0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes) 61 views17 pagesEthics-Module Lesson7
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
Chapter 5
Aristotle and Virtue Ethics
Michael O. Orimaco
Learning Outcomes
At the end of this chapter, the students are expected to:
articulate the meaning and nature of virtue ethics; distinguish virtue
ethics from deontology and consequentialism; explain Aristotelian
virtue ethics or Eudaimonism as different from Ethics of Care and
Agent-based Theories; describe Aristotle’s ethical points, largely on
the concept of happiness, virtue, telos, and good habit; and use
Aristotelian ethical frameworks or principles to analyze moral
experiences.
Introduction
Virtue has become a compounding concept in ethics in the
modern times not only due to the Greek forefathers, namely,
Socrates, Plato and, more particularly, Aristotle, but also from its roots
in a more ancient Chinese philosophy of Confucius. However, the
Greeks overshadowed Confucius and dominated in the development
of Western moral philosophy until the Enlightenment era.
Subsequently, the formulation of Virtue Ethics is primarily grounded in
the Greeks tradition, which demonstrates theories essential for moral
development not only to the Westerners but also to the Easterners
(Orientals) and to the entire morally capacitated beings in the world.
Meaning of Virtue Ethics
Basically, virtue ethics is defined as an approach to ethics that
emphasizes the person’s character in moral thinking. This implies that
Tait or character is essential to the person’s achievement of the9g | GENERAL ETHICS
“good”. Hence, virtue ethics is not an action-based ethics (as in the
case of deontology and consequentialism), but a person-based one,
Thus, in any moral situations, virtue ethics does not provide the moral
agent specific principles to guide her actions. What virtue ethics
provides in attaining the good are simply ideal behaviors, traits, and
characters. That is why in Aristotelian ethics, with which most virtue
ethics theories drew inspiration, practical wisdom is a central category
that helps individuals become virtuous.
But to understand virtue ethics in general, we must first
qualify it as being composed of theories that, as mentioned above, lay
emphasis on the role that character and virtue play in moral
philosophy, rather than those which consider deliberate actions based
on duty or on anticipated good consequences. In other words, in
virtue ethics, there are no universal principles that oblige the person
to act because it is his duty to act or because the situation calls him to
render good consequence. Based on this contention, we can extract
two distinctive approaches in ethics, namely, deontological approach
and consequentialist approach. On the one hand, deontology or rule
based ethics, was popularized by Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) during
the Enlightenment era. The term deontology was derived from the
two Greek words deon, which means duty, and logos, which means ©
study or science. Hence, deontology is etymologically defined as the
study of duty. But it is usually understood as a kind of normative
theory with regard to what choices are morally required, forbidden, or
Serteet ene & Moore, 2012). Deontology, therefore,
eoisedaritaiea : ae and obligation to act morally.
Pierre pn fe other hand, holds that choices are to be
about (Ibid). As ae by the situation or consequences they bring
or ieBR rie Ftd as the definitive basis for the rightness
apeccinea ie ii lgment. Thus, this ethical doctrine believes that
What mite good outcome or consequences.
enrene raved jchlsditinet from the two approaches of
i logy and consequentialism, is that it
does not emphasi
action she has to ener (riral agent’s choice as to what course of
Practical moral develog Hence, virtue ethics emphasizes the person's
‘opment which is the key to the attainment ofARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 99
authentic happiness. For this reason, virtue ethics deals with broader
queries like: What kind of life should | live? What is the good life? How
can | be consistent in my moral actions? Indeed, these are some of the
ethical questions that we will be dealing in this chapter.
The Three Main Strands of Virtue Ethics
‘The “what” or gist of virtue ethics can be properly understood
through its three main strands, namely: Ethics of Care, Agent-Based
Theories and Eudaimonism. Firstly, the Ethies of Care holds the idea
that a moral action centers on social and environmental relationships
in which care or kindness is considered as the main virtue. It suggests
that “care” is a central category in determining the moral worth of
human actions. Michael Slote (1983: 36) corroborates this point by
stating that “caring is the primary virtue and that a morality based on
the motive of caring can offer a general account of right and wrong
action”. Hence, the motive in developing man’s moral practices in
which care is the primary virtue is clearly the main objective of the
ethics of care. In relation to this, according to Held (2006), the ethics
of care examines moral practices and values. It focuses on moral
development which is more possible through the reformation of
practices than the mere use of reason from any abstract rules. Thus,
this reformation of practices, which is to be nurtured and developed
into virtue, is the foremost emphasis of ethics of care. Secondly,
‘Agent-Based Theories are unitary normative theories. ‘This means that
the status of actions is entirely dependent upon the moral status of an
agent's motives and character traits. As Slote (2001: 38) writes:
‘A warm agent-based virtue ethics puts a fundamental
emphasis on a person's motives and, more particularly, on a person’s
overall morally relevant motivation. Say for example, an act is morally
acceptable if and only if it comes from good or virtuous motivation
involving benevolence or caring (about the well-being of others) or at
least doesn’t come from bad or inferior motivation involving malice or
indifference to humanity.100 | GENERAL ETHICS
Thus, again, in agent-based theory, an action is right if it
expresses a virtuous motive or at least does not exhibit a malicious
intention from the agent.
Finally, Eudaimonism comes from the Greek word
Eudaimonia, which can be translated as happiness, well-being or the
good life. For Aristotle, happiness or the good life is the highest goal of
man which can be achieved by a lifetime of actively exercising moral
virtues or “aréte” (a Greek word which precisely combined with
qualities, such as valor, to make up good character). And to enhance
moral virtue, according to Aristotle, we need phronesis or practical
wisdom, which can resolve any concurrent ethical problem. Indeed,
with moral virtue, human life would attain Eudaimonia, the happiness
which should be seen as a final end, and not as a subjective state
characterized by the seemingly well-lived life irrespective of the
emotional state of the person experiencing it. This will be further
discussed in the later section.
However, to speak of dissimilarities between Eudaimonism
against the first two main strands of virtue ethics is obvious. Say for
instance, the former comprises the entire development of a moral
person, that is, to become holistically good as she reaches to the point
of the ultimate end, while the two latter strands emphasize morally
800d action within the sphere of a certain circumstance or event.
Thus, Eudaimonism aims for eternal goodness rather than depending
on the contingent recurrence of certain actions. Furthermore, to
determine their resemblance is too apparent. As mentioned above,
bade ens a general does not particularly deal with the rightness of
mae jal als ene! Rather, with the aid of Peele
But because this cfaptantec the moral agent in seeking the “B0%" |
focuses chiefly on Aristotle's virtue ethics,
will only discuss the key 7 it
'y concepts ; Let me
develop them below, ‘pts of Aristotle’s moral teaching.
Aristotle's Virtue Ethics
Aristotle was born
Greece), in 384 BCE. Since
fondness for medical analogi
in Stagira, in Macedonia (now northern
his father was a doctor, he also has the
ies in the Ethics. He traveled to AthensARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 101
the age of seventeen where he became a student of Plato (Barlett &
Collins, 2011). As is well known, Athens was the center of learning in
the Greek world during this time. Aristotle remained for more or less
20 years at the Academy established by Plato. When Plato died in 347
BCE, Aristotle left Athens for thirteen years, during some of which he
was a tutor to Alexander the Great. In 334 BCE, Aristotle founded the
Lyceum in Athens and started giving lectures to audience who were
primarily youths.
Meanwhile, before his death in 322 BCE (Aristotle, 2004),
Aristotle gives lectures on ethics that centers on the concept of
Eudaimonia or happiness. His ethics was first written in Eudemian
Ethics which later developed into Nichomachean Ethics. Accordingly,
the latter work is believed to have been named in honor of Aristotle's
son, Nicomachus. In this particular book, Aristotle offers moral
principles of conduct that would guide humans in attaining the “good
life”.
To fully understand Aristotle's ethics, we must take into
consideration the notions of virtue, telos and good habit in relation to
happiness because these concepts will help render the true nature of
Aristotle’s notion of happiness or Eudaimonia, That is why, in this
section, these concepts are profoundly explicated. Let me start with
the notion of happiness.
On Happiness
As is well known, Socrates understands virtue as the major
source of happiness. Plato continued this tradition and argued that
moral virtue is vital to the rational soul of man. Aristotle followed
Socrates and Plato’s agenda, but according to Crisp, Aristotle's
concept of happiness differs from Socrates and Plato's happiness for
Aristotle’s concept of happiness consists only in virtuous activity
(Aristotle, 2004). Happiness, which most of Aristotle’s interpreters call
Eudaimonia, is the ultimate goal/end of human life. This happiness or
the ultimate end is genuinely desired for its own sake or without
qualification. So, actions which precede this end become the most
valuable and cannot be superseded by any actions driven by ordinary
kinds of ends. As Lear (2004: 20) corroborates, “to choose for actions102 | GENERAL ETHICS
which result in honor, wealth and power is definitely part of man’s
inclination to seek for happiness (as pleasure), but unfortunately this
could not be the end which offers true happiness.”
Like Eudaimonia, pleasure is also good. That is why Aristotle
does not condemn man for desiring pleasure because it is a significant
part in human flourishing. But for Aristotle, the desire and actions that
ead to pleasure only presuppose limited value since its end is
temporary. Hence, the satisfaction that one gets from these actions
cannot be truly called happiness. For Aristotle, these actions, which
only lead humans into the pit of the two opposing vices (either excess
or deficiency), drive them away from the ultimate end. Hence, for
Aristotle, only virtuous acts can lead man toward living the good life or
happiness.
This is indeed the central concept in Aristotle’s virtue ethics:
virtue or the mean is the key to happiness. And by the word “mean”,
we mean that which settles at the middle ground. Please see below
Aristotle’s Table of Virtues and Vices. Meantime, let me briefly discuss
Aristotle’s concept of virtue. M
The Concept of Virtue
Virtue is defined as a behavior showing high moral standards
- ee Quality of goodness in a person. An example to this is
fhe nee cicled or truthfulness. Following Aristotle, the
wee BS the eo, 2nd ed. (2006: 678) categorically describes
mee Gee ite of vice. Vice in this context should not be
Sica within the specific context of social vices, like drug
according to Aree mete. Smoking, and gambling. Rather,
8 Aristotle, vices, whe ‘the twa “eotrames of HEARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 103
of man’s proper or moral behavior. The table below helps us
understand the relation between virtue and vices in the Aristotelian
sense.
TABLE OF ARISTOTLE'S VIRTUES AND VICES
[Fear and
\Confidence
IRashness \courage \Cowardice
[Licentiousness/
Kettinduigence _|emperance _|insensbility
Pleasure and Pain
(Getting and = ‘ iliberality/
spending (minor) _|[Prodteality sberatty’ IMeanness
(Getting and ulgarity/ Pettiness/
Ispending (major) _||Tastelessness [Magnificence |icsinginess
Honor and i ha
Dishonor (major) _|N2nity IMagnanimity _|[Pusillanimity
lHonor and fambition/empty |[Proper (Unambitiousness/
[Dishonor (minor) _||vanity lambition/pride |lundue humility
‘ [Patience/Good ||Lack of spirit/
[Anger frascibility ltemper lunirascibility
[Understatement/
self-expression _|[Boastfulness_jfruthfulness | modesty
[Conversation Buffoonery ittiness _|[Boorishness
[cial Conduct _|[Obsequiousness |[Friendliness _||Cantankerousness
[shame Shyness iModesty [Shamelessness
[Malicious
Righteous "
indignation Em 4 lenjoyment/
I A indignation pitefulness
Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle: The ‘Nicomachean Ethics Revised
Edition, trans. J. K. Thomson (New York: Viking, 1995), 104.
For Aristotle, as we can see above, there are two kinds of
Virtues, namely, intellectual virtue and moral virtue. On the one hand,104 | GENERAL ETHICS
intellectual virtue corresponds to the act of thinking which affirms or
negates something. On the other hand, moral virtue signifies the act
of choosing which actions to pursue or avoid. For Aristotle, intellectual
virtue involves two stages, namely, the contemplative stage and
practical stage. According to Aristotle, the contemplative stage is
neither practical nor productive because it is purely intellectual in
nature. Aristotle argues that it is in this stage that the categorization
of the good as truth and the bad as falsity occurs. Interestingly,
Aristotle claims that the practical intellect already possessed the truth,
In intellectual as practical, according to Aristotle, the truth or the
understanding of the good which is in agreement with the right desire
is already obtained (Aristotle, 2009). In this stage, intellectual virtue is
accomplished because, here, the moral agent’s determination for the
virtues or the mean adheres with the desire for right and truth.
Therefore, the accomplishment of intellectual virtue can be done
through the possession of “practical wisdom”.
In contrast to intellectual virtue, moral virtue emphasizes the
role of the will in choosing the good and right actions. As is well
known, moral virtue is always inclined toward the correct conduct.
This kind of virtue, according to Aristotle, is the actualization of
practical intellect whereby the agent has a disposition to behave in the
right manner or to act according to the mean between extremes of
deficiency and excess. However, with deliberate desire and habitual
choice for the good and truth, moral virtue can be a constant practice
of a rational acting agent.
According to Aristotle, the capacity of the human person to
Possess intellectual and moral virtues is what makes him
distinguishable from the lower forms of animals. Though animals are
eee pe Perception, they do not have, according to Aristotle, the
aad 2 ; ect and will. For this reason, animals anne
Aston ee pore es right action which is based on truth a
state of chores er dins to Aristotle (2009), since a moral virtue is
or character that is concerned with choosing the good and the
right, then both the act of reasoni Gel dst Be
true and right. soning and deliberate desire 1mARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 105
Telos or the Ultimate End
Literally, the Greek word telos is translated as “result” or
“end”. Its verb form teleo means “to come to an end,” as for the death
of an individual. Based on this literal meaning of telos, Aristotle
conveys two distinct notions of end, namely: telos as ordinary ends,
which is also composed of hierarchy (lower and higher ends), and telos
as the ultimate achievement of human being or the final end. On the
one hand, ordinary ends signify a goal wherein accomplishments are
simply viewed as byproducts of human beings’ common desire. This
goal is the stopping point or the “last thing” (Lear, 2004: 11), but it is
not really the final or the ultimate one. Since it is ordinary, it entails
only temporary fulfilment from one’s experience of an apparent good.
Yet, we can assert that, at this juncture, telos is indeed the point of
completion of an activity that an individual wishes to achieve because
of the foreseen apparent good. Consider these two examples as
guides. Mario decides to play basketball. Most likely, he wants to
solely experience pleasure by playing the game itself or by winning it
(if he will actually win), or to maintain a healthy body, or something
else which prompts and motivates him to play the game. However,
when he is about to play basketball, he remembers that he has an
appointment with his thesis adviser on the same time. Consequently,
he cancels the game and proceeds immediately to his adviser. In
relative manner, Maria studies hard all the lessons in school because
she wants to earn higher grades in all her subjects so that, later, she
might become a scholar. If we examine tightly these examples, both
demonstrate ends which correspond to the desired good. So ‘in this
context, Lear (2004: 15) states that every human person Is directed
toward a goal or end which is good because such good is, most of all,
the desired end, As we can see, the end (telos) of the actions in these
examples is simply viewed as an ordinary end towards an ordinary
Bood.
Nonetheless, the first example above implies that nereett
actually a hierarchy of ends. As Aristotle (Phys. 3 195a23-25), wit
“and then there is the end and the good of the other things: nt -
the sake of which will be the best and the end of the other supe lp
the first example, Mario opted to see his thesis advisor rather106 | GENERAL ETHICS
play basketball. For sure, choosing to play basketball is a lower end,
while choosing to see the advisor is a higher end, which other higher
ends are possibly attached, e.g. to finish his thesis and pass the
subject. In addition to the idea of hierarchy of ends, we may also talk
about a series of ends. This statement is clearly manifested in the
second example above, whereby higher end determines the extent to
which lower end is worth pursuing. Thus, Maria’s desires for higher
grades in order to achieve an honorable reward during the graduation
ceremony becomes a springboard for another higher ends, such as
landing on a good job in the future. As we can see, in these series of
ends, there is this pattern of relations between lower and higher ends,
which is also applicable to other modes of action which involves
desirable results,
Now, what we can infer from the discussion on the series of
ends is that the hierarchies cannot go on ad infinitum (toward infinity).
For Aristotle, there must be an apex of the hierarchy which is also
known as the ultimate end or the highest good. This is because, for
Aristotle (2004: 20), without a final resting point, “our desire (orexis)
would be empty and vain”. This is means that without the highest
Bood as the ultimate end, there would be no reason for a rational
being to act morally. And again, for Aristotle, the highest good as the
ultimate end of moral actions is “happiness” without qualification.
Allow me to develop Aristotle’s concept of happiness below so we
‘may be able to understand it fully. This is important because, as We
already know, happiness is the focal Point of Aristotle's virtue ethics.
Moral Virtue as Good Habit
The formation of a i it is it id
_ moral virtue or good habit is indee
essential to Aristotelian ett ‘
hics. This is due to the fact that a moral
Seige SE in happiness by being consistently living a good life
‘tually in accordance to the habit is
i 800d. Thus, a good hal
in
Katee: to the development of virtue because itis considered t0
1003a) writes a eattern for doing virtuous actions, Aristotle (NE II,
are made perfert adapted by nature to receive these virtues and
Perfect by habit”. in this sense, though virtue is already partARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 107
of our natural inclination, human being still needs the habit of doing
good for him to become virtuous. What we must do then is to
constantly practice doing virtuous acts in order to develop a habit. For
instance, we acquire the virtue of patience by repeatedly integrating it
into our deliberate actions, or by being constantly patient. In similar
way, we can obtain the virtue of courage by maintaining it within the
purview of the mean while avoiding rashness and cowardice.
Therefore, our actions can only be morally good and right if there is a
habitual practice of virtues. This is to say that to eventually maintain
these moral actions which lead us to attain authentic happiness, the
formation of good habits is a requisite.
Moreover, the formation of virtue or good habit has two
stages: first, the habit of contemplation or the education of thought
for the formation of intellectual virtue and, second, the habit of the
actual practice of moral virtue. On the one hand, the habit of
contemplation is a matter of constantly acquiring knowledge and
using one's mind in the right way that leads to the habitual exercise of
virtue (Aristotle: 2004). Through the habit of education of thought, the
state of character is constituted by the stable equilibrium of the soul
(NE Il:1, 1003a). This is to say that the state of character which shapes
moral virtue primarily requires proper mental activity aside from the
actual performance of moral action. In other words, before we can
actually practice virtue, we have to think about practicing virtue all the
time; or, to put it in a Heideggerian jargon, we need to attune
ourselves (our consciousness) to virtue all the time. On the other
hand, the habitual actual practice of virtue presupposes that every
human being has brought out the contemplated understanding of
virtue into actions. In other words, we put into practice what the mind
thinks. In addition, the putting into practice of this understanding
should be done consistently so that it would lead to the formation of
800d habit, True enough, virtue is defined as a behavior showing high
Moral standards, or a good moral quality, or the general quality of
goodness in a person. But for Aristotle, we should push this further by
developing a habit of doing the good all the time.
Therefore, the process by which a state of character and
moral virtues are formed is just similar to the process of habit-
formation. Let’s take the case of walking. Learning to walk is an108 | GENERAL ETHICS
activity characterized by choice; it is not automatically accomplished
once a certain level of physical development has been attained
Children learn to walk by actually practicing the act of walking-by
standing, taking a few steps, falling down, and then repeating the
whole process over and over again until the action becomes second
nature and can be done with ease. In this analogy, a repeated
performance of the action is necessary in order for the child to learn
how to walk, whether she ends up learning to walk well or badly, In
like manner, the habituation of virtue necessitates the deliberate
repetition of doing virtuous action consistently to increase the degree
of moral virtues until perfection is attained.
Conclusion
As we can see, to understand Aristotle’s ethics in general, we
have to begin with knowing virtue as the key toward man’s authentic
happiness. Virtue, which is a state of character that is concerned with
choosing the good and the right, is the only requirement for
happiness. Happiness is the ultimate end of rational being that is not
to be confused with pleasure in the ordinary ends. As the final telos, it
is the end for the sake of itself, without any qualifications. So, man
cannot just aim for pleasure alone since it only leads us toward an
infinite chain of ends. There should be a final resting point of the
aeary of ends. For Aristotle, this is the ultimate end or the highest
good.
Virtue ethics then centers on the moral character of the
person carrying out an action. In other words, virtue ethics is person
ae, i” contrast to actions which are based on duties and rules of
Seas and the consequences of particular actions of
oe en ‘olism. In fact, the three main strands of virtue ethics
ia z fore, Ment Based Ethics, and Eudaimonism) mous
Rewevse enor tee in the achievement of the “g00 *
p mdiffers from the Ethics of Care and Age”ARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 109
Moreover, since virtue ethics focuses on the inherent
character of a person, its concern therefore is the whole person,
rather than the particular events or actions. Its method recognizes the
agent's habits and behaviors that will allow her to achieve
“Eudaimonia,” or a good life. This is to say that good life can only be
attained if the person possesses and completely practice these virtues.
‘As James Keenan (1995) puts it: “Being virtuous is more than having a
particular habit of acting, e.g. generosity. Rather, it means having a
fundamental set of related virtues that enable a person to live and act
morally well.” Therefore, with the fundamental necessity of practical
wisdom, a lifetime practice of these virtues leads to true happiness.
Finally, virtue ethics also fundamentally includes an account of
the purpose or meaning of a human life, In Aristotelian sense, human
flourishing or happiness is man’s purpose or goal. But Aristotle did not
condemn man for desiring pleasure as an ordinary end because it is a
significant part in human flourishing. What he emphasizes is that
ordinary ends cannot sustain authentic happiness. Pleasure as an
ordinary end is only tantamount to an apparent good whose quality is
only temporary. In contrast to pleasure, true happiness is a state
wherein man experiences the highest good. So, this noteworthy
experience, for Aristotle, is supposedly the ultimate or final end of
man.ARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 111.
Chapter Exercise
Note: Limit your answers to ten (10) sentences only.
i, In your own words, what characterizes virtue ethics in
general?
2. What are the different strands of virtue ethics? Kindly
explain briefly each strand.
3. How do you distinguish virtue ethics from deontological and
consequentialist ethics?112 | GENERAL ETHICS
4. Make a brief descriptive explanation on Aristotle's virtue as
the mean.
5. How relevant are intellectual and moral virtues to the final
end or Eudaimonia?ARISTOTLE AND VIRTUE ETHICS | 113
How does Aristotle consider the formation of virtue as good
habit?
Distinguish ordinary ends from Eudaimonia or the
ultimate telos. Explain your answer.114 | GENERAL ETHICS
8. — Formulate a critique on Aristotle's virtue ethics.
9. Establish your own moral principle(s) as a consequence of
your criticism on Aristotle. Say what is it and explain why?