"Democracy As Civilisation": Christopher Hobson
"Democracy As Civilisation": Christopher Hobson
1, January, 2008
“Democracy as Civilisation”
CHRISTOPHER HOBSON!
Since the fall of the Berlin Wall, democracy has come to embody the very idea
of legitimate statehood in international politics. It has done so largely through defining
a new standard of civilisation, in which “democraticness” determines the limits of
international society and helps to construct relations with non-democracies “beyond
the pale”. Like the “classical” standard, this new version again reflects a considerable
interest in the socio-political organisation of states. Central in this shift back to a
more “anti-pluralist” international society has been the democratic peace thesis,
which emphasises how the internal (democratic) characteristics of states influence
their external behaviour. Against more optimistic interpretations, it is argued that the
democratic peace is a distinctly Janus-faced creature: promoting peace between democra-
cies, while potentially encouraging war against non-democratic others. Within the
democratic peace, non-democracies become not just behaviourally threatening but also
ontologically threatening. Non-democracies are a danger because of what they are
(or are not). In sum, the argument presented is that democracy, positioned as the
most legitimate form of domestic governance in international society, has become
caught up and used in global structures of domination, hierarchy and violence. Thus,
the role of “democracy” in international politics is much more complicated, and, at
least in its current guise, less progressive than often portrayed.
The United States has no right, no desire, and no intention to impose our
form of government on anyone else . . . Our aim is to build and preserve a
community of free and independent nations, with governments that
answer to their citizens, and reflect their own cultures. And because
democracies respect their own people and their neighbors, the advance
of freedom will lead to peace.1
!
Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the Oceanic Conference on International Studies,
University of Melbourne (July 2006) and the Critical and Cultural Politics Research Group, University
of Wales, Aberystwyth (October 2006). I would like to thank the participants at these meetings, as well
as the reviewers and editor for their useful suggestions and feedback. Special thanks go to Cindy
O’Hagan and Raymond Apthorpe for encouraging me to pursue this argument.
1. George W. Bush, “State of the Union Address”, 2 February 2005, available: ,http://www.white
house.gov/news/releases/2005/02/20050202-11.html. (accessed 15 January 2006).
Introduction
What the failed attempt at coercive democratisation in Iraq has helped to reveal is
a fundamental tension in how the idea of democracy operates in world politics.
On the one hand, something called “democracy” is almost universally accepted
as a normative good. As Sen puts it, “in the general climate of world opinion,
democratic governance has now achieved the status of being taken to be generally
right”.2 Established democracies seek to confirm their status through constantly
reaffirming their “democraticness” at home, while attempting to promote it
abroad. States that have recently transited to democracy hope to consolidate
their hard-fought position through continuing reforms, internationally monitored
elections and a host of other mechanisms supported by a transnational web of
democracy promoters. These same actors that assist recently democratised
states—older liberal democracies, international organisations and a plethora of
NGOs—also encourage moves towards democracy in the states that have so far
resisted this global trend. The hope is to continue and consolidate the sizeable
shift towards liberal democracy that has occurred in recent decades, which has
resulted in a host of benefits—the growth of human freedom, greater respect for
human rights and a decline in interstate war—to name a few of the most
prominent.
At the same stage, the end of the Cold War also meant the disappearance of
major ideational challenges to the liberal democratic model.3 Increasingly a stric-
ter understanding of what democracy means, and what one should look like, has
emerged from the United States and other influential liberal democracies. The
entry ticket to the “community of free and independent nations” Bush speaks of
is a type of democracy that corresponds to the model found in America and its
liberal democratic allies. The grouping of transnational actors promoting democ-
racy has tended to do so through offering a version that reflects the standards and
interests of the most powerful democracies.4 With democracy becoming the legit-
imate form of domestic governance in international politics, its emancipatory
potential has been distinctly curtailed, through being caught up and used in
global structures of domination, hierarchy and violence. Democracy, usually
seen as being demanded from “below”, is now clearly also something demanded
from “above”. Thus, a serious tension emerges from the contradictory practices
and discourses surrounding democracy in international politics. On the one
hand, the emancipatory intent of democracy is symbolised in events like the
recent “colour revolutions”. On the other hand, there is the disastrous Iraq misad-
venture, partly motivated and justified in the name of democracy. Both represent a
face of “democracy” in world politics at present.
2. Amartya Sen, “Democracy as a Universal Value”, Journal of Democracy, Vol. 10, No. 3 (1999), p. 5.
3. This is not to deny the challenge posed by Islamic extremism, but to suggest that it does not rep-
resent the same, unified and complete ideational alternative in the way fascism and communism were.
As Dunn puts it, “at this point democracy’s ideological triumph seems bewilderingly complete. There
is little immediate danger, of course, of its running out of enemies, or ceasing to be an object of real hate.
But it no longer faces compelling rivals as a view of how political authority should be structured, or of
who is entitled to assess whether or not that authority now rests in the right hands.” John Dunn, Setting
the People Free: The Story of Democracy (London: Atlantic Books, 2005), p. 162.
4. Barry Gills, Joel Rocamora and Richard Wilson (eds.), Low Intensity Democracy (London: Pluto
Press, 1993); William Robinson, Promoting Polyarchy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
“Democracy as Civilisation” 77
Without denying the positive uses of the idea(l) of democracy, more attention
needs to be given to its less progressive, more coercive dimension. The normative
“goodness” of democracy means the way the concept is implicated in processes of
domination, hierarchy and violence is regularly lost. Admittedly, there have been
important contributions highlighting the less salutary dimensions of democracy
promotion,5 the democratic peace thesis6 and the democratic entitlement in inter-
national law.7 To date, however, these studies have remained discrete and too
small in number. The “theoretical and empirical lacunae . . . in respect of the inter-
relationship of democracy and international relations in post-Cold War politics”,
which Hazel Smith and her colleagues considered in a special issue of Global
Society, remains significant a decade later.8 What needs to be further reflected on
is the way these separate, albeit interrelated, discourses and practices all feed
into and reinforce the pre-eminent position of democracy in world politics. One
particularly vital matter, with which this article concerns itself, is the role of
democracy in defining legitimate statehood, and, in so doing, helping to structure
relations between democratic and non-democratic states. The part played by this
powerful idea(l) in informing a new standard of civilisation is examined, with it
being argued that “democraticness” is now central in determining the limits of
international society and in constructing relations with those “beyond the pale”.
It is shown that democracy’s position in international politics is much more
complicated, and, at least in its current guise, less progressive than regularly por-
trayed. Against readings which see democracy’s global entrenchment as opening
possibilities for greater levels of international peace, stronger international law
and more secure protection of human rights, it is argued that its place at the
heart of a new standard of civilisation means “democracy” also can, and does,
promote processes of exclusion, hierarchy and violence. Put simply, the overwhel-
mingly bright aura that surrounds “democracy” should not blind us from this
darker side.
The argument will proceed as follows. First, discourses of civilisation(s) in inter-
national politics will be briefly outlined. This will lead to a discussion on stan-
dards of civilisation, with the “classical” standard of the 19th and 20th centuries
being considered. Only through understanding properly how it has existed will
we then be able to comprehend the features that inform the standard in its
present guise. In reflecting on this latest iteration of the standard, it will be
argued that democracy plays a central and determining role. The manner in
which this new standard is constituted and operates will be analysed through
examining how democracy is bringing together the two faces of international
legitimacy, what Clark terms “rightful membership” and “rightful conduct”.9
Specifically, the way the democratic peace thesis encourages a strengthening
between these two dimensions will be highlighted, with emphasis placed on
the less progressive outcomes of this highly influential discourse. It will be
5. Ibid.
6. Tarak Barkawi and Mark Laffey, “The Imperial Peace: Democracy, Force and Globalization”,
European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 5, No. 4 (1999); idem, Democracy, Liberalism, and War
(Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 2001).
7. Susan Marks, The Riddle of All Constitutions: International Law, Democracy, and the Critique of
Ideology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
8. Hazel Smith, “Democracy and International Relations”, Global Society, Vol. 12, No. 2 (1998), p. 156.
9. Ian Clark, Legitimacy in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).
78 C. Hobson
17. Jan Ifversen, Civilisation and Barbarism, Discourse Politics Identity Working Paper No. 1
(Lancaster: Institute for Advanced Studies in Social and Management Sciences, Lancaster University,
2005), pp. 7–9.
18. Mark Salter, Barbarians and Civilization in International Relations (London: Pluto Press, 2002),
p. 18.
19. Reinhart Koselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
1985).
20. Gerrit Gong, The Standard of “Civilization” in International Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1984), p. 3.
21. Ifversen notes that while “civilisation” is still regularly used, “barbarism” is used much less
frequently. The latter concept, however, has been making something of a comeback since the “war
on terror” commenced. See Ifversen, op. cit., p. 9.
22. Gerrit Gong, “Standards of Civilization Today”, in Mehdi Mozaffari (ed.), Globalization and
Civilizations (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 80.
80 C. Hobson
23. Chris Brown, “World Society and the English School: An ‘International Society’ Perspective on
World Society”, European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 7, No. 4 (2001), p. 427.
24. Christian Reus-Smit, The Moral Purpose of the State (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999),
pp. 36–39. For a discussion of “practical” and “purposive” forms of association, see Terry Nardin, Law,
Morality, and the Relations of States (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983).
25. Hedley Bull’s oft-quoted definition of international society emphasises the importance of
common values as a defining feature: “a society of states (or international society) exists when a
group of states, conscious of certain common interests and common values, form a society in the
sense that they conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of rules in their relations with
one another, and share in the working of common institutions”. Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society
(London: Macmillan, 1977), p. 13.
26. Bowden, op. cit., ch. 5.
27. Quoted in ibid., p. 124.
“Democracy as Civilisation” 81
The key elements of the standard thus centred on “the degree of socio-political
organisation and the form of government”.30 And the model for this was, of
course, to be found in Europe. To be acknowledged as “civilised”, non-European
states had to replicate European forms of internal governance and external sover-
eignty. The result was that being “civilised” essentially meant being “European”,
in form at least.
Those that did not reach or conform to the model of civilised statehood were
denied full standing in the European international system. This did not,
however, prevent interaction between political communities seen to be at different
levels of civilisation. In practice there were two sets of rules, one of which applied
between “civilised” states, and the other to “civilised” states dealing with “barba-
ric” outsiders. Keene explains that “within Europe, international order was sup-
posed to provide for peaceful coexistence in an anarchic and plural world by
encouraging toleration . . . Beyond Europe, international order was intended to
promote civilization.”31 Imperialism, colonisation, capitulation, unequal treaties
and civilising missions—these were the dominant features of interaction
between “civilised” states and “uncivilised” communities that failed to conform
to the model found in, and provided by, the Europeans. The “classical” standard
of civilisation did considerably more than regulate entry into the European inter-
national system. It also legitimated a different set of rules, norms and practices for
dealing with “uncivilised” parts of the world.
What is convincingly demonstrated in recent critical scholarship on the “classi-
cal” standard is how detrimental this dual system of exclusion, and inclusion
through assimilation, was. Bowden emphasises the extent to which it perpetuated
and justified violent acts of imperialism in the name of “civilising” the other.32 In a
similar vein, Keal identifies the particularly severe impact the imposition of
28. Ibid., p. 122.
29. Gong, The Standard of “Civilization” in International Society, op. cit., pp. 14–15.
30. Bowden, op. cit., p. 123. See also Brett Bowden, “In the Name of Progress and Peace: The ‘Stan-
dard of Civilization’ and the Universalizing Project”, Alternatives, Vol. 29, No. 1 (2004) pp. 43–68; and
Antony Angie, “Finding the Peripheries: Sovereignty and Colonialism in Nineteenth-century Inter-
national Law”, Harvard International Law Journal, Vol. 40, No. 1 (1999) pp. 1–71.
31. Edward Keene, Beyond the Anarchical Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002),
p. 147.
32. Bowden, Expanding the Empire of Civilization, op. cit.
82 C. Hobson
33. Paul Keal, European Conquest and the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003).
34. Shogo Suzuki, “Japan’s Socialization into Janus-faced European International Society”,
European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 11, No. 1 (2005) pp. 137–164.
35. Ibid., p. 155.
36. Keene, op. cit.
37. Salter, op. cit., pp. 38 –42.
38. Quoted in ibid., p. 38.
39. Hedley Bull and Adam Watson (eds.), The Expansion of International Society (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1984).
40. Gong, The Standard of “Civilization” in International Society, op. cit.
41. Jack Donnelly, “Human Rights: A New Standard of Civilization?”, International Affairs, Vol. 74,
No. 1 (1998) pp. 1–23.
42. Ibid., p. 5.
43. Bull and Watson, op. cit., p. 427.
44. John Hobson and J.C. Sharman, “The Enduring Place of Hierarchy in World Politics: Tracing the
Social Logics of Hierarchy and Political Change”, European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 11, No.
1 (2005), p. 92. A similar point is made from a legal perspective in Gerry Simpson, Great Powers and
“Democracy as Civilisation” 83
52. Anthony Langlois, “Human Rights without Democracy? A Critique of the Separationist
Thesis”, Human Rights Quarterly, Vol. 25, No. 4 (2003) pp. 990–1019.
53. Clark, op. cit., ch. 8.
54. Simpson, op. cit.
55. Ibid., p. 77.
56. Ibid., p. 78.
“Democracy as Civilisation” 85
In the post-Cold War era, marked by this liberal anti-pluralism, there has been a
far greater interest in the internal makeup of states, with liberal jurists even claim-
ing the emergence of a “right” to democracy.57 This has also meant a much heavier
emphasis placed on labelling, ostracising and, when necessary, confronting pariah
states that do not conform to the new standard. An increased concern with such
outlaw states has been most prominent in US foreign policy, with President
Bush’s “axis of evil” being the obvious example. Indeed, one characteristic that
unified this “axis” against “the civilized world” was the “non-democratic” label
that America applied to them.58 Reflecting on this anti-pluralist trend, Donnelly
makes the useful distinction between “behavioural” and “ontological” outlaw
states. The former “violate particular international norms”, while the latter “are
outlaws more for who they are than what they have done”.59 The manner in
which international society is reformulating, with a more explicit and stricter
standard based around democracy, is one that leads to states being more easily
classified as “ontological outlaws”. It is what these states are—non-democratic—
that becomes the essential problem and the basis of their pariah status.
Democracy as Civilisation
Democratic governance has become the benchmark for full international legiti-
macy in a world where “a democracy is what it is virtuous for a state to be”.60
Democracy has taken on the conceptual characteristics of “civilisation”, associated
with notions of progress, development, modernisation and a host of other laud-
able traits. The phenomenon of democratic states being considered “virtuous”,
however, is hardly a new one. Ivor Brown wrote shortly after the First World
War of a “world in which every one is trying to show that he is more democratic
than everybody else”.61 This trend quickly declined with the rise of fascism, but
with the end of the Second World War an ideological contest drawing on different
understandings of democracy soon emerged. Central to the dynamics of the Cold
War were two competing visions of this concept—liberal democracy was cham-
pioned by the United States and its allies against the people’s democracies of
the Soviet Union and its satellites. Neither side actively denied “democracy”,
but rather contested its boundaries by attempting to redescribe it in such a
manner as to include one camp, whilst excluding the other. Commenting on the
situation in 1979, Dunn noted that “democratic theory is the moral Esperanto of
the present nation-state system, the language in which all Nations are truly
United”.62 Writing a decade earlier, Macpherson had highlighted three types of
democracy in existence, since along with the liberal and communist versions of
57. Thomas Franck, “The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance”, American Journal of Inter-
national Law, Vol. 86, No. 1 (1992) pp. 49–91.
58. George W. Bush, “State of the Union Address”, 29 January 2002, available: ,http://www.white
house.gov/news/releases/2002/01/20020129-11.html. (accessed 25 November 2007).
59. Jack Donnelly, “Sovereign Inequalities and Hierarchy in Anarchy: American Power and Inter-
national Society”, European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 12, No. 2 (2006) pp. 139 –170.
60. John Dunn, Western Political Theory in the Face of the Future, 2nd edn (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1979), p. 11.
61. Ivor J.C. Brown, The Meaning of Democracy (London: Richard Cobden-Sanderson, 1920),
pp. 175 –176.
62. Dunn, op. cit., p. 2.
86 C. Hobson
democracy, there was also a Third World model.63 With the conclusion of the Cold
War, it was liberal democracy that proved victorious, a perhaps obvious, but
necessary point made by Fukuyama.64 Models of democracy were replaced by a
model of democracy. In this regard, Fenves suggests that Fukuyama hit upon
an important “linguistic fact”, namely “the absence of any universalizable alterna-
tive to the language of liberal democracy for the legitimization of political insti-
tutions”.65 What the end of the Cold War signified was not simply that
democratic states were confirmed as “virtuous”, but also the rise of a much
more limited understanding of what “democracy” as an institution, and in prac-
tice, means. It is one variant—the Anglo-American liberal one—that is promoted
as democracy and the benchmark of fully legitimate statehood.66
Liberal democracy, supposedly exemplified by the United States, has become
hegemonic to the extent that the “liberal” is regularly dropped out, with this
model naturalised as democracy. What is lost is that there are multiple types of
democracy, of which the liberal version is only one.67 In this regard, Hutchings
gives the important caution not “to become closed to the appreciation of alterna-
tive ways of thinking about what democracy means”.68 To do this, it must be
recognised that liberal democracy has been conditioned, shaped and determined
by its primarily Anglo-American heritage. In considering alternative conceptions
of democracy within Africa, Bradley makes the point that it is “a configuration of
governance moulded by the general values, biases, and nuances of a given
culture”.69 What this suggests is that the model of democracy promoted not
only by the United States but also the European Union, United Nations and a
host of other countries and international bodies is not politically and culturally
neutral but one that distinctly reflects the experiences, interests and values of
these promoters. In the case of the world’s most prominent and forceful promoter,
democracy is viewed through an American lens, with an understanding that
closely corresponds to the dominant liberal, procedural definition found in
American political science.70 And clearly the way democracy is promulgated by
63. C.B. Macpherson, The Real World of Democracy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966).
64. “As mankind approaches the end of the millennium, the twin crises of authoritarianism and
social central planning have left only one competitor standing in the ring as an ideology of potentially
universal validity: liberal democracy.” Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man
(New York: Free Press, 1992), p. 42.
65. Peter Fenves, “The Tower of Babel Rebuilt: Some Remarks on ‘The End of History’”, in Timothy
Burns (ed.), After History? Francis Fukuyama and His Critics (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994),
p. 229.
66. Without denying the importance of other versions of democracy, especially the model more
common in Continental Europe, it has been the liberal version that has largely prevailed and
become hegemonic. For example, in international law democracy is understood in such a manner
which emphasises political rights, while largely ignoring economic and social ones.
67. David Held, Models of Democracy, 2nd edn (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996); Macpher-
son, op. cit.
68. Kimberly Hutchings, “Modelling Democracy”, Global Society, Vol. 12, No. 2 (1998), p. 174.
69. Matthew Todd Bradley, “‘The Other’: Precursory African Conceptions of Democracy”, Inter-
national Studies Review, Vol. 7, No. 3 (2005), p. 407.
70. Close ties exist between academic and policy-making communities in relation to democracy
promotion and democratisation. See Robinson, op. cit., ch. 1 and Nicolas Guilhot, The Democracy
Makers: Human Rights and International Order (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005). The
classic procedural definitions come from Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy
(London: George Allen & Unwin, 1943) and Robert Dahl, Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1971).
“Democracy as Civilisation” 87
the leading power has considerable ramifications for the way it is received and
interpreted by other actors in world politics. An understanding that closely corre-
sponds to American experience and the politics of the United States, which
emphasises political and civil rights at the same time as giving less importance
to economic ones, becomes naturalised as democracy. In the process “alterna-
tives”, as Hazel Smith notes, “are made invisible”.71
The relationship between liberalism and democracy found in this version of
democracy is an historically contingent one. Even if one does not fully accept
this argument, instead following Fukuyama and suggesting the universality of
liberal democracy, there will still be differences across societies in terms of the
weighting given to the two parts. Within the American tradition, liberalism has
been hegemonic, structuring democracy.72 Yet there is no reason why in other
societies the two components may not be combined differently. They may be
related more equally, or the democratic dimension could instead structure the
liberal one. The regimes found in Scandinavia offer the most notable real-world
example of prosperous democracies where the liberal dimension is not necessarily
prioritised. Forms of social democracy, along with models that emphasise a far
greater level of activity and participation by the people, are viable alternatives
hidden behind the dominant version. Variations within and between the different
models found in Western democratic states largely disappear when democracy is
exported, with the type promoted being one that corresponds closely to the
Anglo-American standard. And whereas the dominance of liberalism was not a
problem for America at its founding due to exceptionally fortunate circumstances,
it is highly questionable whether similar conditions now exist in most of the
world.73
A new standard of civilisation based on democracy thus retains the Western-
centricism that marked its “classical” iteration. Like the earlier version of the stan-
dard which reflected the interests and values of the dominant European powers,
now democracy is understood and promoted in a similar fashion.74 Within the
new standard, democracy is viewed largely through an American, or more gener-
ally Western, lens. And in so doing, once again a socio-political form of organis-
ation is encouraged, promoted or dictated that conforms to a model emerging
from a core of powerful Western states. This new standard is not asking states
to meet some objective criteria but is asking (or telling) “them” to become more
like “us”. It is for this reason that Mozaffari is mistaken in suggesting that the
new standard operates more through “attraction” than “coercion”.75 Rather,
democracy’s progressive label and the universalising language with which it is
cloaked means that the structures of power it operates in and with are overlooked.
Behind the seemingly benign universal standard of democracy is a specific con-
ception of what democracy is and what democratic states should be. Coercion
operates through defining and limiting what democracy is and can be.
States that do not conform to this liberal democratic standard now struggle to be
recognised as fully legitimate. Indeed, a “sin” that presently unites all rogue and
pariah states is their undemocratic nature.76 Particularly instructive is the case of
Iran, which has claims to being considered democratic,77 but is refused this label
as it does not conform to dominant perceptions of what democracy should be.
When identifying it as part of the “axis of evil”, Bush singled it out as a country
where “an unelected few repress the Iranian people’s hope for freedom”.78
States like Iran that are judged to be non-democratic or insufficiently democratic
are becoming, in the terminology of Donnelly, “ontological outlaws”.79 It is what
these states are, or perhaps more accurately are not, that removes them from, in
Bush’s words, “the civilized world”.80 One major reason for this is that the internal
makeup of states is now widely seen as determinative of external behaviour. Thus,
democracies are threatening precisely because they are non-democratic. At the
heart of these perceptions is the hugely influential Democratic Peace Thesis
(DPT), which proposes that the internal (democratic) character of states has a cau-
sative role in helping to generate international peace. It is necessary to consider
the democratic peace in more detail, as it plays a crucial part in cementing
democracy’s pre-eminent position in international politics. The pacifist nature
of democratic states, identified by the DPT, helps to represent and inform their
“virtue”, while non-democracies increasingly are targeted as obstacles on the
road to “perpetual peace”.
war between democratic states: “in the modern international system, democracies
have almost never fought each other”.82 While a powerful causal explanation for
this phenomenon has yet to be fully provided, studies tend to demonstrate a very
robust correlation between democracies and peace. This leads Russett and Oneal
to suggest “that democracies rarely fight each other is now generally, if not univer-
sally accepted”.83 This may be somewhat of an overstatement considering the
extensive and continuing debate over the DPT’s empirical and theoretical validity.
Perhaps what is more relevant, however, is that the DPT is now generally perceived
as being true. So Russett and Oneal may be justified in their assertion, at least in
regard to key policy-making circles.84 To the extent that democracy is seen to
facilitate and encourage peace internationally, the DPT helps to construct such
states as being “virtuous” and desirable.85 Democracies are lauded for their role
in contributing to the Grundnorm of peace and their part in the recent global
downturn in interstate violence.
The DPT helps to validate and entrench democracy’s place at the heart of a new
standard of civilisation. Within the realm of foreign policy, one of the central
justifications for democracy promotion is, as President Bush explains, the belief
that “if you look at history, democracies are peaceful nations. The spread of
democracy yields peace”.86 The DPT encourages and legitimates the spread of
democracy as a foreign policy aim, with the basic logic being that a growth in
the number of democracies will lead to an expansion of the zone of peace. This
thinking has been most evident in the foreign policy of the United States, where
the promotion of democracy has occupied an especially prominent position
since the end of the Cold War. Writing when Deputy Secretary of State under
the Clinton administration, Strobe Talbott argued that “the larger and more
close-knit the community of nations that choose democratic forms of government,
the safer and more prosperous Americans will be”.87 With the Bush presidency it
was expected that democracy promotion would be less central, but this quickly
changed following the terrorist attacks of 11 September 2001. The spread of
democracy to the Middle East was the consensual long-term solution to the violence
threatened by terrorists and rogue regimes.88 As neo-con Charles Krauthammer
put it, “there is not a single, remotely plausible, alternative strategy for attacking
the monster behind 9/11”.89 At the base of this new, more robust form of democ-
Tony Smith, A Pact with the Devil: Washington’s Bid for World Supremacy and the Betrayal of the American
Promise (New York: Routledge, 2007).
82. Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1993), p. 4.
83. Bruce Russett and John Oneal, Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International
Organizations (New York: Norton, 2001), p. 43.
84. This is most obviously the case in the post-Cold War foreign policy of the United States, with the
DPT clearly influencing both the Clinton and Bush administrations.
85. In legitimating a certain type of domestic regime, the DPT therefore also legitimates a certain set
of actors—the United States, Australia and the other “perfect” democracies.
86. George W. Bush, “President Discusses Second Term Accomplishments and Priorities”, 3 August
2005, available: ,http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2005/08/20050803.html..
87. Strobe Talbott, “Democracy and the National Interest”, Foreign Affairs, Vol. 75, No. 6 (1996),
pp. 48 –49.
88. See Christopher Hobson, “A Forward Strategy of Freedom in the Middle East: US Democracy Pro-
motion and the ‘War on Terror’”, Australian Journal of International Affairs, Vol. 59, No. 1 (2005) pp. 39–53.
89. Charles Krauthammer, Democratic Realism: An American Foreign Policy for a Unipolar World
(Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute Press, 2004).
90 C. Hobson
racy promotion are the findings of the DPT. With the spread of democracy,
through arms or otherwise, the zone of peace and civilisation is expanded. As Pre-
sident Bush tells us, “in Europe, as in Asia, as in every region of the world, the
advance of freedom leads to peace”.90 The logic of the DPT is seemingly an inclus-
ive one, with a ticket to the zone of peace being a successful transition to
democracy.
The potential openness of the zone of peace identified by the DPT, and encour-
aged by a transnational web of democracy promoters, is premised, however, on
the domestic makeup of states corresponding to a specific liberal democratic
model, presented as the source of a pacifistic international order. This form of
inclusion through assimilation is matched by the drawing of stricter boundaries
between “peaceful” liberal democracies and “war prone” non-democracies. The
former inhabit an increasingly Kantian world, while the latter are left to fight it
out on a Hobbesian battleground. Fukuyama separates “post-historical states”
that have achieved liberal democracy from non-democratic states lagging behind,
“mired in history”. Central to this distinction is that in the “post-historical” world
peace exists, in comparison to the “historical” world where Realpolitik dominates
and force remains the “ultima ratio” in state relations.91 This demarcation between
a “zone of peace” and “zone of turmoil” is drawn explicitly by Singer and
Wildavsky in identifying the nature of the “real” post-Cold War environment,92
with Goldgeier and McFaul making a parallel distinction between the two worlds
of “core” and “periphery”.93 A similar divide also exists in John Rawls’ “law of
peoples”, which excludes those that are not liberal or “decent”. Citing work on
the DPT, Rawls suggests that “the absence of war between major established democ-
racies is as close as anything we know to a simple empirical reality in relations
among societies” and that this “underwrites the Law of Peoples as a realistic
utopia”.94 Without labouring the point, what needs to be emphasised is that in all
these influential accounts of the “real” world, the DPT plays an explicit role in sep-
arating “peaceful” liberal democracies from their “war prone” others.95 A zone of
peace exists within the civilised democratic core, but beyond lies threatening,
violent non-democratic barbarians. Between the two worlds there is a liberal refor-
mulation of the classically realist security dilemma, which now comes to exist
between democratic and non-democratic states.96 Once again we find ourselves
inhabiting a dualistic international order where toleration and coexistence are
90. George W. Bush, “Remarks by the President at the 20th Anniversary of the National Endow-
ment for Democracy”, 6 November 2003, available: ,http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/
2003/11/print/20031106-3.html. (accessed 25 November 2007).
91. Fukuyama, op. cit., ch. 26.
92. Max Singer and Aaron Wildavsky, The Real World Order: Zones of Peace, Zones of Turmoil (New
Jersey: Chatham House, 1993).
93. James M. Goldgeier and Michael McFaul, “A Tale of Two Worlds: Core and Periphery in the
Post-Cold War Era”, International Organization, Vol. 46, No. 2 (1992) pp. 467 –491.
94. John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (London: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 52–54.
95. Bowden, Expanding the Empire of Civilization, op. cit., ch. 7, runs a parallel argument about how
recent scholarship on different zones of peace and war replicate distinctions found in the classical stan-
dard. He does not, however, relate these distinctions to the DPT. The argument here, however, is that
the DPT plays a crucial role in defining and separating these zones.
96. Beate Jahn, “Kant, Mill, and Illiberal Legacies in International Affairs”, International Organiz-
ation, Vol. 59, No. 1 (2005) pp. 177–207.
“Democracy as Civilisation” 91
the norm within the liberal democratic zone of peace, while Realpolitik and
21st-century civilising missions mark dealings with the non-democratic zone of war.
With the DPT separating the world into “peaceful” democracies and “war prone”
non-democracies, there are obvious parallels and continuities with the previous
civilised/barbarian pairing.97 Indeed, “democracy” has come to embody many of
the meanings of “civilisation”—progress, telos and action. More generally, the
zone of peace, made up of democracies, is partially constituted through the nega-
tion of itself in the opposing zone of war. The world that the “peaceful” democra-
cies inhabit is a civilised one, temporally advanced and spatially separated from
the one that “violent” non-democracies find themselves in, with the latter’s “pro-
gress”, or lack thereof, understood in comparison to the standard upheld by the
former. Not only does this “two worlds” image unify the enemy/other but it also
confirms and reifies the identities of the liberal democratic states that make up
the zone of peace.98 Liberal democratic states are reassured of their “virtue” and
“democraticness” by displacing on to non-democracies the violence and discontent
that can threaten or undermine the democratic order from within. In much the
same way as states previously defined themselves as “civilised” in reference to a
“barbaric” other, the distinction drawn through the DPT helps to confirm the iden-
tities of these states as democratic. This becomes increasingly important when the
gap widens between the ideals of democracy and actual practices, a problem which
has grown considerably during the “war on terror”. Non-democracies, temporally
behind and spatially removed, come to represent and embody exactly what the vir-
tuous and peaceful democracies are not. In so doing, the existence of these non-
democracies also strengthens the bonds between liberal democracies by reassuring
them of their mutual “likeness”.99 These constitutive dimensions of the DPT are
ones that tend to be missed, with most proponents being quiet on fundamental
questions of identification and recognition that underlie their theory.
One of the greatest strengths of the DPT lies in its claims to objectivity, with
almost all studies being firmly based on rigorous social scientific methodology.100
From this perspective, the accounts of zones of peace and war that emerge are
merely corresponding to empirical realities. As Bowden astutely notes,
however, “on another level there is a normative side to the story that promotes
the West as the gatekeeper of liberal international order”.101 This is reflected in
the definitions of the key concepts of war, peace and democracy that underpin
the empirical results of the DPT.102 War is understood so narrowly as to exclude
important instances of aggression and violence by democracies. Conceiving of
peace, meanwhile, in relation to the absence of war removes from sight the struc-
tural violence caused by democracies in situations such as tough sanction regimes,
or, less obviously, in the harsh neoliberal economic reform packages imposed on
states transiting to democracy. Democracy, of course, is a highly contested
concept. In almost all studies on the democratic peace, however, this contestation
and mutability is removed, and democracy is defined in a very fixed and specific
manner. The understanding taken is liberal and procedural, tending to reflect a
certain configuration of American values, institutions and experiences.103
Representative is the definition provided in Russett’s influential study:
The core liberal democracies become exemplars of the model that “perpetual
peace” necessitates. Peace is bought at the price of difference. Liberal democracy
becomes the required condition, as this is the type of regime that offers a possible
end to interstate warfare. And who does not like peace?
The logic of the DPT is thus twofold. First, it creates and encourages a clear
separation between the two “worlds” inhabited by democracies and non-
democracies. The former are recognised as more legitimate due to their
supposedly peaceful behaviour, the latter are trapped in a cycle of war and vio-
lence, temporally and morally behind the civilised liberal democracies that have
progressed towards peaceful relations. History is used to highlight the failings
of non-democracies and to vindicate the “virtuousness” of democracies. At the
same stage, the division that emerges between the two “worlds” is not a fixed
or immutable one. Rather, the narrative told is distinctly teleological, with the
global expansion of democracy being accompanied by a gradual spread of more
peaceful interstate relations. This leads to the second point, namely that within
the DPT there lies a clear and persuasive invitation to expand the zone of peace
and civilisation. Through transiting to the model of democracy found in the zone
of peace, an escape route is offered from the zone of war. And if there is an unwill-
ingness or inability to make this move—which is most likely to be perceived as a
result of temporal backwardness—liberal democracies may be willing to speed
up history and bring democracy forcibly. Thus, in the DPT lie the seeds of a new
mission civilisatrice. With democratic peace scholars holding out the possibility
that a “preponderance of democracies will transform the entire system of inter-
national relations”,105 confident liberal democratic states are faced with the tempta-
tion of accelerating the arrival of a “perpetual peace” by actively bringing
civilisation to the uncivilised, democracy to the non-democratic. Seen in this
light, the war in Iraq is the clearest manifestation of a more basic logic of attempting
to extend the zone of peace through distinctly non-democratic means.106
103. Ido Oren, “The Subjectivity of the ‘Democratic’ Peace: Changing U.S. Perceptions of Imperial
Germany”, International Security, Vol. 20, No. 2 (1995). There is a considerable failure to recognise the
ethnocentricity of the definition of democracy taken. See also Miyume Tanji and Stephanie Lawson,
“‘Democratic Peace’ and ‘Asian Democracy’: A Universalist–Particularist Tension”, Alternatives,
Vol. 22, No. 1 (1997) pp. 133 –155.
104. Russett, op. cit., p. 14. Russett is referring to Dahl, op. cit.
105. Spencer Weart, Never at War: Why Democracies Will Not Fight One Another (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1998), p. 296.
106. One of the justifications for the coercive democratisation of Iraq was the possibility of its acting
as a trigger to bringing about a new wave of democratisation in the Middle East, and with it, the longer
“Democracy as Civilisation” 93
term possibility of peace and stability in the region. See Hobson, “A Forward Strategy of Freedom in the
Middle East”, op. cit., pp. 40–45.
107. Robert Ivie, “Democratizing for Peace”, Rhetoric and Public Affairs, Vol. 4, No. 2 (2001), p. 315.
108. Donald Rumsfeld “Remarks as Delivered by Secretary of Defense at National Defense Univer-
sity, Fort McNair, Washington, D.C.”, 31 January 2002, available: ,http://www.defenselink.mil/
speeches/2002/s20020131-secdef.html . (accessed 25 November 2007).
109. Michael Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs, Part 2”, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, Vol. 12, No. 4 (1983), pp. 323–337; Russett, op. cit., p. 136, idem, “Bushwhacking the Democratic
Peace”, International Studies Perspectives, Vol. 6, No. 4 (2005) pp. 395 –408; Weart, op. cit., ch. 15.
110. The inability of the DPT to deal with the means– ends dilemma it raises is considered in more
detail in Hobson, “The ‘Sorry Comforters’”, op. cit.
111. Russett, “Bushwhacking the Democratic Peace”, op. cit.
112. Doyle, op. cit.
113. Russett and Oneal, op. cit., p. 52.
114. Doyle, op. cit., p. 330; emphasis added.
94 C. Hobson
Conclusions
Democracy’s determining role in a new standard of civilisation means it cannot be
the completely progressive force it is regularly painted or presumed to be. Any
standard—democratic or otherwise—will be deeply implicated and infused
with power, hierarchy and varying degrees of violence. In so far as democracy
has become the defining feature of “what a state should look like and how it
should act”,118 it plays a particularly influential role in determining the makeup
of international society—deciding who is in and who is out, who lives in a
Kantian world of peace and who remains “mired in history”, who are “our” onto-
logical allies and who are “our” ontological enemies, who retains the rights to the
protection that sovereignty (supposedly) provides, and who may need to be
civilised or democratised in the name of peace and progress. These discourses
115. Harald Müller, “Kant’s Rogue State: The ‘Unjust Enemy’ and Liberal Missionarism in Inter-
national Affairs”, Paper presented at the ISA conference, March 2005, p. 4.
116. Ibid., pp. 4 –5.
117. Harald Müller, “The Antinomy of Democratic Peace”, International Politics, Vol. 44, No. 4 (2004)
pp. 494–520.
118. Roland Paris, “International Peacebuilding and the ‘Mission Civilisatrice’”, Review of Inter-
national Studies, Vol. 28, No. 4 (2002), p. 654.
“Democracy as Civilisation” 95