conceptual
philosophy’.19
In this context, I take Simon Glendinning’s ‘Inheriting ‘Philosophy’:
The case of Austin and Derrida Revisited.’ In what follows, I shall try to
capture the Austin-Derrida debate conceding that the general distinction
between analytical and continental philosophy is both ‘vague’ (since it lacks
accepts standards of clarity and rigour’) and overdetermined (since the
supposition of division is not an impartial one).
Glendinning proceeds to point out the nature of the debate saying that
it describes Derrida’s controversial reading of J.L Austin’s theory of
performative utterances as symptomatic of the above schism between
continental and analytical philosophy. Why ‘deconstruction’ and ‘ordinary
language philosophy’ congenial for a discussion is that Bennington finds that
its basic themes suggest that the idea of a distinction between analytical and
22
continental philosophy ‘clouds’ rather than clarifies what is at stake in the
‘ways of going on. Hence it does not go to any minimal extent to clarify the
two different ways of going on while being-an-heir to ‘philosophy’. 20 His
discussion on the ‘tidy-looking dichotomy’ falls into three parts such as (1)
there are parallels between Derrida’s and Austin’s criticism of a style of
thinking which they are willing to call simply ‘philosophy’. (2) Austin’s is
open to critics in the way he criticizes philosophy. Austin’s deployment of the
word Gleichschaltung (means ‘community’, ‘brings some money to line’,
‘inform to a certain standard by force’- originally used by Hitler as a
watchword for ‘integration’; Austin used it in the sense of abandonment of
philosophy’s deeply ingrained worship of tidy-looking dichotomies, for e.g,
between ‘constantive’ and ‘performative’ utterances). (3) It gives an approach
to contemporary philosophy.
The first point to be noted in this context is that, for Austin as for
Derrida, ‘the tidy-looking dichotomy’ is a ‘distorting idealization of our
language that is ‘philosophy’. We abandon it but to relocate the distinction in
inherit/dis-inherit at its most active form.
Searle in his ‘Reply to Derrida’, used the word ‘Reiterating’ (the
Differences) (Searle 1977) to which Derrida remarked: ‘the only sentence to
which I subscribe’ (meaning that I to reiterate the differences). Derrida
rejected the hypotheses of confrontation ‘not only’ because he considers his
23
own work to be importantly similar to Austin’s.21 Glendinning states that
Searle finds the necessity of a confrontation under the impression that Derrida
misunderstood and misstated Austin’s position, but such a confrontation never
takesplace since Derrida and Austin are close to each other. Derrida states
that
Among the many reasons that make me unqualified to represent
a ‘prominent philosophical tradition’, there is this one: I
consider myself to in may respects quite close to Austin, both
interested in and indebted to his problematic. This is said in
Sec, very clearly (Derrida, 1988, p.38). 22
Thus Derrida’s engagement with Austin mainly focuses on the attempt
to undermine a conception of ‘the meaning and utterances’. When Austin
considers meaning ideally be definite and exact, for Derrida, this is a
prejudice or injustice among others in philosophy. Derrida states that no
philosophy has renounced the Aristotlean ideal of ‘univocity of essence or the
telos of language’. This ideal is philosophy. It thus becomes the target of
Derrida’s attack. It is aimed at what is intrinsic to ‘philosophy’ as such.
Although Derrida’s mode of being an-heir to ‘philosophy’ this attempt ‘about
philosophy ……….. it is not simply “philosophical” through and through’.23
The two central developments of philosophical conceptions are (1) the
restriction of utterance to ‘meaning’ to the truth-evaluable content and (2) the
24
invariant nature of meaning in different contexts. It is against the second of
these assumptions Derrida, defends what is best seen as a radical form of
contextualism which is open to non-deviant readings. Derrida states that
‘intentional meaning’ allows ‘no dessimination escaping the horizon of the
unity of meaning’ (Derrida 1998. p.14). It is a logical incoherence to suppose
that there could be marks or signs (inner or outer) which might have this
properly. Further we cannot make sense of some “event” without taking into
account the other ‘events’ included in it. Here Derrida is not simply
advancing a claim about the (factual) repetability or multiple applicability of
words and signs in different contexts but a claim about the ‘eventhood’ of
24
such events’. The functioning of a word, in this context is associated with
its ‘iterability’, a quasi-technical term used by Derrida to capture this ‘logic
that ties repetition to alterity’. It makes the conclusion that epistemic intuition
are unacceptably dogmatic. Further ‘performative communication becomes
once more the communication of an intentional meaning in which there ‘no
dissemination escaping the horizon of the unity of meaning’. 25 However
according to Norris, despite the ritual show of hostilities (sadly typified by
responses to the Derrida-Searle ‘debate’) there is much to be gained from an
ecumenical approach that seeks out genuine points of content while avoiding
any kind of reductive or premature synthesis.’ 26 Then the debate is not
without any substance to which Norris agrees (especially in his remarks of the
later edition of the book ‘Theory and Practice’).
25
1.3 The Rigours of Analysis
The twentieth century has witnessed a ‘linguistic turn’ in philosophy
were philosophy itself has come to be defined as:
Philosophy = df. as analysis of the underlying (deep) structures of
language (subject-predicate form of propositions) with reference to their
ontological import (subject stands for a named object, predicate stands for a
property) and the evaluation of truth or falsity of the class of propositions
(truth-telling discourse).
The revolution started with Frege. Giving reverence to Kant, Frege,
tried to provide a rigorous logical foundation – an ‘old Euclidean standards of
rigour’ for the proofs of arithmetic.# The purpose of Frege was to replace the
‘psychological’ with the logical, the subjective with the objective and the
rejection of meaning of a word in isolation to the context of a proposition.
The first major work of Frege, in ‘Concept Script’ was the ‘turning
point’ in which he devised a system of logic that marks the beginning of this
discipline in its modern form. It includes the notions of ‘assertible content’,
‘negation’, ‘conditional proposition’, ‘the universal quantifier’ and ‘identity’.
Frege also pointed out the analogy between the mathematical notion of a
function and the logical notion of a concept. Thus his function-theoretic logic
#
Famous works of Frege are “Concept Script” (Beggriffschrift), The Foundations of
Arithmetic (Die Grundlagen der Arithmetic), The Basic Laws of Arithmetik (Die
Grundgesetze der Arithmetic), and papers such as ‘Concept and Object’, ‘Function
and Concept’ and ‘Sense and Reference’
26
was supposed perform as an explanation of number-theoretic account of
logicism. It also explains how this analogy could help clarify what in the
older logic was called the predicate of a proposition. Further, Frege pointed
out the importance of the use of the notion of quantifiers and the variables
they bind, in order to thereby express the concept of generality.
Frege applied the programme developed in the concept script to the
most fundamental of mathematical theories, especially to the theory of
numbers in his Foundations of Arithematik. In this work, Frege, thus poised
between two discursive possibilities, one internal to the mathematics and the
other to analysis proving the basic laws of arithmetic from purely logical
principles. In order to overcome some of the shortcomings in The
Foundations, Frege, published a series of articles in which his distinction
between ‘sense and reference’ occurs.
In his Basic Laws of Arithmetic, the programme sketched in The
Foundations, was carried out with proofs set out as derivations within a
formal system (axiomatics). This system also embodies theory of classes for
which a contradiction was discovered by Russell. This is known as Russell’s
Paradox. This is the sample of rigour in analysis.
Frege has carried out his investigations into the nature of meaning.
Further, Frege treated concepts as special types of objective entities and
concept words, as special linguistic expressions that refer to these concepts. It
27
is with these concept words that a logician has to work out just as he do with
other types of linguistic expressions. Frege therefore, can be called a realist
who believed in the objective existence of concepts, relations and objects.
The objects in the world, in the Fregean view, are entities designated by
special types of linguistic expressions.
Frege’s notion of philosophical analysis:
Definition : assertibility = logic plus content (semantics) given
in terms of the theory of sense.
The above definition requires an equivocation like the following:
true = known to be true.
Frege also finds an indissoluble link between thought and meaning and
introduced the distinctions between ‘sense (Sinn) and reference (Bedeutung)’.
Unlike Saussure, he claims that the relationship of reference to the referent is
not arbitrary, but there is a notion of sense in which the sign belong. This
does not mean that reference and sense of a sign form the idea, instead, he
points out that reference and sense have to be distinguished from the idea.
Frege stated this by declaring p=q is logically true, if p and q have the same
sense, but empirically true, if they have only the same reference. Further for
Frege, all expressions in a well constructed language have sense. Ideally each
expression would have a single, uniform sense, shared and understood by all
28
competent users of language. It is on the basis of the sense of the expression
that one can specify the conditions for the truth or falsity of the sentence as a
whole.27 In short, according to Frege, the sense is that part of the meaning of
an expression which is relevant to the determination of the truth-value of a
sentence in which the expression occur. To know the sense of a proper name
is to know the criterion for identifying any given object as the meaning of that
name; to know the sense of a predicate is to know the criterion for deciding
whether it is true of an arbitrary object. ‘The distinction between sense and
reference thus brought the following changes in the analysis of the term
‘meaning’ itself. Accordingly, meaning is (1) the personal, subjective (and
therefore variable) associations, images, or ideas an expression calls up in
some mind; (2) the sense of the expression and (3) the referent of the
expression. Out of these three options, Frege rejects the relevance of
subjective associations, at the same time gives importance to (2) and (3) since
they are relevant for logic and a scientific use of language’.28
According to this Fregean semantics, some senses must be presented in
themselves, directly apprehended in their own nature. Although senses look
like signs in determining objects, they are different from ordinary signs in the
sense that there is no possibility of misinterpreting them. A sense, thus
becomes a sign that forces us to take it in exactly one way. It can be said that
Fregrean theory of meaning therefore, needs a kind of direct and unmediated
presence of sense. This Fregean semantics in many ways resembles Husserl
29
especially when Husserl deals with the nature of prepositional contents, our
access to them, and their acts of language production. According to Wheeler
both Frege and Husserl are antireductions. Both take the defense of
mathematical and logical consequence against psychologism to be of central
concern.’29 The ‘presence’ model common to Frege and Husserl, and shared
by many theories later are largely antimetaphysical. In that sense, Frege and
Husserl bespeak of a sort of interface with continental philosophy.
Russell’s notion of philosophical analysis involves logic-ontology
interface given as:
logic <=> ontology.
His metaphysical school of logical atomism is defined as follows:
Logical atomism = metaphysics based upon the logical analysis
of language.
Russell’s two major contributions to philosophical analysis are (a) Theory of
Definite Descriptions and (b) Theory of Types. The Theory of Types is
formulated as a solution to the ‘Russell’s Paradox’ found in Frege’s
philosophy of mathematics. His theory of definite descriptions is acclaimed
as the paradigm of philosophical analysis (Ramsey, Ayer).
30
Russell’s philosophy of logical atomism makes explicit the principle
on which the metaphysical interpretation of logical constructionism depends.
Russell’s analysis aims to show:
Logical forms of proposition ‘correspond to’ worldly form of facts
The ideal language is essential to reflect the real structure of the world.
Russell formulated a basic “Principle of Acquaintance” as the important
requirement of an ideal language. As its name indicates, this principle enjoins
that the “atomic” sentences get their meaning through direct correlations with
experience. They therefore, become the names of particular sense-data and
terms of properties of sense-data and relations between sense data. Logical
atomism can therefore be explained as the thesis that all knowledge can be
stated in terms of atomic sentences and their truth – functional components.
Russell distinguished proper names from definite descriptions. The
existence of a proper name, according to Russell, is connected with the object
it represents but there are definite descriptions that have no denotation and
hence have no meaning. Such descriptions, according to Russell, do not
function as names. On analysis, they will disappear as putatively denoting
phrases that need re-writing. ‘To put it briefly and more or less neutrally,
logical atomism is a method analyzing definite descriptions, also called
singular descriptions’, i.e. phrases in English typically beginning with the
word “the”.30 In opposition to definite description, there is indefinite
31
description which does not designate a particular object and carries the words
such as “a” or “any”. This is the standard analysis on which one brings out
the underlying logical (deep) structure of subject-predicate propositions.
Calling definite descriptions as incomplete symbols, Russell argued
that ‘it is a symbol which is not supposed in have any meaning in isolation but
is only defined in certain contexts. The idea of incomplete symbol made a
revolutionary change in Russell’s thought. In the light of this, the primary
task of philosophy therefore becomes to keep away from the misleading
surface structure of language to the underlying deep structure or from he
grammatical form to the logical form’. The shift of attention towards
language – towards actual words spoken or written – was to be of the greatest
importance both for Russell’s own thought and for that of philosophers who
came after him.31
Wittgenstein made two revolutions in philosophy. One is his famous
work on the Tractatus and the second is the Philosophical Investigations.
Critics identifying the difference constituting an opposition between early
‘realism’ and later ‘anti-realism’ gives meaning a truth-functional form.
Accordingly,
Realism: Meaning = definition: truth-conditions (True or false is
determined by the way they are distributed over propositions)
This gave a truth-conditional theory of meaning.
32
In contrast, in anti-realism:
Meaning = definition: verification or justification condition.
This gave a justification condition theory of meaning (meaning
depends on cognitive procedure). Wittgenstein’s earlier notion of
philosophical analysis is given by truth-tabular conception of logical truths
(‘every proposition is a truth-function of elementary propositions’).
Sometimes the early theory of meaning is called the ‘Chess’ Theory of
Meaning (every move in language is governed by rules), whereas the later
theory is called ‘Mosaic’ theory where contexts are included in meaning.
Inspite of the above contrast or move poignantly put, the rivalry, there is a
deep continuity between early and later philosophy which is what we need to
exploit in this dissertation.
Wittgenstein’s Tractatus owes much to Frege and Russell. It is a
comprehensive work of extreme originality in which Wittgenstein explains
the limits of language and limits of thought. The chief motif behind this work
is to explain the nature of logical necessity that Russell had left unexplained
in Principia Mathematica. The marginal status of theories in his early
philosophy did not deflect this theory from its main goal, which was to show
that logically necessary propositions are a kind of by-product of the ordinary
use of propositions to statefacts.32 In the preface to the Tractatus,
Wittgenstein said, ‘the book deals with the problems of philosophy, and I
33
believe, that the reason why these problems are posed is that of the logic of
our language is misunderstood.33
In order to clear this misunderstanding, Wittgenstein therefore,
proposes the strategy of critique of language and thus explains the limits of
what can be said. What cannot be said lies outside the frontiers of thinkable
and they are non-sensical and cannot enquire by means of logic. On the
enquiry of it Wittgenstein introduces two concepts such as “picture” and
“truth-function.” According to the picture theory, a proposition is a picture of
reality in which the elements of proposition and of the world are structurally
related to one another. This picture may be either true or false.
The picture theory also gives an account of the nature of thought.
According to it ‘a thought is a sentence with a sense’ (Tractatus 4). Here the
relevance of language in the formation of sentences becomes explicit. The
totality of true thoughts thus give the true picture of the world.
Propositions describe the states of affairs and are composed of
expressions. Apart from the logical expressions, all expressions are either
analysable or unanalysable simple names. Simple names stands for the
objects in reality which in turn are their meanings. It is these simple names
that link language to reality, pinning the network of language to the world.
The elementary proposition is a concatenation of names in accordance with
the logical syntax, which does not name anything, but says that things are thus
34
and so. It represents the existence of a possible states of affairs that is
isomorphic to it, given the method of projection. Further, the logical syntax
of any possible language mirrors the metaphysical structure of the world.
The logical analysis of the structure of language distinguishes two
different possibilities of truth-conditions, as two extreme cases. “ In one of
these cases, the proposition is true of for all the truth possibilities of the
elementary propositions. We may that the truth-conditions are tautological.
In the second case, the proposition is false for all the truth possibilities: the
truth-conditions are contradictory. In the first case we call the proposition is
tautology; in the second a contradiction” (Tractatus, 4. 46).
Thus the tautology and contradictions are the two limits of language.
Only propositions show what they say. Tautologies and contradictions
‘show’ that they say nothing. Therefore neither tautology nor contradiction is
a true proposition. They lack meaning, as they are not pictures. However,
tautologies and contradictions are not nonsensical. They are part of the
symbolism as ‘0’ is part of the symbolism of arithmetic. Wittgenstein’s
distinction between ‘sense’ and ‘senseless’ as lying within the chosen
symbolism (truth-functional logic) and outside of it, later gave rise to
‘meaningfulness’ and ‘meaninglessness’ in Carnap. This overlaps Derrida in
a sense. We seek the post-analytical engagements in the following section.
35
1.4. The Post-analytical Engagements
There is controversy over whether there is continuity between the early
work of Wittgenstein (the Tractatus phase) to that of his later work, (the
Philosophical Investigations) or whether there is radical break. According to
MacDonough, there is a sustained theme that runs throughout Wittgenstein’s
writings – namely Philosophical Investigations, 352, 356, On Certainity: 199,
200 and Part IV of the Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. This
theme is mainly concerned with the question of whether there is some ‘queer
argument’ (P1 352) or relationship which connects the tautologies to a set of
ontological or linguistic views. However, the context of allusions to this
argument in the later writings get altered from that of the Tractatus. The
difference is that in the later writings, Wittgenstein’s attitude to the argument
seems to have become critical. Wittgenstein’s rigour is rather legendary; but
the dismantling of his ‘extreme version’ of logical atomism brick by brick by
later work is strongly suggestive of deconstructive motif.
This extraordinarily simple and yet audacious, even revolutionary
move, Staten says, parallel to that of Derrida when he replaces the
phenomenology “voice” (silent, internal) with the concept of “writing”. This
becomes the focus of attention later in the thesis.
‘The Philosophical Investigations’ begins as an enquiry into
“meaning”. This enquiry leads to the intertwined concepts of
36
“understanding”, “thinking”, “grasping a rule”, “being guided”, “giving
orders”, “teaching and learning”, and so on. It not only rejects the subtle
medium of mind but also does not demarcate between words as a more nearly
spiritual medium and gestures, pictures and inarticulate sounds as sub
linguistic. Instead, the scene of language is unfolded as a rebus with an
indefinite potential for an indefinite kind of signifying sequences. 34 As
Wittgenstein said ‘it could be seen in the right light only by contrast with and
against the background of his old way of thinking.’
If this ‘old way of thinking’ was an intellectual exercise in the logical
versus rhetorical dichotomy, in the Philosophical Investigations, there is an
end to this practice, or it is, to quote Wittgenstein’s verbal mystification, ‘a
battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language.’
Wittgenstein paid little attention to the history of philosophy. The only
reference text he wanted for the Philosophical Investigations, his own great
deconstructive work was his own earlier work, the Tractatus Logico-
Philosophicus. It makes Staten to say that ‘by bringing Wittgenstein into
relation with Derrida, we can overcome the historical amnesia Wittgenstein
can cause, without betraying the fundamental radicality, of his method.35
In the Philosophical Investigations, the logic of linguistic expressions
constructed in altogether different terms. The analysis of language is made
neither by means of depth-grammar that points to the truth-functions of
37
elementary propositions nor are propositions in their ‘basic’ constituents
made up of names. Language is ordinary language. Language is languages
that is, it consists of and can be conceived as exhibiting many different types
of or combinations of language-games. It is to be explained and understood
as it is found. The meaning of a word is its use. It speaks about the role
‘meaning’ plays in our language.36 It is neither logical nor rhetorical. The
concept of ideal language and thorough-going determinism disappears at this
level. In other words, the logic of truth-conditions in the Tractatus was
changed to the logic of “use-conditions”, and the primary role of philosophy
becomes a “critique of language”, an activity of clarification rather than as a
discipline that asserts various substantive propositions or factual claims about
the world. In Wittgenstein, the notion of language-game serves a number of
functions. Sometimes, it is used as a simplified model of a language, a cool to
be used in the analysts of complex many-sided ordinary language.
Wittgenstein’s later view on the nature of language, thus involves the
dissolution of a number of philosophical concepts like dogmatism,
determinism, essentialism, representationism, universalism, a priorism etc.
According to Christopher Norris, the whole point of Wittgenstein’s appeal to
language games and cultural forms of life is to coax philosophers down from
such forms of self-induced skeptical puzzlement.37
38
Let us start with Quinean notion of philosophical analysis, by
comparing this with his predecessors in a rough and ready way.
1. For Frege, the conceptual notion gets the sanction of science, logic
provides the perfect canon.
2. For Russell, it is the logic ontology interface.
3. For Wittgenstein, it is the isomorphism (one-to-one relation) between
logic and ontology.
4. For Quine, logic itself is ontology. It is the ontic idiom par excellence.
Quine’s major pre-suppositions in philosophy can be classified under
two general headings, such as those having to do with philosophy of language
(logic) and those having to do with ontology. What he has to say on
naturalism (no dividing line between science and philosophy) as marked
affinities with the general orientation of empiricist and pragmatist
philosophers. Two of his papers ‘On What There Is,’ and ‘Two Dogmas of
Empiricism,’ gained him importance in the list of analytical thinkers.
Quine’s paper ‘On What There Is?’ explores a sound ontological base
for his naturalistic account. It is here that Quine sets down his criterion for
ontological commitment by means of which he has attempted to overcome the
hostility to metaphysics. It does not mean that Quine encouraged
metaphysics, instead he would revitalize and rehabilitate metaphysics as
ontology. This has been done by reconstructing the formation of the
39
questions with which ontology deals with in accordance with the guiding
principles of modern logic with precision and clarity. In addition to this,
Quine also makes use of the general power of predicate calculus in which lies
the use of the method of quantification. It is enough for Quine for purposes of
classifying one’s ontological commitments to make use of first-order
quanitifcation where the quantified variables range over one or more types of
individual objects. In short, Quine’s statement “to be is to be the value of a
variable”, sums up the essence of the criterion of ontological commitment.
Quinean pattern of argument in the ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’,
undermines the traditional analytic/synthetic distinction. Traditionally a
statement is analytic, if it can be reducible to a form governed by the logical
law of identity. Likewise, a statement is synthetic if it cannot be reducible to
a statement that is basically of the form of an identity. The main drawback in
all these kinds of approach, according to Quine, is the lack of holistic
approach. He believes that in determining the truth, and our knowledge of the
truth, we should consider not on individual sentence taken singly and apart
from its inter-relations with other statements in total network of beliefs.
Taskian disquotational theory and Davidson’s Principle of Charity are direct
descendants of this holism or ‘narrative turn’ as described by Richard Rorty.
According to Christopher Norris, Quine examines the essentialism found in
the logical empiricist distinction between analytic and synthetic statements (or
‘truths of reason’ or ‘truths of act’) and then goes on to argue in holistic
40
fashion that ‘our statements about the external world face the tribunal sense –
experience not individually but only as a corporate body.’ 38
Much more than Quine’s indeterminacy of radical translation,
Davidson’s doctrine of radical interpretation has an edge in that it is as much
an acknowledged model for literary criticism as deconstruction is in the ‘wild’
version. Starting from his contribution towards the semantics (meaning-
theory) for natural language, whatever realistic consideration that underlie it
by virtue of its affiliation to Tarski’s semantic conception of truth, it reaches a
paradoxical conclusively approximating interpretation with the way we use
language. Davidson concludes with a paradoxical remarks that ‘there is no
such a thing as language’. Davidson’s starting point is to bring a cohesion
between two radically different languages, but ends up with some sort of
indeterminacy.
Davidsonian theory of meaning thus states that meaning must to
language – like. Meaning is fundamentally linguistic, and not something
behind or expressed in language. In place of the term ‘means that’, Davidson
therefore elects the biconditional – ‘if and only if’ – as the connective needed
in a theory of meaning. Davidson’s theory of meaning accordingly associated
with the inter-related phenomena of belief, desire, intention and other mental
states which themselves form an autonomy of family of concepts. In that
sense, meaning is a conceptual content with wide and varied application. In
41
addition to the conceptual content, meaning also has other “senses” which
will cause into being only on interpretation. “Being subject to interpretation”
means that nothing intrinsic to the term determines that it must refer to a
given object, instead every mark is subject to interpretation without essence.
To have a meaning according to Davidson is that, to have a place in a
language-game. But such a meaning will not work in the case of metaphor.
Since metaphors do not have a special kind of meaning. It makes us to see
one thing as another by making some literal statement that inspires or prompts
the insight.39 This treatment of metaphor is a direct attack on the reductionist
view of metaphor used by the Platonists and Positivists according to which
metaphors are either paraphrasable or useless for the purpose of representing
reality and is usually literally false but uttered with the aim of bringing
something to the attention of the hearses.
Davidson also held the view that “giving the meaning of a sentence”
was equivalent to stating its truth-conditions. But Davidson considered the
notion of truth absolutely indispensable and primitive in the sense that truth
cannot be reduced to reference or to other notions. According to this theory,
all data for determining meaning and for determining truth-value consist in
what is said and when it is said. Davidson’s indeterminacy therefore becomes
a milder kind and in fact more radical and pure than Quine’s, since he denies
any sub-basement of content that can be separated from the linguistic
framework. Davidson’s abandonment of the division between scheme and
42
content also denies the notion that experience is something organized by
theory or that there are alternative schemes that does not make sense.
Similarly, Dummett who tries to systematize analytic philosophy was
forced to move a rather radically different counter-paradigm called anti-
realism which threatened to swallow all forms of realism. It is not therefore
without justification that Norris apprehends danger to his way of legitimizing
Derridean logic placing it in the camp of anti-realism. Norris’s efforts go in
vain by any simple move which efforts is purported to neutralized the radical
opposition between realism and anti-realism. Norris is not a safe bet against
the odd option. The crisis Derrida has generated will not subserve Norris’s
reading of Derrida.
The post-analytic engagement is not shown to be redundant in the light
of thesis 5. Thus Wheeler finds that Derridean notion of dissemination is
also paralled with Quinean indeterminacy of translation. Quine used the
metaphor, “the myth of the museum”, to point out the common misconception
of language with regard to sign and referent. By the term indeterminacy,
Quine points out the indeterminacy of translation in going from one language
to another. According to Wheeler, ‘a vivid way to express the view common
to Quine and Derrida is to say that all thought can be at most brain-writing or
spirit writing, both of which modes of inscription yield texts with at least the
hermeneutic problems of other texts. There is no meaning or meaning bearer
43
behind language that is not itself a language like phenomenon.’ 40 Similarly,
Norris also finds such a parallelism in Quine and Derrida stating that the
empiricist programme of Quine could scarcely be more remote from Derrida’s
ceaseless undermining of any assured link between sign and referent.
Nevertheless, it is clear that Quine like Derrida, perceives covert metaphysics
at work in traditional ways of conceiving philosophy; also that he shares the
deconstructionist will to demystify language by removing the appeal to, some
ultimate ground of concept or meaning.’41
Pursuing the same line of inquiry, Wheeler also finds so many
parallelisms in Davidson and Derrida. Both have arrived at analogous
positions after rejecting the dogmas of empiricism and phenomenology and
also on the denial of “magic language”. They also agree on fundamental
issues in the philosophy of language as they are committed to some degree of
indeterminacy of interpretation for the same reasons. According to Wheeler,
the Derridean phenomenon of dissemination is akin to the Davidsonian
variety of indeterminacy rather than to the kind of global, total sets of
alternatives that Quine envisions in word and object’. 42 However there is
difference between Davidsonian and Derridean indeterminacy. Derrida states
that truth, if anything must be a match between an utterance and a given, but
it does not speak of such a matching can be made sense of. Davidson not only
denies any such matching between an utterance and given but he also does not
consider whether any such matching is required for truth. Davidson considers
44
truth functions as an analytical interpretative concept rather than as a
metaphysical concept. Wheeler states that ‘the core problem driving the
analysis of both Derrida and Davidson is that allegedly non-Aristotelean and
non-essentialist accounts of the world (e.g., Kantian and “linguistic” ones)
still seem to rest on essentialism about conceptual or linguistic items………
The radical break that both Davidson and Derrida make is to work out the
consequences of denying essentialism and objective necessities across the
board.43
To Sum Up
1. The analytical model subsumes analysis.
2. The post-analytical is brought into the deconstructionist camp.
3. There is not much underlying difference between analytical and post-
analytical.
4. There is not much rivalry between realism and anti-realism.
5. There is no ‘divide’ between analytical and continental philosophy.
6. There may not be much discontinuity between modernity and post-
modernity in view of modernists ‘unfinished project’. Thus the
perspective on Derrida is a very legitimate one to be unfolded in the
coming chapters.
45
1.5 Taking it Forward:
In this context, we recall the four theses and three motifs before
entering into thesis 5.
T1. Deconstruction is a sub-branch of philosophy of analysis.
T2. Deconstruction is a sub-branch of ethics.
T3. Deconstruction is a sub-branch of literary theory (‘wild’).
T4. Conceptual philosophy is the staple of analytic philosophy.
The justification for (1) is derived from the tools of analysis in
conceptual philosophy as envisaged in (4). (3) is not very much favoured and
(2) waits for consideration towards the end of the thesis (‘late’), were we shall
also add thesis (5) and (6).
The three Motifs are reiterated once again.
Motif 1 Wheeler pushes analysis to the deconstructive side but competitive.
Motif 2 Derrida is quite analogous for deconstruction of Wittgenstein (in his
own work).
Motif 3 the way Norris divides analytic/post-analytic/continental altogether is
not correct in the light of ‘genetic affiliation’ thesis and its consequent
‘continuum thesis’. It is no longer possible to defend Norris even on grounds
46
of realism. Thus we tried to situate Derrida within a full-blooded analytical
perspective.
We shall now open continuity to the previous thesis.
Thesis 5: Deconstruction enters into ‘feud’ with speech-act variety of
analytical philosophy (Austin and Searle).
Critics points out that the debate between Austin and Searle on the one
had and Derrida on the other is illusory, because it represents the real talking
past to each other.
What survives the ‘crisis of analytical philosophy is the legacy of
Kripke’s reading of later Wittgenstein which has its focus on rule-following
considerations. This is a focus that adds as a ‘bridge’ both to critical theory
and post-modernism. Such a bridge is not provable within the compass of the
thesis. But its tenability is beyond doubt. And thus we pass on to say: If this
is taken for granted then we have a counsel for next thesis (6).
We have to admit to “a conviction that the present situation in
[analytic] philosophy is one that calls for a revitalization, a renewal, of the
subject” (Putnam, 1992, ix cf. Putnam, 1998). Similarly Jaakko Hintikka has
declared that………… ‘we have to have a new start in, practically in all
branches of philosophical studies including logic, foundations of
mathematics, language theory, epistemology and philosophical
47
methodology.44 This call for a realignment as seen in Kripke’s rule-following
which by and large brings an interface with Derrida, as Austins’. As if to
endorse this Staten argues that the concept of rule does not explain anything
in the Investigations: it is what has to be explained. The word rule is itself
subject to the same conditions for meaningfulness that other words are, and it
too has a vague and shifting family of meanings’. 45 Analysing the survival of
analytic philosophy, Jaakko Hintikka said, ‘……… survival of analytic
philosophy depends on philosophers acknowledgement and utilization of [the
opportunities for constructive philosophy to be found in Wittgenstein later
thought]46. Thus it is proved beyond doubt that Norris’s marginalizing post-
analytic motifs is a disaster. This goes directly against Derrida’s own
suspicion about the hard-and-fast distinction between ordinlary-extraordinary
(formal) language. Derrida says
I am suspicious of the opposition between
ordinary/extraordinary language. What I am trying to do is to
find – and I think this is close to the Wittgenstein that you
presented – the production of the extraordinary within the
ordinary and the way the ordinary is, as you put it ‘vulnerable’
to or not ‘immune’ to what we understood as extraordinary.’47
Thesis 6: The genetic affiliation between the analytical and continental
philosophies is warranted by analytic and post-analytic considerations. It
48
remains now to substantiate the above claims (Thesis 1 – Thesis 6) in the
pages to follow before capping it with a consideration of ‘late’ Derrida, the
philosopher of the public sphere, who comes to proximity with critical theory
of Habermas in sharing a platform against the terrorist attack on the World
Trade Centre.
49
Notes
1. Julian Wolfreys. Literary Theories: A Reader and Guide. Edinburgh
University Press. 1988. p. 283. (LTRG hereafter).
2. Ibid. p. 283.
3. Ibid. p. 283.
4. Jacques Derrida, Points – Interviews, 1974-1994. Stanford University
Press. 1995. p. 212. (Pts. Hereafter).
5. Christopher Norris: Derrida, Fontana, 1989. p.18. (Dda hereafter)
6. Ibid. p. 19.
7. Geoffrey Bennington, Deconstruction is Not What You Think,
Routledge. 1988. p. 7.
8. Barbara Johnson, in the introduction to Derrida’s work
‘Dessimination’, continuum. 2005. p. xv (Dsmn. Hereafter).
9. John. D. Caputo, Deconstruction a Nutshell: A conversation with
Jacques Derrida. 1997. p. 32 (D N hereafter).
10. Dda. p. 27.
11. P.M.S. Hacker, The Rise of the Twenteeth Century Analytic
Philosophy, Ratio (New series) ix 3 December, Blackwell, 1996. p.
258.
12. Ibid. p. 248.
50
13. Dagfinn FØllesdal, Analytic Philosophy: What is it and why should
one engage in it? Ratio (New series) ix 3 December, Blackwell, 1996.
p. 194.
14. Simon Glendenning, Arguing with Derrida, Blackwell 2001, p.37 (A.D
hereafter).
15. Ibid. p. 84.
16. Ibid. p. 66.
17. Ibid. p. 74.
18. Ibid. p. 83.
19. Ibid. p. 83.
20. Ibid. p. 11.
21. Ibid. p. 18.
22. Ibid. p. 18.
23. Ibid. p. 19.
24. Ibid. p. 21.
25. Ibid. p. 23.
26. Christopher Norris, Deconstruction Theory and Practice, Routledge
2003. p.144. (DTP hereafter).
27. Munitz. M., Contemporary Analytical Philosophy, Macmillan 1981. p.
114. (CAP hereafter).
28. Ibid. p. 114.
51
29. Samuel C. Wheeler, Deconstruction as Analytic Philosophy, Stanford
University Press, 2000. p. 16 (DAP hereafter)
30. Nicholas Griffin (ed). The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell,
Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 203.
31. Ibid. p. 224.
32. Nicholas Bunin and E.P Tsui-James. The Blackwell Companion to
Philosophy, Blackwell, p. 128.
33. L.H Holler, Philosophy and the Critique of Language : Wittgenstein
and Mauthener, Blackwell 1998, p. 65.
34. Henry Staten, Wittgenstein and Derrida, Blackwell, 1985, p. 90 (W &
D hereafter).
35. Ibid. p. 3.
36. DAP p. 207.
37. Christopher Norris, Truth About Postmodernism, Blackwell. 1993,
p.219. [TAP hereafter].
38. Christopher Norris, The Deconstructive Turn, Essays in the Rhetoric of
Philosophy, Methuen. 1984. p. 8. (D.T. hereafter).
39. Donald Davidson, Enquiries into Truth and Interpretation O.U.P. 1984.
p. 261.
40. DAP. p. 44.
41. Christopher Norris, Resources of Realism, Macmillan 1998. p.9.
42. DAP. p. 29.
52
43. DAP. p. 23-24.
44. Aaron Preston, Conformism in Analytic Philosophy, The Monist,
April 2005, Vol. 88, No. 2. p. 311.
45. W & D. p. 102.
46. Aaron Preston, Conformism in Analytic Philosophy: On Shaping
Philosophical Boundaries and Prejudices, The Monist. April 2005. Vol.
88, No. 2. p. 311.
47. A D. p.112.
53