Ordinary Language
Ordinary Language
Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary
Journal of Philosophy
Publication details, including instructions for
authors and subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sinq20
To cite this article: Martin Gustafsson (2005): Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples:
Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein, and the Philosophical Significance of Ordinary
Language, Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 48:4, 356-389
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any
representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to
date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should
be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not
be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or
damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in
connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Inquiry,
Vol. 48, No. 4, 356–389, August 2005
MARTIN GUSTAFSSON
Uppsala University, Sweden
ABSTRACT In Cavell (1994), the ability to follow and produce Austinian examples of
ordinary language use is compared with the faculty of perfect pitch. Exploring this
comparison, I clarify a number of central and interrelated aspects of Cavell’s
philosophy: (1) his way of understanding Wittgenstein’s vision of language, and in
particular his claim that this vision is ‘‘terrifying,’’ (2) the import of Wittgenstein’s
vision for Cavell’s conception of the method of ordinary language philosophy, (3)
Cavell’s dissatisfaction with Austin, and in particular his claim that Austin is not clear
about the nature and possible achievements of his own philosophical procedures, and
(4) Cavell’s notion that the temptation of skepticism is perennial and incurable.
Cavell’s reading of Wittgenstein is related to that of John McDowell. Like McDowell,
Cavell takes Wittgenstein to be saying that the traditional attempt to justify our
practices from an external standpoint is misguided, since such detachment involves
losing sight of those conceptual and perceptual capacities in terms of which a practice is
understood by its engaged participants. Unlike McDowell, however, Cavell consistently
rejects the idea that philosophical clearsightedness can or should free us from that fear
of groundlessness which motivates the traditional search for external justification.
It was familiarly said that the point of Austin’s stories, those examples
apart from which ordinary language philosophy has no method, required
what you might call ‘‘ear’’ to comprehend (as in, more or less at random,
setting out the difference between doing something by mistake or by
accident, or between doing something willingly or voluntarily, carelessly
I.
When I was fourteen, I went to a class in elementary music theory where one
of the students had perfect pitch. The teacher would often begin his lessons
by playing a tune on the piano, a tune which we were supposed to write
down in musical notation. On one occasion, someone asked what one
should do if one heard a tune and wanted to write it down, but did not have
access to a tuning-fork or something else by means of which one could
decide the key. The teacher suggested using the telephone: at least in
Sweden, the tone one hears before one starts dialing is a 440 Hz A.
However, after the class, the student who had perfect pitch told me, in all
seriousness, that the telephone should not be trusted: ‘‘Often the tone is not
an A, but almost an A flat. That’s really annoying.’’
I remember finding this remark highly intriguing, but for reasons I could
not make entirely clear to myself at the time. Now, I think I can say that at
least part of my bewilderment had to do with the following insight: having
perfect (or absolute) pitch involves not just the ability to identify the pitch of
a given tone without making use of a tuning-fork or some similar device.
Moreover, if he who has perfect pitch is confident enough in his talent, he
might even pass judgment on particular tuning-forks. After having listened
to the tone it produces, he might claim that a tuning-fork is misconstructed
since the A which it is said to generate is, in fact, too low or too high. For
me, who does not have perfect pitch, delivering this sort of criticism is
impossible. My way of arguing that a particular tuning-fork is wrongly
constructed is, rather, to compare its alleged A to the A produced by other
tuning-forks (and similar such devices). Only if, on such comparison, I
found that the tone generated by the tuning-fork deviated from the
other tones, would I dare to claim that the tuning-fork does not produce a
genuine A.
The nature of my bewilderment over the student’s remark can be further
explored by means of the following thought-experiment. Imagine a world in
which everyone has perfect pitch. In this world, tuning-forks would not have
358 M. Gustafsson
the function they have among us, since people would decide what pitches
tones have simply by listening to them. (That is to say: in this world, there
would be no tuning-forks.) These people always, or very nearly always,
agree in their judgments. When they teach their children to identify pitches,
one thing they do is to produce sample tones, by singing or whistling, and
say things like ‘‘This is a D flat’’, ‘‘This is an F’’, and so on. This sort of
training does, in fact, work; after a while, the children are able to identify
pitches as directly and as competently as their parents. (This is not to say
that such ostensive exercises will be the only training required for the child’s
learning to use names of pitches.)
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Now there is a temptation, at least for someone who lacks perfect pitch,
to argue that such a community’s way of identifying pitches is, as it were,
strangely free-floating. One might be tempted to say that there seems to exist
no solid foundation on which this practice rests. On hearing a tone, these
people spontaneously agree that it is, say, a B. But if we asked them what
reason they have for thinking so, it might happen that all they would say
would be something like: ‘‘We simply hear, directly, that the tone is a B. We
don’t need any further justification. Indeed, any attempt at such further
justification would be superfluous; nothing could lend additional support to
our identification of the pitch. To us, that the tone is a B is already fully
transparent.’’
This sort of answer may appear unsatisfactory. Borrowing a phrase from
John McDowell, one might want to say that all that seems to be going on
here is ‘‘a congruence of subjectivities.’’2 Hearing tones causes beliefs in
these people, beliefs that, luckily enough, concur intersubjectively. To be
sure (one might want to continue), this spontaneous consensus must have a
natural explanation: nature has endowed these people with similar
perceptual apparatuses. But nonetheless, the consensus seems in a certain
sense like mere luck, for what they agree on is not supported by any rational
procedure of justification.
Consider what would happen if these people suddenly started disagreeing
with one another—if the peaceful consensus which has so far characterized
their practice were replaced by widespread discord. Someone says a given
tone is a B; someone else calls it a C; a third listener identifies it as a C sharp;
a fourth listener thinks it is a D; and so on. In this case, there might be
nothing available which could restore the consensus, no agreed-upon
procedures or criteria by means of which the true answer could be identified.
If such disagreement became the rule, the practice would break down.
Indeed, it would then perhaps be too generous to characterize the prevailing
chaos in terms of disagreement, for the breakdown would be so deep-going
that the sort of determinacy of content required by the notion of
disagreement would be threatened. The old words would cease to have a
clear function within that community. It would no longer be clear what it
would mean for these people to ‘‘identify the pitch’’ of a given tone.
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 359
best answer would be something like: ‘‘We simply hear, directly, that the
tones have the same pitch. We don’t need any further justification. Indeed,
any attempt at justification would be superfluous; nothing could lend
additional support to our recognition that the pitch is the same. To us, the
identity of pitches is already fully transparent.’’ At this point, the tone-deaf
person might be tempted to respond that all that is present here is a
congruence of subjectivities: hearing tones causes beliefs in us, beliefs that,
luckily enough, agree intersubjectively. And he might find support for this
analysis in the observation that if we suddenly started disagreeing with one
another about the results we get when we measure pitches by means of
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
II.
I have been discussing what, to my mind, is a rather suggestive instance of a
sort of philosophical puzzlement that plays a central role in the writings of
the later Wittgenstein. I have not been talking about rules, but
Wittgenstein’s so-called ‘‘rule-following considerations’’ are very much
related to the sort of worries I have pondered above. Worries of this sort
also play an important role in Stanley Cavell’s writings, and this is, indeed, a
point at which Cavell is directly influenced by Wittgenstein.
In an often-quoted passage from his early essay, ‘‘The availability of
Wittgenstein’s later philosophy’’, Cavell describes a ‘‘vision’’ he thinks can
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
One who likes to quote this passage is John McDowell. If I read McDowell
correctly, however, he would want to qualify its final sentence. According to
McDowell, the vision Cavell sketches seems terrifying only in so far as it has
not been properly understood. McDowell says, ‘‘[t]he terror of which Cavell
speaks at the end of this marvellous passage is a sort of vertigo, induced by
the thought that there is nothing but shared forms of life to keep us, as it
were, on the rails. We are inclined to think that is an insufficient foundation
for a conviction that when we, say, extend a number series, we really are, at
each stage, doing the same thing as before’’ (MVR, p. 61). But this vertigo,
he continues, is based on a misunderstanding. If we get clear about the sense
in which we are dependent on our shared ‘‘whirl of organism’’, we will
realize that:
what we are doing is illusory. The cure for the vertigo, then, is to
give up the idea that philosophical thought, about the sorts of
practice in question, should be undertaken at some external
standpoint, outside our immersion in our familiar forms of life.
(MVR, p. 63)
(MVR, p. 211).
I cannot here explain all the details of what McDowell takes to be the
‘‘cure’’ for, or the ‘‘protection’’ against, this vertigo. One of McDowell’s
central ideas, however, is that occupying the sort of external, detached
viewpoint from which a given practice might seem to lack a ‘‘solid
foundation’’, involves losing sight of (or being blind to) those thoughts and
perceptions which are made possible by the practice, and in terms of which
the practice is characterized from the inside, by its engaged participants.
According to McDowell, being unsatisfied with the place at which
justification comes to an end within the practice—feeling that justification
should end ‘‘further down’’, at a more ‘‘solid’’ place—means: not having
access to, or perhaps having denied oneself access to, those conceptual and
perceptual capacities in terms of which the practice is understood by those
who are ‘‘normally immersed’’ in it (MVR, p. 211). This means that a
question can sensibly be raised about the significance of this sort of
disappointment with a practice. For if this disappointment is based on a
description of the practice which is alien to the practice itself—in particular,
if the description is not faithful to those conceptual and perceptual
capacities in the light of which the procedures of justification which are
immanent to the practice will seem perfectly sufficient—then there is reason
to ask why this sort of disappointment is anything to worry about at all.
My earlier discussion of perfect pitch, normal pitch, and tone-deafness
provides an instructive illustration of McDowell’s point. Our dissatisfaction
with the way pitches were identified by the inhabitants of the world where
everyone has perfect pitch had to do with our construing the ability to hear
directly that this is an A in terms of the ability to say, directly, ‘‘This is an
A’’, on occasions where everyone else in the community would say the same
thing. Precisely because we lack perfect pitch, we have problems recognizing
any substantial difference between these two abilities. This might be said to
mark the limited extent to which someone who lacks perfect pitch can
understand what it means to have perfect pitch. One might say that not
having perfect pitch means lacking the perceptual and conceptual capacities
required in order to understand clearly how hearing directly that this is an A
can be a matter of perceiving how things are, rather than just a matter of
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 363
being caused, by some natural event, to believe something that one’s peers
also believe. In this sense, perfect pitch is indeed an enigma to he who does
not have it. This is not to say, à la Nagel, that someone who lacks perfect
pitch does not know ‘‘what it is like’’ to have perfect pitch. The relevant
difference is not one between subjective qualities, in Nagel’s sense. Rather,
the point is epistemological: he who lacks perfect pitch is unable to situate
perceptions of the relevant sort within the logical space of reasons (rather
than within the space of causes). He has difficulties conceiving perceptions
that do not involve the measuring of a given tone against a reference tone as
genuine justifications of the claim that this is an A. And similarly for the
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
wish, to escape […] those shared forms of life, to give up the responsibility of
their maintenance’’, adding, famously, that ‘‘[n]othing is more human than
the wish to deny one’s humanity.’’4
Admittedly, there are passages in which McDowell suggests that
philosophical peace of mind might be no more than a practically
unattainable ideal. ‘‘Interesting philosophical afflictions’’, he says, ‘‘are
deep-seated. Even after temporarily successful therapy, they re-emerge,
perhaps perennially, in new forms. If the risk of re-emergence is perennial,
peace is always beyond the horizon.’’5 Cavell, however, questions the idea
that such peace of mind makes sense, even as an ideal. While McDowell
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
III.
I now turn to the analogy Cavell makes in the passage quoted at the
beginning of this paper: between being able to practice with understanding
the method of ordinary language philosophy and having perfect pitch. Let
me start by saying that when I first read this passage I found the analogy
striking but also very puzzling. I could not make clear to myself what the
alleged similarities between these two abilities were supposed to be, and
nonetheless I felt sure that such similarities existed. A few pages after the
quoted passage Cavell again mentions perfect pitch, in a discussion of the
relation between philosophy and autobiography. ‘‘If’’, he says, ‘‘philosophy
is for me finding a language in which I understand philosophy to be
inherited, which means telling my autobiography in such a way as to find
the conditions of that language, then I ought even by now to be able to
begin formulating some of those conditions.’’ He then goes on to give a list
of linked conditions, among which he includes ‘‘a version of perfect pitch’’
(PoP, pp. 38–9). Eight pages later, he says of these conditions that ‘‘the
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 365
feature of perfect pitch is apt to be the hardest to recognize, and the most
variously or privately ratified.’’ And then:
This is not easy to comprehend, and I do not claim to have anything like a
complete understanding of what Cavell is trying to say here. But I do find
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
his talk about perfect pitch as the title of the experience that one is taking
steps, walking on, on one’s own, illuminating. The best way for me to
explain what kind of elucidation I find here, is by relating the passage I just
quoted to the significance of the fact that the remarks of ordinary language
philosophers are, typically, in the first person plural: ‘‘We say …’’, ‘‘We
don’t say …’’, ‘‘When we say … we imply …’’, and so on. According to
Cavell, this feature is a central clue to the nature of such remarks. (See, for
example, MWM, p. 14.) He argues that the use of the first person plural
shows that such remarks combine two aspirations that, at first, might seem
difficult to reconcile. On the one hand, such remarks are not statements of
empirical science: they are not based on polls, statistical studies of linguistic
behavior, or other such evidence. One might say that this constitutes their
first-person aspect. On the other hand, in making remarks of this form, the
ordinary language philosopher does claim to speak for others. This is
crucial, since ‘‘the primary fact of natural language is that it is something
spoken, spoken together’’ (MWM, p. 33). According to Cavell, if the
philosopher claimed to speak only for himself, as someone completely
detached from the linguistic community of which he is a member, he would
be speaking for no one—not even himself. Language, as we know it, is
something we share.
Some philosophers have felt that the first-person aspect and the plural
aspect of such statements are straightforwardly incompatible. They have
argued that if you claim to say something about how language is used by a
community, the only way to justify those claims is to make empirical, socio-
linguistic observations. According to Cavell, this argument ignores that the
relevant statements about ordinary language are made by native speakers of
that language, speakers who,
do not, in general, need evidence for what is said in the language; they
are the source of such evidence. It is from them that the descriptive
linguist takes the corpus of utterances on the basis of which he will
construct a grammar of that language. To answer some kinds of
specific questions, we will have to […] count noses; but in general, to
tell what is and isn’t English, and to tell whether what is said is
366 M. Gustafsson
properly used, the native speaker can rely on his own nose; if not, there
would be nothing to count. (MWM, p. 4)
It is easy to misunderstand the idea expressed here. Cavell’s point is not that
the native speaker has some sort of intuitive and infallible insight into the
linguistic dispositions of his fellow speakers. On the contrary, Cavell freely
admits that the speaker’s claims about what ‘‘we’’ say might be mistaken,
and that the speaker’s peers might disagree with them. The point is, rather,
that if such disagreement arises, what happens is quite different from, and in
an important sense much more troubling than, when a socio-linguistic
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Now where does perfect pitch, as the title of the experience that one is
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
walking on, on one’s own, come in here? Well, in something like the
following way: having perfect pitch involves a peculiar mixture of self-
reliance and vulnerability. He who has perfect pitch trusts his own
perceptual capacity. His having perfect pitch means that he cares little
about consulting tuning forks. Nor does he ask others for their opinion—
after all, that this is an A is not settled by polls. However, if people started
disagreeing with him about the pitches of tones, that would be troubling. It
might be a sign that he is no longer part of that special community of people
who have perfect pitch (his talent may be gone.) Or, it might mean an even
more profound disintegration of his, or his fellow-speakers’, sanity. This
situation is analogous to the case described in the following remark by
Wittgenstein:
In a rather (but, as we shall see, not altogether) similar sort of way, the
ordinary language philosopher must dare to rely on his own sense of how we
speak. His remarks can be neither confirmed nor falsified by polls. Nor is a
dictionary, or some other officially sanctioned collection of linguistic rules,
of much help. For his investigation takes place at a level where such
officially sanctioned rules do not function as normative standards in the
relevant sense of the word (this point will be further clarified below). It
might turn out that his peers do not want to agree with what he says they
should say. But this lack of agreement does not, by itself, constitute a
falsification of his remarks. Rather, it might make unclear the extent to
which these people are his peers; or, it might be a sign that it is unclear to
him what is involved in his being part of the community in question. If
disagreement becomes prevalent and persistent enough, he might even doubt
his own sanity.
368 M. Gustafsson
You have a donkey, so have I, and they graze in the same field. The
day comes when I conceive a dislike for mine. I go to shoot it, draw a
bead on it, fire: the brute falls in its tracks. I inspect the victim, and
find to my horror that it is your donkey. I appear on your doorstep
with the remains and say—what? ‘‘I say, old sport, I’m awfully sorry,
&c., I’ve shot your donkey by accident’’? Or ‘‘by mistake’’? Then again,
I go to shoot my donkey as before, draw a bead on it, fire—but as I do
so, the beasts move, and to my horror yours falls. Again the scene on
the doorstep—what do I say? ‘‘By mistake’’? Or ‘‘by accident’’?7
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Even if Austin here speaks in the first person singular, his intent is in
the relevant sense plural: his example is designed to remind us of how we
speak. And he succeeds, brilliantly. We all agree that in the first scenario
the donkey was shot by mistake, whereas in the second scenario it was
shot by accident. But what if people did not agree with this? What if
they said the opposite: no no, the first donkey was shot by accident and
the second by mistake? Well, supposing that they are serious, their
disagreement would be utterly weird—much more so than the falsification
of a socio-linguistic hypothesis. For you (who, I suppose, agree with Austin)
would not understand to what their disagreement amounted. It could not
just be a local rupture, for you would then also want to know what places
these people assign to a host of other concepts, such as ‘‘intention’’,
‘‘responsibility’’, ‘‘blame’’, ‘‘excuse’’, and so on and so forth. Of course it
might happen that such an inquiry makes them change their minds about
Austin’s story, and admit that the first donkey was shot by mistake and
the second by accident. If so, there is perhaps not much to worry about. But
it might also turn out that those people want to place the relevant concepts
in a pattern that is foreign to you, or that you do not succeed in
understanding these people at all. In either case, the result is more or less
radical estrangement: these people may become enigmas to you (Cf. MWM,
p. 67).
IV.
In the previous section I said something brief about the level at which the
investigations of the ordinary language philosopher take place. I said this
had to do with what I take Cavell to mean when he talks about perfect pitch
in terms of ‘‘walking on on one’s own.’’ Let me try to clarify what I meant
by reflecting on a passage from a paper by Stephen Mulhall. In his reply to
Steven Affeldt’s criticism8 of his book Stanley Cavell: Philosophy’s
Recounting of the Ordinary, Mulhall discusses Cavell’s notions of grammar
and criteria, and he argues that there is a perfectly good sense in which
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 369
What Mulhall says here is just not right. Typically, if someone were to
dispute my claim that the color of my living room wall is blue rather than
green, we would not try to settle the dispute by consulting the color chart in
an interior decoration book. A color chart might be of help if we were
quarrelling about, say, whether a certain shade of green is called (by a
certain paint maker) ‘‘Apple Green’’ or ‘‘Pear Green.’’ But a chart will not
help us decide whether a given color is blue or green. In our world, color
charts just do not have that kind of authority in this sort of case. If two
people really disagree about whether the color of a wall is blue or green, and
if they are at all confident in their ability to distinguish these colors, they will
continue to disagree about whether the relevant color sample is blue or
green. It matters little whether such a color chart counts that sample as a
shade of green or a shade of blue. If I am really convinced that the color is
blue, the color chart’s calling it, say, ‘‘Sea Green’’, will not make me change
my mind; rather, I will argue that what this color chart calls ‘‘Sea Green’’ is,
in fact, a shade of blue.
Nor will asking other people be of much help. Suppose I think the color of
the wall is a borderline case, but if I had to make a decision I would call it
‘‘blue’’ rather than ‘‘green.’’ Then, if almost everyone else told me that they
would rather call it ‘‘green’’, I might change my habits of talking. But if I do
not, I will still be counted as a member of that linguistic community. My
continuing to classify this shade as ‘‘blue’’ does not mean that people will
regard me as incompetent in my use of color words. At most, they will think
of me as just a little bit idiosyncratic. By contrast, if I am absolutely
convinced that the color is not a borderline case, but definitely blue, the fact
that other people disagree with me would be very troubling. But it would
not be troubling in the way a straightforward falsification of an empirical
hypothesis is troubling. It would be worse. As Wittgenstein says in the
passage quoted above, such disagreement would make me totally confused
and I might then perhaps take my peers or myself for crazy. It might, of
course, turn out that I have become color-blind; but this will then show itself
in my being unable, in regular and predictable ways, to distinguish between
370 M. Gustafsson
green and blue in a series of other cases. This scenario is not, I suppose,
what Mulhall has in mind.
So ironically, the example Mulhall offers illustrates precisely the opposite
of what he takes it to show. If, by ‘‘a normative standard against which a
particular judgment is to be assessed’’, we mean something like a color
chart, then there are many uses of language which are not governed by any
such standard. Indeed, many of the most basic, everyday uses of language
involve no such authoritative standard. Now what I am arguing is that,
according to Cavell, the ordinary language philosopher is interested in
precisely these very basic and elementary strata of linguistic practice. That is
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
the level at which his investigation takes place. Indeed, how could it be
otherwise? If he were interested in uses of language where authoritative
standards analogous to color charts did play the kind of role Mulhall
describes, his task would be relatively simple but also relatively uninterest-
ing. All he would have to do then would be to inform us about the
authoritative charts, rule-books, and so on. But this is precisely what he
cannot do; it is precisely the sense in which his task is not simple. Instead, he
has to remind people of what they already know (but cannot be informed
about), and the only basis on which he can claim to do so is his own position
as competent language user, his own sense of the language he has inherited
and claims to share with others.10
This is related to what Cavell regards as another central feature of
philosophical investigations of ordinary language, namely, that such
investigations ‘‘can as appropriately or truly be said to be looking at the
world as looking at language’’ (MWM, p. 99). Considering the cliché that
Austin’s central philosophical concern lies in drawing distinctions, Cavell
discusses how examples and (‘‘most characteristically’’) stories set the stage
for Austin’s distinctions. He contrasts Austin’s use of examples with that
which can be found in the writings of more traditional philosophers, such as
Russell, Broad and Moore,
On reading Austin, says Cavell, ‘‘what we learn will not be new empirical
facts about the world, and yet illuminating facts about the world. It is true
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 371
that he asks for the difference between doing something by mistake and
doing it by accident, but what transpires is a characterization of what a
mistake is and (as contrasted, or so far as contrasted with this) what an
accident is’’ (MWM, p.104).
Consider a case when you need to use a color chart. You and your friend
are having a dispute about the color of his living room wall: you say it is
Apple Green, he says it is Pear Green. Your problem might then be
described as follows: you want to know about a set of rules telling you which
one of the labels ‘‘Apple Green’’ and ‘‘Pear Green’’ is rightly applied to an
already identified bit of reality. Now this is very different from the kind of
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
V.
I now return to the theme of section II: the similiarities and differences
between Cavell’s and McDowell’s ways of understanding Wittgenstein’s
372 M. Gustafsson
within their anchoring in human life, however, the objective purport of such
concepts and perceptions is unproblematic. Indeed, McDowell’s
Wittgenstein thinks such anchoring is a precondition for objectivity.
Weighing the anchor means closing oneself off from the world.12
So far, there is perhaps not much disagreement between McDowell and
Cavell. In any case, the disagreement I am interested in here has to do with
the question of whether Wittgenstein’s vision of language is, as Cavell puts
it, ‘‘terrifying.’’ I suggested before that McDowell would not, without
qualification, agree with this characterization. According to McDowell, if
Wittgenstein’s vision appears terrifying, it is only because we have not fully
understood it. By contrast, Cavell’s Wittgenstein does not think that
philosophical clear-sightedness offers protection against such terror. On the
contrary, his view appears to be that the dream of such protection is
fundamentally misguided.
In order to get clearer about this issue, it is useful to consider some of the
ways in which the relation between having perfect pitch and lacking perfect
pitch is different from the relation between being ‘‘normally immersed’’ in
familiar practices and being philosophically dissatisfied with such practices.
Here is one such difference. In relation to a community where everyone has
perfect pitch, I would be an outsider. For I cannot identify pitches without
making use of something like a tuning-fork. Similarly, someone who is tone-
deaf is an outsider in relation to people who have normal pitch. And the
colour-blind are unable to use colour words in that direct sort of way that
characterizes the practice of people endowed with normal colour vision. In
all these cases, the outsider’s position is, as it were, totally involuntary: his
inability is a natural deficiency he can do little or nothing about. Roughly
speaking, he has no choice but to view the practice from without. By
contrast, in the sort of case on which both McDowell and Cavell focus,
where someone is philosophically dissatisfied with familiar practices, the
situation is different and more complex. For in this sort of case, the person is
perfectly able to participate in the relevant practices. Indeed, most of his
time he is as ‘‘normally immersed’’ in those practices as anyone else.
Consequently, his philosophical alienation must somehow be self-imposed,
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 373
and thus quite different from the non-participation of the tone-deaf or the
color-blind.
Moreover, this philosophically dissatisfied person is not clearly aware of
his detachment: he does not take himself to have lost sight of the concepts
whose objective purport he wants to legitimize. On the contrary, he thinks
his reflections lead to a firmer grasp of those concepts. His sense is that the
procedures of abstraction and generalization that typically characterize his
approach serve to clarify or purify the concepts, rather than to hide them
from view. So here we have a second disanalogy between this sort of
philosophical detachment and the way in which someone who lacks perfect
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
pitch is detached from practices that involve the exercise of perfect pitch. He
who lacks perfect pitch knows he is an outsider. Whereas, if Cavell’s and
McDowell’s diagnosis is right, the philosophically dissatisfied person is not
aware of his having dissociated himself from the conditions under which the
concepts he claims to be clarifying are meaningfully applied.
Note how extremely provocative this diagnosis is, or should be. The
provocation is largely due to the fact that the supposedly detached
philosopher is a master of the practice from which he is said to have
alienated himself. He is a competent language user. And yet, Cavell and
McDowell dare to claim, when such a person thinks he is gaining a reflective
understanding of certain concepts of that language, what happens is the very
opposite: those concepts slip through his fingers.
How is such self-inflicted yet unconscious alienation possible? If the sort
of diagnosis that Cavell and McDowell are offering is going to seem at all
plausible, they must give a credible answer to this question. At this point,
one can begin to sense a distinctive difference between the two philosophers.
McDowell can be read as providing an answer according to which the
temptation to alienate oneself from familiar practices is contingent upon
certain events in relatively recent intellectual history. In Mind and World, he
argues that the philosophical anxieties he discusses require the background
of a conception of nature as ‘‘disenchanted’’, a conception which ‘‘was made
available only by a hard-won achievement of human thought at a specific
time, the time of the rise of modern science.’’13 Admittedly, it is not
altogether clear if the root of the anxieties McDowell refers to here is
identical with the sort of self-inflicted alienation I have been describing
above, or if those anxieties should rather be seen as resulting from one
specifically modern form of such alienation, other forms being imaginable
under different historical circumstances. The latter alternative would leave it
open for McDowell to argue that the temptation to alienate oneself from
familiar practices is not, in general, as historically conditioned as he
sometimes seems to be suggesting. On the other hand, the fact remains that
the only account he gives of the origin of this temptation is in terms of the
emergence and metaphysical exploitation of our modern conception of
374 M. Gustafsson
be rendered as follows: the part of the object that is seen consists of all the
points of the object which are such that you can draw straight lines from the
observer’s eye to those points without interruption. If no non-transparent
matter blocks the way from the eye to a given point, then that point belongs
to the visible part of the object. The eye is like a searchlight directed toward
the object: the part that gets illuminated is the part which can be seen, while
the part which remains dark is out of sight. Since any instance of seeing
something is possible to picture in this sort of way, it seems to follow that
whenever we see an object, we see only that part of it which faces us in the
above mentioned sense—the object’s front surface. Hence (the argument
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
continues), to the extent that we want to say that a certain object consists of
something more than such a front surface, we will have to admit that we
never see the whole object, but only a part of it.15
This argument may seem indisputable. But Cavell thinks there is a
fundamental problem with it. This problem becomes discernible once we
dare to raise the following question: does the model the epistemologist
invokes really manage to identify and distinguish between parts of an object?
At first, this question may sound ridiculous. Clearly, one wants to say, the
suggested scheme distinguishes between parts. One part is the part made up
of all the points to which straight lines can be drawn without interruption,
and the other part is the part to which such uninterrupted lines cannot be
drawn. That seems obvious enough.
But are these so-called ‘‘parts’’ really parts in any substantial sense of the
word? Think again about Peter’s and Paula’s discussion. To understand
what it means for Peter to be struck by the fact that he did not see the whole
ball, it is crucial to realize that the identity of the part he did see is not
established by reference to the fact that this part happens to be facing him.
Suppose Peter grabs the object and turns it around. That would mean that
the part that he just saw gradually disappears from view, and yet it remains
the same part as before. Some other part of the thing, a part that was not
seen earlier—the back side—will then come into view. If the thing is a ball,
that other part will have the same convex shape as the part that was visible
earlier. If the thing is a shell, Peter will instead be looking into a concave
hollow.
So when Peter and Paula talk about ‘‘the back side’’ of what Peter took to
be a ball, the identity of that part ‘‘is established independently of the
(merely geometrical-physical) fact that it is then and there not visible from
[Peter’s] position’’ (CR, p. 200). And analogously for the front surface. This
makes their usage significantly different from the one suggested by the
epistemologist’s scheme. In fact, it is crucial to the general aspirations of the
epistemologist—his will to conclude that we can never see any part of an
object other than its front surface—that no such independent identification
of parts occurs. If the identity of a part is established independently of the
geometrical-physical facts of a particular moment of seeing, then it is
376 M. Gustafsson
perfectly possible to see the back side of an object: just walk around the
object, or turn it around.16
Considered merely as a formal move within his model, the epistemolo-
gist’s conclusion, ‘‘We never see any part of an object other than its
front surface’’, is indeed indisputable. But it is also both trivial and
empty: it is a tautologous consequence of the conventions that define the
model, and has no bearing on anything else. The problem is that the
epistemologist wants his generalization to amount to something more
than such an empty move. His conclusion is supposed to result from
an application of the model to reality. He intends to make a substantial
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
claim.
This means that the epistemologist has run into a dilemma. His general
aspirations require that no independent identification of parts be made. His
wish to make a genuine claim requires the opposite: that such an
independent identification of parts is made. The validity of the epistemol-
ogist’s conclusion depends on the model’s being a model of nothing;
whereas the substance of the conclusion requires that the model is actually
applied.
This might be difficult to realize. One might think that applying the model
cannot be a problem, for it seems to fit (automatically, as it were) all
instances of someone’s seeing an object. Again, it is trivial that each such act
of seeing takes place under certain geometrical and physical circumstances,
and the scheme seems to tell us how those circumstances determine what is
actually seen. But, again, the problem is with the expression, ‘‘what is
actually seen.’’ There is of course a sense in which it is true that geometrical
and physical circumstances determine what part of an object is visible from
a given point of view. It is essential, however, that we can specify the seen
part, the ‘‘what’’, without reference to those geometrical-physical circum-
stances. Otherwise, it is totally unclear what is being ‘‘determined’’ by the
geometrical and physical circumstances; all we get is a redescription of those
circumstances in terms of ‘‘visible points.’’
And if we try (by force, as it were) to make reality fit this empty
redescription in a more substantial sense, the result is arbitrary distortion.
For example, how are we going to account for the fact that real-life
observers can and must move around in the world? If the identity of the
parts of an object is established solely in terms of their geometrical relation
to the observer, such moving around becomes incomprehensible. After all,
for a creature with visual organs, moving around among objects means
coming to see new parts of the objects, parts that were previously out of
sight. But seeing parts that were previously out of sight is precisely what the
redescription seems to leave no room for, since it entails that we always see
the same part of an object, ‘‘the front surface.’’ So, the upshot is that we do
not move around. Allegedly, what actually happens when we, as we usually
put it, ‘‘walk around objects in order to take a look at their back sides’’, is
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 377
that the front surfaces of objects change their visual appearance. The picture
is that it is the passing show around us which alters, somewhat like when
watching a film, whereas the position of our eyes remains fixed.17
I hope my discussion of this example has given the reader a sense of the
complexity Cavell sees in the relation between our familiar use of concepts
and the philosophical dissatisfaction with that use. Moreover, the example
should suggest why it is there, in that complex relation, that Cavell finds the
explanation of how a master of the language can take himself to be
clarifying familiar concepts when, in reality, he loses sight of those very
concepts. It is, for example, highly significant that our imagined
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
parts in any particular case, the epistemologist’s model seems to cleanse our
ordinary ways of making that distinction from the shifting concerns which
make us raise the issue in real-life situations. In real cases, we have specific
worries: we suspect that what looks like a ball is, in fact, a shell; we want to
know whether John sees that the vase before him has a crack in it; we use an
ultra-sound scanner to look at a fetus in order to check its development; and
so on and so forth. In each such case, saying ‘‘I don’t see the whole thing’’
has a specific point, the appreciation of which requires, precisely, a sharing
of interests, feelings, and perhaps senses of humor, significance, and
fulfillment. The epistemologist’s conclusion, by contrast, is in that sense
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
purified our concepts so that they are no longer tainted by human life. The
struggle with this temptation is what Cavell calls the struggle with
skepticism. He explicitly says this struggle is ‘‘endless.’’19 Our question is:
what are his reasons for saying so? Why, according to Cavell, can’t we put
an end to the struggle, simply by taking Wittgenstein’s vision to heart and,
in McDowell’s already quoted words, ‘‘give up the idea that philosophical
thought […] should be undertaken at some external standpoint, outside our
immersion in our familiar forms of life?’’
To begin with, Cavell thinks it cannot be made fully clear, beforehand and
at a general level, what it is that we are supposed to give up here. What can
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
word, requires a consensus that, in this sort of case, cannot be taken for
granted without begging the question.
This is not to say that one cannot have a meaningful discussion about the
appropriateness of a projection. In some cases, as in ‘‘feed his pride’’, there
is spontaneous agreement—or ‘‘attunement’’, to use the term Cavell prefers
in this connection. In other cases, however, the agreement or attunement is
less immediate. As Cavell notes, ‘‘a new projection, though not at first
obviously appropriate, may be made appropriate by giving relevant
explanations of how it is to be taken, how the new context is an instance
of the old concept’’ (CR, p. 192). In fact, this should make it even clearer
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
that the idea of deciding beforehand which projections are tolerable and
which are intolerable is absurd. Explanations of the sort Cavell is talking
about are given, for example, when an art form is renewed, or when a
scientific revolution is instigated. It is of the essence of such renewals and
revolutions that their character and appropriateness is unforeseeable. We
need to consider each such case individually, when we are actually
confronted with it. Before such actual confrontation, it is indeterminate
what the adequate diagnosis of and response to the projection will be.20
Consider the following example. A director claims to have made a film
noir. Watching the film makes us puzzled and suspicious, however. For, in
many seemingly important respects, this film seems quite different from
classical film noir. Either it constitutes a radical renewal of the genre, or it is
not a film noir at all—and we suspect the latter. Clearly, deciding the issue
cannot just be a matter of applying pre-established rules or definitions or
criteria. To be sure, many film guides and cinematographic textbooks list
criteria for what constitutes a film noir, but one thing that characterizes the
imagined situation is that such official criteria are useless, since the director
clearly intends to challenge their purported accuracy. The way to resolve our
puzzlement is, rather, to engage in a careful reexamination of what it is that
we want to say when we classify a film as a film noir. Perhaps a sensitive
critic can show us that our spontaneous reaction (to say that the film is not a
film noir at all) is in fact in tension with what we are able to recognize as the
most profound characteristics of classical film noir when we watch them
carefully and perceptively. By reminding us of those characteristics and
experiences, and by making careful comparisons between paradigm
examples of the genre and the new film, such a critic may be able to
identify surprising continuities. Taken together, such comparisons and
reminders may make it clear to us that we should acknowledge that the critic
is right: the film is, indeed, a film noir. It may of course also happen that the
critic’s explanations do not work, but betrays his own superficial grasp of
the genre. In such a case, we might want to conclude that our initial refusal
to count the movie as a film noir was perfectly sound.
There are many other cases similar to this one. In his early essay, ‘‘Music
discomposed’’ (MWM, pp. 180–212), Cavell expresses his misgivings about
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 381
reminders together in the right sort of way, Cavell makes us think again, and
think hard, about what it is that we want to say when we talk about
compositions and improvisations and chance. Clearly, he wants to
encourage the suspicion that the theories behind some of Krenek’s and
Cage’s works are problematic. However, he is careful to point out that his
aim is not to prove, for example, that those works are not musical
compositions. Indeed, it is totally unclear what proving such a thing would
amount to (MWM, p. 205). Rather, the aim of his procedure is restricted to
that of urging us to reconsider what is involved, and what we take to be of
value, in that sensitivity and in those modes of response by which we give
music the place it has in our lives.
According to Cavell, the aim of ordinary language philosophy is, or
should be, similar. The disagreement between the ordinary language
philosopher and his more traditional interlocutor is not resolvable by
reference to rules or definitions. On the other hand, this disagreement is
different from a disintegration like that described at the beginning of this
paper, of the practice where all participants have perfect pitch. With respect
to such disintegration, it makes little sense to try to revive the practice by
entering a dialogue with oneself or with one’s peers. If our perfect pitch is
gone, then it is gone; verbal exchange will not make it come back. By
contrast, practicing the method of ordinary language philosophy, as Cavell
conceives it, means keeping the hope for agreement alive. In this sort of case,
entering a dialogue is meaningful. Even if there is no guarantee that a
resolution will be found, it makes sense to strive for it, and it is the ordinary
language philosopher’s job to do so.21
One way of summarizing Cavell’s dissatisfaction with Austin’s methodo-
logical self-understanding is to say that Austin does not take seriously
enough the need for a genuine dialogue in philosophy. He has a wonderfully
sensitive ear for the nuances of everyday language, but his impatience with
those who do not see those nuances or do not find them illuminating
displays a lack of understanding of, or perhaps of interest in, what it is that
pulls those unappreciative interlocutors away from the ordinary. Austin
often argues as if the difference between him and his interlocutor is,
basically, just a matter of discrimination—as if the perceptivity of his
382 M. Gustafsson
Austinian examples may serve to break the spell of such a scheme. But
there is no guarantee that this will happen. Sometimes some people will
experience the examples as immensely powerful and significant. A more
typical reaction, however, is to say that they are irrelevant. The interlocutor
may admit that the examples remind him of how we talk in real life. But
then, he might add that this established way of talking is of little
philosophical significance. He explains away the reminders. This may be
done in various ways. In a Humean fashion, the interlocutor may argue that
the practical demands of everyday life force us to talk with the vulgar, even
if this means saying things that are strictly speaking false. Alternatively, he
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
may decide that what does not fit his model lies outside the realm of
conceptual content altogether: he may classify it as imprecision due to
practical demands or limitations, as a merely ‘‘pragmatic’’ aspect of
everyday usage, or whatever. Since we are here moving at a level at which
talk about language and talk about reality cannot be neatly separated, such
explaining away constitutes a disapproval, not just of everyday language but
of everyday reality: our life-world is reduced to mere ‘‘appearance.’’ It is
part of being held captive by a scheme that one is good at finding such
explanations, explanations that seem able to disarm any attempt to make
what is ordinary significant for philosophical investigation.
The reminders themselves do not determine how the interlocutor will
respond. Nor do they determine how he should respond. In a sense, no
response is wrong, as long as it tells us something about how the
interlocutor wants his words to function. Indeed, this is precisely the
significance of the interlocutor’s reactions: they show us (and him) what he
wishes to say. Austinian examples are not proofs but provocations. They
bring forth responses that clarify the relation between the interlocutor and
the words he wants to use. Clarification of this relation is achieved even in
cases where the reminders are explained away. For such explaining away
also tells us something about the interlocutor’s desires and requirements.
His preferring a certain explanation may make it clearer what the structure
of his philosophical scheme is, what he expects from this scheme, and so
forth. The hope is that if we are careful and patient enough, our discussion
may reach a point at which it is becoming clear to everyone, including our
interlocutor, that the ways in which he wants to use his words do not hold
together. We state reminders; those reminders get explained away; we state
more reminders in response to the ways in which the former ones were
disarmed; and so on and so forth. Eventually, this dialectical process may
make it patent to us and to the interlocutor that his position is unstable, that
he is wavering between different and incompatible requirements. This is
what it means to show that the interlocutor is speaking nonsense, in a
philosophically pertinent sense of that word. Rather than proving that his
way of talking constitutes an inappropriate departure from everyday usage,
what we do is bring the investigation to a point where it is plain, to us and to
384 M. Gustafsson
VI.
According to Cavell, Wittgenstein’s vision of language entails that we are
burdened with the responsibility of keeping language alive and the world in
view. Moreover, Cavell says we fear that responsibility: we would like to get
rid of it. At bottom, it is this fear that shows itself in our tendency to reason
as if being immersed in human life forms is an impediment to (rather than a
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Thus, Cavell’s Wittgenstein thinks the fact that I have become fully aware
of my responsibility in itself means that I am prepared to acknowledge both
that the temptation is still there, and that the possibility of my succumbing
to it is a real and permanent danger for which no secure protection can be
provided. If this sounds speculative or even abstruse, it may be helpful to
note that something similar may be said about various other kinds of human
interaction. For example, consider marriage. As a spouse, I am responsible
for keeping my marriage alive. Passively ignoring the required effort means
killing the relation; the marriage then continues to be a marriage only in the
formal sense of the word. And yet it is tempting to give up this responsibility
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
Notes
1. Cavell (1994), p. 21. All future references to Cavell (1994) are made parenthetically in the
text by means of PoP and the appropriate page number.
2. McDowell (1998), pp. 61, 207. All future references to McDowell (1998) are made
parenthetically in the text by means of MVR and the appropriate page number.
3. Cavell (2002), p. 52, note omitted. All future references to Cavell (2002) are made
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
parenthetically in the text by means of MWM and the appropriate page number.
4. Cavell (1979), p. 109. All future references to Cavell (1979) are made parenthetically in
the text by means of CR and the appropriate page number.
5. McDowell (2002), p. 294.
6. Wittgenstein (1978), paragraph VI-35.
7. Austin (1979), p. 185, n. 1.
8. Affeldt’s criticism is in Affeldt (1998).
9. Mulhall (1998), p. 40.
10. I take my point here to be closely related to what Affeldt says about Cavell’s notion of
criteria in the following passage: ‘‘To speak of our sharing an order of criteria is to speak
of an order in our judgments (and conduct). Eliciting criteria reveals the fine-grained
structure of our agreement in judgment. It does not reveal a separate order under-
girding and controlling that agreement. […] It would be a philosophical distortion of
what is involved in our being, as Cavell puts it, initiates of language, to imagine that we
somehow always have or possess (perhaps only tacitly) a catalogue of criteria which we
use in speaking and making judgments. One central reason for Cavell’s insistence that
our agreement in language and our agreement in criteria are the same phenomenon
differently described is precisely to fend off this, philosophically tempting, idea’’ (Affeldt
(1998), p. 15).
11. Perhaps the difference between the two tasks is not very different from Kant’s difference
between formal and transcendental logic: whereas the former takes the application of
rules for granted, the latter constitutes an investigation into the conditions for the
possibility of such application (Cf. MWM, p. 168).
12. One might want to argue that the term ‘‘objectivity’’ is misplaced here, since this term is
too ingrained with philosophical prejudices of the sort which both McDowell and Cavell
are concerned to reject. But McDowell would disagree. He freely admits that the notion
of objectivity involves the idea of inquiry as answerable to something other than
ourselves, but argues that this is a perfectly intelligible idea that does substantial work
within our familiar practices. What needs to be rejected, according to McDowell, is not
the familiar notion of objectivity, but the idea of a gap between the world and us. (See,
for example, McDowell (2000), pp. 110–111.) I take Cavell to ascribe a similar view to
Wittgenstein, for example in the following remark which alludes to Kant’s conception of
things-in-themselves: ‘‘For Wittgenstein it would be an illusion not only that we do
know things-in-themselves, but equally an illusion that we do not (crudely, because the
concept of ‘knowing something as it really is’ is being used without a clear sense, apart
from its ordinary language game)’’ (MWM, p. 65). As the parenthetical remark makes
clear, the point here is not that Wittgenstein takes the concept of ‘‘knowing something as
it really is’’ and its cognates to be somehow illegitimate. Rather, Cavell is arguing that
Wittgenstein thinks those concepts have familiar uses, uses that are perfectly all right.
What Wittgenstein is said to react against is the philosophical attempt to remove those
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 387
concepts from that stream of life within which they do their work. According to Cavell,
it is precisely that sort of attempt which makes it seem as if a gap opens up between
familiar practices and reality.
13. McDowell (1996), p. 70.
14. What follows is a free rendering of the discussions in CR, pp. 197ff., and MWM, pp.
249ff. Thanks to Stina Bäckström for a good conversation about these passages, and to
David Finkelstein for a stimulating discussion about the philosophical significance of
ball shells.
15. I am disregarding the case when the object is made of some transparent material, such as
glass. In this sort of case, the scheme, as specified above, does allow us to say that we
‘‘see the whole object’’ even if the object consists of something more than a front surface.
In fact, reflecting on the phenomenon of transparency may have far-reaching
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
master of the science can accept a revolutionary change as a natural extension of that
science; and that he accepts it, or proposes it, in order to maintain touch with the idea of
that science, with its internal canons of comprehensibility and comprehensiveness, as if
against the vision that, under altered circumstances, the normal progress of explanation
and exception no longer seem to him to be science’’ (CR, p. 121).
21. What I am saying here and in the rest of section 5 is meant to address the worry that
ordinary language philosophy, as conceived by Cavell, must be impotent as a mode of
criticism. This worry is perhaps reinforced by a misunderstanding of the intimate
connection between, on the one hand, the impossibility of flat repudiation, and on the
other, the first person plural character of the investigations of ordinary language
philosophy. Cavell writes, ‘‘the way you must rely upon yourself as a source of what is
said when, demands that you grant full title to others as sources of that data—not out of
Downloaded by [Ohio State University Libraries] at 15:19 03 June 2012
politeness, but because the nature of the claim you make for yourself is repudiated
without that acknowledgement: it is a claim that no one knows better than you whether
and when a thing is said, and if this is not to be taken as a claim to expertise (a way of
taking it which repudiates it) then it must be understood to mean that you know no
better than others what you claim to know. With respect to the data of philosophy our
positions are the same’’ (MWM, pp. 239–40). Isn’t the consequence that the conflict
between the ordinary language philosopher and his interlocutor is exactly like the earlier
imagined conflict between people who used to have perfect pitch but who no longer
agree in their identification of pitches? If so, it seems as if all the ordinary language
philosopher can do is to insist that his own ‘‘everyday’’ way of talking is the appropriate
one. And that would not convince his opponent, who we may expect to be an equally
staunch defender of ‘‘philosophical’’ usage. According to the sort of reading I present
here, however, a main purpose of Cavell’s criticism of Austin and other ordinary
language philosophers is precisely to show them a way out of this kind of stalemate.
According to Cavell, to argue that ‘‘philosophical’’ usage constitutes a demonstrably
inappropriate deviation from everyday language is dangerous, precisely because the real
consequence of such belligerence is impotence: the ordinary language philosopher and
his opponent will be talking past one another, and each one will be as convinced as
before that he is (demonstrably) right. (See, for example, CR, p. 146.)
22. For an illuminating discussion of what Cavell thinks it means to lapse into
meaninglessness, see Witherspoon (2002).
23. McDowell (1996), p. 177.
24. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at workshops at Uppsala University and at
The University of Chicago. I thank the audiences for thoughtful discussions. In
particular, I wish to thank Zed Adams, Steven Affeldt, Avner Baz, Stina Bäckström,
Stanley Cavell, James Conant, David Finkelstein, Stephen Mulhall and Lisa Van
Alstyne for helpful comments and criticisms. I am, of course, solely responsible for any
remaining mistakes and misinterpretations. Work on the paper was financed by The
Swedish Research Council.
References
Affeldt, S. (1998) ‘‘The ground of mutuality: Criteria, judgment, and intelligibility in Stephen
Mulhall and Stanley Cavell’’, European Journal of Philosophy, 6, pp. 1–31.
Austin, J. L. (1979) Philosophical Papers, 3rd ed (New York: Oxford University Press).
Baz, A. (2003) ‘‘On when words are called for: Cavell, McDowell, and the wording of the
world’’, Inquiry, 46, pp. 473–500.
Cavell, S. (1979) The Claim of Reason (New York: Oxford University Press).
Cavell, S. (1989) This New Yet Unapproachable America (Albuquerque, NM: Living Batch
Press).
Perfect Pitch and Austinian Examples: Cavell, McDowell, Wittgenstein 389
University Press).
Mulhall, S. (1998) ‘‘The givenness of grammar: A reply to Steven Affeldt’’, European Journal of
Philosophy, 6, pp. 32–44.
Witherspoon, E. (2002) ‘‘Houses, flowers, and frameworks: Cavell and Mulhall on the moral of
scepticism’’, European Journal of Philosophy, 10, pp. 195–208.
Wittgenstein, L. (1978) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, 3rd ed (Oxford: Blackwell).