0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes) 145 views349 pagesDodge - Foundations of Algebra and Analysis
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
To my very own “Grandmother” :
Helena Peirce
© Copyright 1969 by Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, Incorporated,
53 State Street, Boston, Massachusetts, 02109.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be
reproduced in any form, by mimeograph or any other means,
without permission in writing from the publishers.
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 69-13516
Printed in the United States of America
SBN 87150-048-7
SECOND PrintING: August 1970preface
This text is designed to give the student a background in the foundations
of algebra and analysis. The algebra of symbolic logic and the concept of set
are introduced early in the text so that the main definitional development of
the complex number system flows easily from a set of postulates for the
natural numbers. Important concepts are introduced when needed to provide
better motivation through immediate usage. Thus, the approach is integrated
for a greater continuity of ideas than would be possible if a course in sets were
followed by a course in the number systems.
A preliminary edition of the text was class-tested in a two-course sequence
of two semester-hours each at the University of Maine. It was taught, pri-
marily, to freshman and sophomore students who intended to.major in or
to teach mathematics. This sequence provided a total of sixty class sessions,
or about one fifty-minute class period for each section of the text. There was
more than enough material for such use, but most topics were covered in the
allotted time.
At least ten exercises at the end of each section, providing a total of more
than 1100 exercises, allow the student ample opportunity to reinforce the
ideas presented in the text. The exercises develop concurrently with the text
and thus are not always listed in order of increasing difficulty.
Attention is called to the Table of Symbols and Notations, the Hints for
Selected Exercises, and the Answers for Selected Exercises. Other items of
constant reference are the tautologies of Theorem 3.4, the postulates for the
natural numbers in Definition 22.1, and the field postulates of Definition
43.1. Such often-used pages might well be indexed with paper clips.
In the hints and answers sections one will find hints for the solutions of
approximately one-fifth of the exercises, and answers for about half of the
exercises—generally the odd-numbered ones—and for the alternate parts of
vvi PREFACE
most multi-part exercises. An Instructor’s Manual is available from the pub-
lisher at no cost to teachers using this text. It includes answers to most of the
other exercises, supplementary questions, and suggestions for the use of this
book.
If the reader enjoys the historical sketches located in unnumbered
sections at the beginning of each chapter, he should also enjoy such books as
E. T. Bell’s Men of Mathematics and H. Eves’ An Introduction to the History
of Mathematics.
The following copyrighted material has been used with the kind per-
mission of the publishers. How to Solve It by G. Polya (Princeton University
Press, Princeton, N.J., 1945) provides the basis for Section 8. The selections
from Alice in Wonderland by Lewis Carroll at the beginning of each of
Chapters 2 through 7 and 9 are from The Annotated Alice with notes by
M. Gardner (Clarkson N. Potter, Inc., New York, 1960). The material on a
high school for mathematics immediately preceding Chapter 8 is enlarged
from a letter by Lewis Carroll found on pages 201 and 202 of A Scrap-Book
of Elementary Mathematics, 4th ed., by W. F. White (The Open Court
Publishing Company, La Salle, Ill., 1942). A listing of these and other
source books is found in the Bibliography.
The kind help and encouragement from my wife, Donna, and from many
friends at the University of Maine are deeply appreciated. Many errors and
oversights have been rectified through the suggestions of my colleagues
George S. Cunningham, John J. Dranchak, Howard W. Eves, Charles A.
Green, the late Spofford H. Kimball, Frank J. Mestecky, Peter G. Sawtelle,
William F. Stearns, John W. Toole, and others. My thanks are also extended
to the publishers, especially to Paul E. Prindle and Bruce B. Thrasher for
their most patient and efficient production of this work, the first in a series of
texts in this general subject area.
CLayTon W, DopGE
Orono, Mainecontents
PREFACE, 0
TABLE OF SYMBOLS AND NOTATIONS, Xi
1 LOGIC
Thales, 1
1. Introduction, 3
2. Statements and Connectives, 5
3, Tautologies, Absurdities, and Contingencies, 0
4. The Mathematics of Logic, /4
5. Quantifiers, /9
6. The Logic of Mathematics, 24
7. A Simple Logical Discourse, 29
8. Proof, 34
2 SETS
Pythagoras, 43
9. Sets and Subsets, 45
10, Union and Intersection, 57
11. Some Basic Properties, 53
12. Complement, 56
13. Power Set, 59
14. Relations, 62
15. Equivalence Relations, 66
16. Functions, 7/
17. Operations, 75
viiCONTENTS
BOOLEAN ALGEBRA
18.
19.
20.
Archimedes, 83
Boolean Algebra, 85
Logic, 91
Switching Circuits, 93
NATURAL NUMBERS
21.
22.
23.
24,
25.
26.
27.
28.
29,
30.
31.
End of the Greek Era, 103
Motivation, /05
The Natural Numbers, 1/0
Order, 115
Subtraction and Division, 118
Mathematical Induction, 122
Exponents and Inequalities, 128
Two More Principles, 132
An Independent Postulate Set, 134
The Peano Postulates, /39
Cardinal Numbers and Addition, 142
Cardinal Numbers and Multiplication, /47
INTEGERS
32.
33.
34,
35.
36.
37.
Fibonacci, 151
Ordered Pairs, 153
Basic Properties, 158
Inequality, 163
Absolute Value, 165
Mathematical Induction, 169
The Integers, 173
RATIONAL NUMBERS
38.
39,
40.
4l.
42.
43.
44,
45,
Newton, 177
Ordéred Pairs, 179
Identities, 182
Subtraction and Division, 184
Inequality, 186
Miscellaneous Properties, 190
The Field, 194
Modular Arithmetic, 198
Rings and Integral Domains, 204CONTENTS = ix
a) REAL NUMBERS
Gauss, 211
46. Sequences and Limits, 2/2
47. Cauchy Sequences, 220
48. Equivalence, Addition, Multiplication, 224
49. Basic Properties, 227 ;
50. Order, 230
51. Completeness, 233
52. Real Numbers, 236
53. Dedekind Cuts, 241
8 COMPLEX NUMBERS
Cauchy, 247
54. Ordered Pairs, 249
55. The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra, 253
9 INFINITY AND BEYOND
Weierstrass, 259
56. Infinity, 261
57. Beyond Infinity, 265
58. Cardinal Arithmetic, 277
59. The March of the Ordinals, 273
60. Three Paradoxes, 276
61. Two Axioms, 279
APPENDICES
Umbugio, 283
Proof of a Completeness Theorem, 285
Synthetic Division, 286
Proofs of Some Set Theorems, 291
pOP>
Hints FOR SELECTED EXERCISES, 295
ANSWERS FOR SELECTED EXERCISES, 303
BrBuioGRAPHY, 335
INDEX, 339table of symbols
and notations
These symbols are defined on the pages indicated.
[ye
(x)
&
anoguec
}
{| ph, {5 ph
@,{ }
u
in
es eee
(ae |
negation, 6
and, 6
or, 6
implies, 7
equivalence, 7
if and only if, 7
Sheffer’s stroke, 14
therefore, 15
open sentence, 19
for all, for every, 20
there exists, 20
such that, 20
end of proof, 30
is an element of, 45
set, 45
equals, 46
set builder, 46
null or empty set, 47
universe, 48
subset, precedes, 48, 89, 240,
pi, 50
intersection, cap, 51, 85, 240
union, cup, 57, 85, 240
xixii TABLE OF SYMBOLS AND NOTATIONS
BA, A’, ~A, (A)
HA)
(a, 6)
AxB
eee
+1
P(r)
a
nt
Sa
HS)
vd
E(a, b)
—x, %
complement, 56
power set, 59
ordered pair, 62, 154
Cartesian product, 63
domain, 65
range, 65
relation properties, 67
equivalence relation, 68, 142
equivalence class, 68
partition, 69
function, 7/
one-to-one, 72
inverse, 72, 185, 194, 228, 238
identity map, 75
binary operations, 75, 78
Boolean identities, 85
inverse, 86
addition and multiplication, 105, 107, 110, 139,
140, 143, 147, 155, 156, 173, 180, 181, 194, 201,
204, 205, 209, 225, 238, 242, 244, 250, 274, 275
natural numbers, 110, 139
one, 110, 139, 174, 183, 194, 205, 227, 238
inequality, 115, 116, 163, 164, 187, 231, 267
subtraction, 118, 161, 184, 221, 227
division, 119, 161, 185, 229
divides, 120
proposition, 122
exponents, 128
factorial, 132
Fibonacci number, 133, 173
successor, 139
cardinal number, 142
integers, 154, 156, 173
equivalence, congruence, 154, 179, 199, 207, 224
integer, 156
zero, 159, 174, 183, 194, 205, 226, 238
negative, 160, 174, 184, 194, 205, 227, 238, 243TABLE OF SYMBOLS AND NOTATIONS
|x| absolute value, 65, 232
Jt positive integers, 174
[a, 5] ordered pair of integers, 179
R’,R rational numbers, 179, 180
Ela, 6}, a/b rational number, 180, 183
F field, 194
{a] residue class, 199
i 7 matrix, 205
(a/b) quotient, 207
Uh f sequence, 2/4
lim limit, 214, 234
e epsilon, 214
max maximum, 2/6
min minimum, 2/6
P.(n) polynomial, 217
E', EE real numbers, 224, 225, 238, 241
vl real number, 225
ft reciprocal sequence, 228
Fy {FndD sequence of real numbers, 233
lub least upper bound, 236
glb greatest lower bound, 236
A Dedekind cut, 241
Zz zero cut, 243
E, complex numbers, 250
(a; 6) ordered pair of real numbers, 250
i imaginary unit, 257
x aleph, 26]
d #(N), 261
LH unit intervals, 266, 269
c #(E:), 267
ST, Sym powers, 268
= similarity, 273
A) order type, 273
A* reversed order, 274
« O(N), 274
a ordinal number, 277x oe A -
Some things are not what they seem to be.l logic
THALES
Any study is more meaningful and interesting when one is acquainted
with those who developed its concepts. Mathematics is no exception. The
makers of mathematics are people with people’s weaknesses and strengths.
By some stroke of fate they saw beyond the limits set by their predecessors.
Many looked from lofty heights, others from the depths of despair and con-
fusion. Some led exemplary lives, while others were reprobates. All were
blessed with a spark of genius and the opportunity to use their talents. But
above all, they were human.
It seems fitting to use the first page or two in each chapter to recount
selected incidents from the lives of these mental giants. Thus the reader should
gain an appreciation of the human side of some of those responsible for the
mathematics he is studying.
The mathematics of ancient times was quite mystical and empirical. For
example, the ancient Egyptians knew that a triangle having sides of length
3, 4, and 5 is a right triangle, but why this is true, and how it should be
established as true, were not known until about 600 B.c. The ancients were
of a practical bent and not at all concerned with theory. Much of mathe-
matics is still taught from that same point of view.
Deductive reasoning first appeared in-ancient Greece about 600 B.c.
Thales of Miletus, a merchant, traveled extensively throughout the Medi-
terranean region, learning much of the mathematics and mysticism of Egypt
and elsewhere. He appears to have been the first to attempt a proof of any
sort. He is credited with discovering that vertical angles formed by inter-
secting lines are equal, that the base angles of an isosceles triangle are
equal, and other similar geometric facts. Furthermore, his discoveries were
12 cH.1 Logic
supported by some sort of deductive reasoning. Here we find the very
beginnings of modern ideas in mathematics.
Little is known of Thales’ life, but some interesting tales are related
concerning the personality of this famous merchant, statesman, philosopher,
mathematician, and astronomer, one of the “seven wise men” of antiquity.
Thales is reported to have owned a salt mine, which was located on a moun-
tain, and used a train of mules to bring the salt to market. It is said that while
crossing a stream on the way down the mountain, one of the mules accidentally
stumbled, and by the time he had regained his footing, much of the salt had
dissolved, lightening his load considerably. It was a long trip, so the mule had
a long time to consider just why he had a lighter burden than usual. Remem-
bering the incident, this clever beast began wallowing in the stream on each
A diameter of a circle
bisects the circle.
downhill trip. Now, in an attempt to remedy this situation, most of us would
probably beat the animal unmercifully the instant he started to wallow in the
stream. But not Thales. He would not stoop to using such a method. He
merely gave the mule another long trip to remember by loading him with
sponges instead of salt. The cure was immediate.
On another occasion Thales demonstrated to a friend how easy it wasINTRODUCTION SEC. 1 3
to get rich. One spring, he quietly purchased all the oil presses in the region.
‘When the fall olive crop was harvested, he realized a fortune renting his presses
at high rates.
One night when he tripped and fell into a ditch while watching the stars,
an old lady standing nearby asked him how he could possibly see anything
in the sky when he could not even see what was at his own feet. When asked
what was the strangest sight he ever saw, he replied, “An aged tyrant.” To
lead better lives, Thales advised people to “refrain from doing what we
blame in others.”
1 | INTRODUCTION
Mathematics deals largely with numbers: natural numbers, integers,
rational numbers, real numbers, complex numbers, and many others. It is
important, therefore, for the earnest student of mathematics to understand
the basic structure of our complex number system.
Consider the following questions:
(1) Is 5 > —172 Why?
(2) Is|—al = a? Always?
(3) Since 3 + 27 # 2 + 3%, where /? = —I, is 3 + 2i < 2 + 3ioris
34+ 2i>24 3:7
(4) Is there just one infinity? What is infinity?
(5) Is there a smallest positive real number? If so, what is it?
(6) Assuming that the null set @ is the set having no elements, and
that set A is contained in set B, A © B, if and only if every element in A is also
in B, how can one prove that # < A for every set A?
(1) Why does (—a)(—6) = +ab?
(8) Suppose the statement “if it is raining, then the ground is wet” is
true. Suppose also that it is not raining. Can one logically conclude that the
ground is not wet?
(9) Is the statement “no books on this shelf are blue” equivalent to
the statement “‘it is false that all books on this shelf are blue”’?
(10) Remembering that complex roots of polynomial equations come in
conjugate pairs x = a + bi, why does the polynomial equation x — 2 —3i
0 have only x = 2 + 3as a root and not x = 2 — 3 also?
These are but a few of the basic questions which this book attempts to
answer. These questions concerning sets, logic, and numbers, while quite
elementary, are certainly not easy to answer. Many times, the most basic
concepts require the most careful examination.4 cH.1 Locic
The complex number system is approached with the goal of under-
standing its foundations. First the natural numbers 1, 2, 3,... are discussed,
then the integers are built up from them, then the rational numbers, the real
numbers, and finally the complex numbers. To give a better understanding
of how these systems are logically structured, we develop set notation and
study elementary logic prior to examining these number systems.
After completing this course, the student should have a better apprecia-
tion of the logical foundations of mathematics in general and of the number
systems of mathematics in particular. Thus he will be much better able to
comprehend the subtleties of more advanced mathematical studies.
EXERCISES
I-1 through 1-10. Answer the questions (1) through (10) posed in this
section. Give examples where possible. Prove your answers.
Your intuition should not be trusted in mathematics. Many times your
‘first impression is incorrect. Answer quickly each of the questions or problems
in Exercises 1-11 to 1-26, then work out each correct solution.
1-11. Do they have a fourth of July in England?
1-12. A car drives 27 miles at 40 m.p.h., then 27 miles at 60 m.p.h.
What is its average speed?
1-13. A car drives 27 min at 40 m.p.h., then 27 min at 60 m.p.h. What
is its average speed?
1-14, Guess how many letters are in this “sentence.”
1-15. A large clock takes 30 sec to strike six. How long will it take to
strike twelve?
1-16. Would you consider working 30 days at a job paying | cent the
first day, 2 cents the second day, 4 cents the third day, 8 cents the fourth day,
and so forth?
1-17. By what percentage does #; exceed 345?
1-18. If a ball of yarn 3 in. in diameter costs 30 cents, how much
should a ball of yarn 5 in. in diameter cost?
1-19, If A can do a job in 3 days and B can do it in 5 days, how long
will it take them together to do the job?
1-20. One glass contains some milk and another glass some hot choco-
late. A teaspoonful of hot chocolate is taken from the second glass and put
in the first. Then a teaspoonful of the mixture is taken from the first and
returned to the second. Which glass now contains more of the other liquid?
1-21. A plane leaves Boston flying at 250 m.p.h. Fifteen minutes later
a plane leaves Bangor, Maine, 200 air miles away, flying at 150 m.p.h. When
they meet, which one is farther from Boston?STATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES SEC.2 5
1-22. Is the statement “this statement is false” true or is it false?
1-23. Why cannot a man living in the United States be buried in
Canada?
1-24. Is it legal for a man to marry his widow's sister?
1-25. From the bottom of a 30-ft well, a frog can climb up 3 ft each day,
sliding back 2 ft each night. In how many days does he escape the well?
1-26. You wish a long night’s sleep, so at 8 P.M. you set your alarm for
9.4m. How much sleep does this permit?
2 | STATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES
Under what circumstances is the statement
“x? — 2x =0 or x? + 2x = 0"
true? In particular, is it true for x = 0? Again, consider the statement
“if it is raining, then the ground is wet.”
Is this statement true if the ground is wet, but it is not raining (as when a
sprinkler is on)? To find the mathematician’s answer to these and related
questions, we now turn our attention to the study of symbolic logic.
2.1 DEFINITION. By a statement, or a proposition, is meant a
sentence which is either true or false, but not both. Statements are generally
denoted by lower case letters p,q, r,....
Some examples of statements are:
(1) Today is hot.
(2) Today is Friday
(3) 2 is a prime number. (True)
(4) 5+ 5 = 12, (False)
(5) George Washington is the current president of the United States
of America. (False)
The following are not statements:
(6) Are you listening?
(7) The whipplecork is plockled in the aardvinch.
(8) Wow, what a day!
) xisay.
(10) This statement is false.6 cH.1 Loaic
A statement ends in a period, not a question mark or an exclamation point.
Thus (6) and (8) are not statements. Because (7) makes no sense, it cannot
be true or false. Similarly (9) is not a statement, even though it has the proper
‘form, until the variables x and y are replaced by meaningful terms.
Sentence (10) is deceiving; it looks like a statement. If it is a proposition,
then it is either true or false, but not both. Suppose it is true. Then what it
says is true, and it is false. But it cannot be both true and false. Hence (10)
cannot be true. Well, suppose (10) is false. Then what it says is false, and
(10) is not false, it is true. Again, it cannot be both true and false. Therefore,
(10) cannot be classified as either true or false. Hence it is not a statement.
Various ways exist for obtaining new statements from old ones. A few
of them are considered here.
2.2. DEFINITION. The statement p’, read “not-p” and called the
negation of statement p, is defined to be the denial of statement p. That is,
p’ is false if p is true, and p’ is true if p is false.
We use truth tables to illustrate the truth values of statements, where
T stands for “true” and F for “false.” Thus we have the truth table for
negation in Fig. 2.1. This table simply restates that p’ is false when p is true,
and p' is true when p is false. Since it gives a picture of the truth values for
negation, the truth table may be more easily remembered than the verbal
definition.
P P
ae aoe
F T
Figure 2.1. Negation.
Any proposition symbolized by a single letter is called a primitive propo-
sition. Connectives are logical symbols between (or connecting) two state-
ments to form a new statement, called a compound statement. We define four
such connectives:
2.3 DEFINITION. The proposition p A q, read “‘p and q” and called
the conjunction of p and q, is true when both p and q are true and is false
otherwise.
2.4 DEFINITION. The proposition p v g, read “p or g” and called
the disjunction of p and q, is false when both p and q are false and is true
otherwise.STATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES SEC.2 7
2.5 DEFINITION. The proposition p —> q, read “p implies q” or “if
p, then q” and called an implication or conditional, is false when p is true and
q is false, and is true otherwise.
2.6 DEFINITION. The proposition p<>4, read “‘p if and only if q”
and called an equivalence ot biconditional, is true if and only if both p and q
are true or both are false. We also write iff to mean “if and only if.”
Truth tables for these four connectives appear in Fig. 2.2.
Ficure 2.2. Logical connectives.
The meaning of each connective should be explained further. Conjunc-
tion has the usual meaning given “and,” except that the two statements need
not be related. Thus we state
2 42 =4and January is a month
as being a true conjunction.
Disjunction is used logically in the inclusive “and/or” sense of the Latin
word vel. Indeed the symbol v looks like the initial letter of that word. Then
2+ 2 =4 or January is a month
is a true disjunction.
When one says, “If it rains, then I will stay home,” the meaning usually
includes the inverse statement, “If it does not rain, then I will not stay home.””
This is not the case in a logical implication. As a logical implication, this
statement gives absolutely no information for the case when it does not rain.
To illustrate the plausibility of our definition for implication, consider
the statement:
“if a figure is a square, then it has four right angles.”
Let p denote the statement “this figure is a square,” and q the statement
“this figure has four right angles.” Certainly this implication is to be con-
sidered true—always true. In Fig. 2.3 notice that the case where p is true and
q is false, is missing. This is the one situation that cannot occur; a figure8 cH.1 LOGIC
cannot be a square and not have four right angles. Since each of the other
three cases can occur, it is reasonable to call the implication true in all of
them.
Figure
Square fel
Oblong
Trapezoid Z_]
Figure 2.3, Implication.
Equivalence has the expected meaning, again remembering that the two
statements need not be related. A true equivalence is, for example,
2+ 2 = Siff July 4 is New Year’s Day.
Truth tables are especially convenient for examining compound propo-
sitions such as (p v q')->p’. In Fig. 2.4, the first, second, and last columns
constitute the truth table for the given proposition. The intermediate columns
merely serve as an aid to constructing the last column. Thus the values for
PV q’ ate determined by remembering that a disjunction is false only when
both members are false. But p and q’ are both false only in the third line; at
least one of them is true in each of the other lines. Now the entire statement
is an implication, and an implication is false only when truth implies falsity;
in this case, only when p V q’ is true and p’ is false. That combination occurs
in the first two rows only.
@vg)>r
Ficure 2.4. (pv q)>p’.
Note that (p v q’) > p’ has the same truth values as p’ has. Then these two
statements are equivalent; one could be used in place of the other in any
logical discussion.
Finally we agree to write, in any truth table, the symbols for the primitive
propositions p,g,r,... in alphabetical order, and to make the rightmost
column T, F,T,F,..., the next column leftward T,T,F,F,..., and so
forth. For three statements, we would have the arrangement of Fig. 2.5. ThisSTATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES SEC.2 9
is not the only system in use, but we adopt it here for the sake of standardiza-
tion of our discussions.
madam naa|s
nana mans
Figure 2.5. Truth table heading.
EXERCISES
»
Decide which of the following are statements.
Every general statement has its exceptions.
Some triangles are equilateral.
Some goobs are feekles.
All sociologists believe in public housing.
When the swallows return to Capistrano.
Are you studying?
Today is February 18th.
Don’t get angry.
Five is a number and “five” is a numeral.
j. Apples are good and red or yellow.
rm OS BOTS
2-2, Answer the questions posed in the opening paragraph of this
section.
2-3. Write a negation for each statement without using “it is not
true that...”
a. Five is a prime number.
b. Today is hot.
¢. This book is purple.
2-4. Complete these truth tables, where possible.
a ple b.
T
F
742-5. Decide the truth value of each statement.
a, If2+2=4, then 6-7 = 42.
b. If2+2=4, then 5°9 = 59.
c. If2 +7 =27, then 6 + 8 = 542.
a. 1f2+7=3,then5+1=6.
2-6. Decide the truth value of each statement.
5$+3=8and2+6= 14.
54+3=80r2+6= 14
343=8if246= 14.
24+3=5and2-3=6.
243=5o0r2+3=6.
S41 =9if3+7=8.
Write a truth table for each proposition in Exercises 2-7 to 2-15.
27. (PAg—-(PvQy.
28. (Pv g>(P \4).
2.9. (pq) v (pod).
2-10. (p vg >(P Aq).
211, (pg) A (qr) (pr).
212. (p’ >p)op.
2-13. (p> 9) ro (p> (qr).
214. (p Ag)>(p vr’).
215. (p> Ar (P>9) A (Pr).
mepaogse
3 | TAUTOLOGIES, ABSURDITIES, AND CONTINGENCIES
3.1 DEFINITION. A logical statement that is always true is called a
tautology; a proposition that is always false is an absurdity; one that is
sometimes true and sometimes false is a contingency.
One of the main purposes of logic is to ferret out tautologies, for these
are the theorems, or laws, of logic. We shall be concerned only with testingTAUTOLOGIES, ABSURDITIES, AND CONTINGENCIES SEC. 3 i
for tautologies, checking the truth tables of propositions for the last column
having only T’s. Figure 3.1 shows some examples. In particular, p-> (p A q)
is a contingency; (p A q)->p, (p Aq) (q A p), and p V p’ are tautolo-
gies; whereas p A p’ is an absurdity, whence (p A p’y isa tautology. That is,
whenever any statement s is an absurdity, then s’ is a tautology.
PAG |p>@ ag)
mamas] s amma]
mammals mansi]s
Ficure 3,1, Some compound statements.
Statements having the same truth tables are equivalent. Figure 3.1 shows
that p> (p Aq) is equivalent to p->q, and that p Aq is equivalent to
q A p. Inany logical argument a statement can be replaced by any equivalent
one. Some interesting equivalent statements appear in Fig. 3.2. It also shows
that each of the connectives can be expressed in terms of negation and just
one of the three connectives A, V, or —r, since also p++q is equivalent to
the conjunction (pq) A (q—>p). It is left to the reader to verify these
equivalences.
Statement Equivalent statements
PAG
pvG (Pi agy
oq (Na) | ee vg.
Figure 3.2. Some equivalent statements.12 cH.1 Logic
3.2. DEFINITION. Calling the implication
p->q the given statement,
we then call
q-p the converse,
p'->q the inverse,
and
q — p' the contrapositive.
As an example, consider the given statement:
if it is February, then thirty days hence will be March.
Its converse is:
if thirty days hence will be March, then it is February;
its inverse:
if it is not February, then thirty days hence will not be March;
and its contrapositive:
if in thirty days it will not be March, then it is not February.
Observe that the given implication and its contrapositive are both true
in this case. Also, if today is January 31, then thirty days hence is March,
but now is not February. Thus the converse and the inverse are not true. One
must be very careful, when using a theorem stated as an implication, not to
assume the converse without its having been proved. The next theorem
indicates this logical relation between these four statements in the general
case.
3.3 THEOREM. The given statement and its contrapositive are
logically equivalent; the inverse and the converse are equivalent. The given
statement is not equivalent to its converse. Symbolically,
>) >P),
@'> 9) 49>?)
but
(pq) (q¢-> Pp) is not true.
We conclude this section by listing some important tautologies, leaving
their proofs for the reader to supply. The reader is urged to clip a paper clipTAUTOLOGIES, ABSURDITIES, AND CONTINGENCIES SEC. 3 13
on this page for quick reference. It is important to have ready access to these
tautologies as they will be referred to by name from time to time.
3.4 THEOREM. The following are tautologies:
(1) (pA py. Law of contradiction.
Q) pvp’. Law of excluded middle.
QB vga vp) and (p Ag) (q Ap). Commutative
laws.
@ (vavVNe(PV|@V n)and(p rg ane
(pA @ An). Associative laws.
OS PAGV (Ag V@Ar))and (pV (GAT)
(» vq) A(@ vr). Distributive laws.
(© pp". Law of double negation.
(1) (pq) (q'>p'). _ Law of contraposition.
(8) (p>q) \(Q>n)> (pr). Law of syllogism.
0) (PA (~~>q)>4. __Law of detachment.
(10) (p Aq)->p. Law of simplification.
Also p(p vq). Law of addition.
GD ( A(pvq)—>¢. Law of disjunction.
(12) (p A p)pand (p Vv p)++p. —_Idempotent laws.
(13) (p Ag)’ Oo’ Vv q)and (p Vv 9)’ (e' Aq’). De Morgan’s
laws.
(14) (pg) (pq) A (Gp). —_Biconditional law.
EXERCISES
3-1 through 3-14. Verify lines (1) through (14) of Theorem 3.4 by truth
tables.
In Exercises 3-15 to 3-22, decide whether each statement is a tautology,
an absurdity, or a contingency.
3-15. (g A (p> 9) >P-
316. (q' A(po ge.
317. (pA (pag) g.
3.18. (p Ag)> >").
3-19. p'—> (pq).
3-20. (p A p')>-4.
321. (PV p> Ag).
3-22. (p vg) (q V py14 cH. 1 Logic
3-23. In Fig. 3.2, verify the equivalence of the three statements given
in the
a. first line. b. second line. c. third line.
3-24. Rewrite each statement as an implication.
a. Ifp, theng. b. gifp.
c. qonly if p. d. gis necessary for p.
e. qis sufficient for p. f. A necessary condition for p is g.
g. A sufficient condition for p is q.
3-25, Rewrite each statement in the form “if..., then...”.
a, A necessary condition for two triangles to be congruent is
that the three sides of one be equal respectively to the three
sides of the other.
b. A sufficient condition for two triangles to be congruent is
that the three sides of one be equal respectively to the three
sides of the other.
c. The base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal.
3-26. Write the converse, inverse, and contrapositive of each statement.
a. If today is Monday, then tomorrow is Tuesday.
b. The base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal.
c x+y =z implies x < z.
3-27. State whether the converse of each theorem is true or false.
a. Ifa = 5, then ac = be.
b. The base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal.
c. Ifatriangle has sides of length a, 6, and c with a? + 5 = c?,
then it is a right triangle.
3.28. Define p/q to mean p’ v q'.
a. Show that p’< (p/p).
b. Show that (p v 4)+> (p/p)/(a/a)).
Since negation and disjunction can be expressed in terms of this Sheffer’s
stroke symbol | only, and since all the logical connectives can be expressed
in terms of negation and disjunction, it follows that all the logical connec-
tives may be expressed in terms of stroke only. Find expressions, in terms of
p,q, and | only, for
ce pag
d. pq.
e perg.
4 | THE MATHEMATICS OF LOGIC
Many arguments can be readily reduced to symbolic logic, so let us
consider the analysis of such arguments. A logical argument consists of someTHE MATHEMATICS OF LOGIC SEC.4 15
assumed statements, called the hypothesis, and a derived statement, called the
conclusion. It is called valid iff the hypothesis implies the conclusion; that is,
iff the statement
“the hypothesis implies the conclusion”
is a tautology. Otherwise the argument is called invalid.
It is interesting to note that a statement such as
(PAP)>49
is a tautology. It shows that a false hypothesis (p A p’ is an absurdity)
implies any conclusion whatsoever. It follows that if the hypothesis is never
true, then the argument is automatically valid. Some authors do not permit
the term “valid” to apply in such a case, but we do not so restrict its use here.
Note also that
p>(ava)
is a tautology; that is, any statement implies a tautology. Thus, if the con-
clusion is a tautology, then the argument is automatically valid.
A rule for testing arguments is now stated. Remember that we call a
statement “true” or “false,” and an argument “valid” or “invalid”; the
terms “true” and “false” are never applied to an argument.
4.1 RULE. Any tautology may be assumed. If p<+q is a tautology,
then any occurrence of p may be replaced by q in any statement. From
pq and p, we may derive g. From p A q, we may derive p. From p, we
may derive p v q.
By the above rules, an argument is valid only when the conclusion can
be derived from the hypothesis (the given statements). Otherwise it is invalid.
An argument may be proved invalid by finding a set of truth values for the
primitive statements p,q, r,... which makes the hypothesis true and the
conclusion false.
Consider the argument
Pe
ro q
PAS
a
where the three statements given above the line are hypothesis, assumed true,
and the statement below the line is the conclusion. The three-dot triangle .".
is read “therefore.” We must show that
(>) A >a) AP ASNr
is a tautology. The form of Fig. 4.1 serves to analyze the argument.16 cH.1 Locic
rog pAS
“gor D
P>4q por
por r
Figure 4,1. A valid argument.
From r’—-q', we obtain its contrapositive g—> r. From p->g andg—>r,
obtain p—>r by the law of syllogism. From p A s, obtain p by the law of
simplification. From p and p— r, obtain r by the law of detachment. Thus
this argument is valid.
It is interesting to note that statement s was not used. That is, statement
P A Stells us that both p and s are true, but we had no use for s. Occasionally
such unnecessary information will appear in the hypothesis.
Now consider the argument and analysis of Fig. 4.2. From p V q and
p’, obtain g, the law of disjunction. Now from g and r—>g, we can
obtain nothing; from the table for implication, if the conclusion q is true,
then the hypothesis r can be either true or false. This line of reasoning yields
no results, so we suspect that the argument is invalid. Let us search for a set
of truth values for p, g, and r which will verify the hypothesis and deny the
conclusion. Clearly we must have p’ and r’. From p v q, since p’ (p is false),
then q (q must be true). Thus p’, q, and r’ are a possible set of values. Since
q is true, then p V g and rg are true, and p’ is true. However, r is false.
This proves that the argument is invalid.
PYG Pvq
mq -
ee :
og
ee rq
2
Figure 4.2, An invalid argument.
An alternative method is available provided there are not too many
primitive propositions p, q, r,... involved. Consider the argument
Doge poe gr
Form a truth table which includes each of the statements involved. Since the
conclusion must be true whenever all the hypothesis is true, we are not at all
concerned with what occurs when the hypothesis is not all true. Thus cross
out any row containing a statement from the hypothesis that is false. If theTHE MATHEMATICS OF LOGIC sEC.4 17
conclusion is true in every remaining row, the argument is valid; otherwise
it is invalid. In this case (see Fig. 4.3) we have rows 1 and 2 crossed out
because p—>q’ is false there; rows 3, 4, 7, and 8, because q is false there. In
rows 5 and 6, all three statements in the hypothesis are true. In row 5, r is
true, but r is false in row 6, whence the argument is invalid because the
conclusion is not true in every row that is not crossed out.
ei q |erd| por iy
Te er r
T|T/FI/F] F F
Tier) i | f T
Peet) 7 F
FIT/T/F] T T
ElG Ele) fF r
Belt) 7
FI F| F/T] T Tx
Figure 4.3, Truth table analysis of an argument.
A few words of caution are appropriate here. From the implication
pq, given p, one can conclude g. Alternatively, given q’, one can conclude
p’ by the contrapositive. However, no conclusion is possible when either p’
or q is given. Drawing a conclusion in such a case is called arguing from the
converse. It is never permissible.
From the disjunction p v , given p’, one can conclude g. However,
given p, it is not possible to conclude either g or q’. That is, no conclusion is
possible in this case.
Finally, given p—>g and g->r, we can conclude p-»r by the law of
syllogism. From p-»q and r—>q, no such conclusion is possible. Also, from
p> qand p—>r, no conclusion of this form is possible.
EXERCISES
Test the validity of each argument in Exercises 4-1 to 4-10.
41. p3q r>p, qon op.
4-2. pv gq qr,
43. pA, r>p.
44. pVg pV.
4-5. p>q', qvr,
46. PVG Gor
47 pVG pPvg. 3. peg18 cH.1 Loaic
48. pog rp ros fs.
49. pq. ee 5
410. poq, gon ros. sive.
In Exercises 4-11 to 4-25, rewrite each argument in symbolic form using
the suggested letters. Then check the validity of the argument.
4-11. IfJohn is sane (J), then he can do logic (Z). If he is not sane, then
he cannot serve on a jury (let S denote “he can serve”). John cannot do logic.
Therefore, he cannot serve on a jury.
4-12. If Henry is a professor (P), then he is a fool (F). If he is not a fool,
then he is learned (Z). Hence, if he is a professor, then he is not learned.
4-13. If today is Friday (F), then yesterday was Thursday (T). But
yesterday was Thursday. Hence, today is Friday.
4-14. The train is late (L) if it snows (S). It is not snowing. Therefore,
the train is not late.
4-15. The train is late (L) only if it snows (S). It is not snowing.
Therefore, the train is not late.
4-16. If this car is made in England (4), then parts are difficult to
obtain (D). This car is expensive (E) or it is not difficult to obtain parts. But
this car is not expensive. Hence it was not made in England.
4-17. If I do not study (S), then I will sleep (/). I will not sleep if Lam
worried (W). Hence, if I am worried, I will study.
4-18. Unless Jones is elected (/), we will lose the airbase (L). Jones will
be elected iff he has your support (S). If we save the airbase, then Jones will
be elected. We will save the airbase. Hence Jones has your support.
4-19 The professor assigns homework (H) iff he lectures (Z). If class
is dismissed (D), then there will be no lecture. There will not be both class
and homework, but there will be one or the other. Hence we have homework.
4-20. My vacation will be in June (J) or in December (D). It cannot be
at both times. If it is in December, then I can expect snow (S), but surely it
would not snow in June (W). If the vacation is not in December, then it will
be quite hot (H). Hot weather implies a June vacation. Hence it is either hot
or snowy when I take my vacation.
4-21. Either John and Dick are the same age (A), or John is older than
Dick (0). If they are the same age, then Mary and John are not the same age
(M). If John is older than Dick, then John is also older than Susy (S).
Hence either Mary and John are not the same age, or John is older than Susy.
4.22. If Sam is in jail (J), then he is not a bother to his family (B). If
he is not a bother, then he is in the army (A). If he is a disgrace (D), then he
is a bother, Hence he is either in the army or not a disgrace.QUANTIFIERS SEC.5 19
4-23. Either Carl has been paid (C) or Sam is spending more than he
can afford (S). If Sam is spending more than he can afford, then his bank
account is empty (£). But Sam’s bank account is not empty. Therefore, Carl
has been paid.
4-24. Mary is married (M) and Sally is single (S). If Arthur has a job
(J), then Mary is married. Hence Arthur has a job.
4-25. Either logic is difficult (D) or not many students like it (Z). If
mathematics is easy (E), then logic is not difficult. Therefore, if many
students like logic, then mathematics is not easy.
5 | QUANTIFIERS
Until the word “the” is replaced by a meaningful term, a statement such
“he was a prize fighter”
is not a proposition, even though it has the form of a proposition. A set of
objects that make a sentence a proposition is called a meaningful set for that
sentence, and such a sentence is called an open sentence. The word (or
symbol) to be replaced is called a variable. Here a meaningful set is the set of
all people. The replacement of “he” by “Joe Louis” makes the statement
true; hence Joe Louis is a truth value for this open sentence. “Clayton W.
Dodge” does not make this sentence true; hence it is not a truth value. The
set of all objects in a given meaningful set that make a sentence true is called
its truth set. The truth set in this case is the set of all past prize fighters.
In the meaningful set of natural numbers, the open sentence x? + 6 = 5x
has the truth set {2, 3}, as the reader can readily verify. In this same meaning-
ful set, 6x? + 7x — 3 = 0 has no truth values. In the meaningful set of
rational numbers, it has {—#, 4} as truth set.
Now it makes no sense to set x = Joe Louis in the open sentence
6x? + 7x — 3 = 0, so we do not permit such a replacement. That is, re-
placements must come from a meaningful set for that particular open
sentence.
‘An example of an open sentence involving more than one variable is
x + 2y = 2x. A truth value here is (2, 1) meaning x = 2andy = 1.
5.1 DEFINITION. Two statements that can be made about an open
sentence p(x) having variable x are
(1) for all x, p(x) is true, and
(2). there exists an x such that p(x) is true.20 cH. 1 Locic
Statement (1) is symbolized by
Vx, p(x)
or simply
P(x).
The “upside down A” is read “for all” or “for each.”
Statement (2) is symbolized by
ax 3 p(x)
or
Ax, p(x).
The symbol 3 is read “there exists,” and the comma, or the symbol 9, an
upper case Russian letter pronounced “er,” means “such that.”
The statement Yx, p(x) is taken as true iff every meaningful value for
P(x) is a truth value; 3x 3 p(x) is true iff p(x) has at least one truth value in
its meaningful set.
Thus 3x 9 6x? + 7x — 3 = Ois a true statement, but Vx, 6x? + 7x — 3
= 0 is false. On the other hand, the statement Vx, 2x + 4 = 2(x + 2) is
true, for whenever x is replaced by a meaningful term (a number), then the
statement (equation) is true; it is an identity.
The statement 3x 3 p(x) means that at least one meaningful value exists
which makes the statement true. It could even occur that every meaningful
value is a truth value. Thus it is perfectly correct to say Ix 32x +4 =
2(x + 2), for there is a truth value (x = 3, for example) verifying the state-
ment.
In stating ¥x, p(x) we mean that whenever there is a meaningful replace-
ment for x, then that value makes the statement p(x) true. It does not require
any meaningful values to exist. For example,
“all kings of the United States are bald”
is a true statement because the United States has no kings. If the meaningful
set is taken as the set of all kings of the United States, then the statement
might read
Vx, x is bald;
its meaningful set is the empty set, and the statement is taken as true. This
convention means that for the statement Vx, p(x) to be false, there must
exist a meaningful value of x which makes the statement p(x) false. We have
established the first part of the following theorem, whose second part we
shall not formally prove. We agree to write p’(x) to denote that p(x) is false.QUANTIFIERS sEC.5 = 21
5.2 THEOREM. (Vx, p(x)’ @x 9 p(x) and (ax 3p(x))'o
(vx, P(x).
An example will help to clarify these ideas. Consider a shelf of black
blocks and white blocks. What possibilities could occur? We could have all
black blocks, all white blocks, some of each, or no blocks at all. See Fig. 5.1.
The statement
3x 9 x is black
is true on shelves 3 and 4 only. Hence its negation
Vx, x is white (not black)
is true on shelves 1 and 2 (only). Similarly,
Vx, x is black
is true on shelves | and 3, whence its negation
ax 9 x is white (not black)
must be true on shelves 2 and 4.
1.
2) Ble)
3. an 8
4/00 ©
Ficure 5.1. Negations of quantifiers.
Arguments involving quantifiers are most easily handled by means of
specialized diagrams called Euler diagrams, in which the interiors of circles
represent the sets of objects involved and are so placed as to satisfy the
hypothesis and, if possible, to deny the conclusion.
Consider the argument:
Some cats are felines.
All felines are quadrupeds.
.. All cats are quadrupeds.
Let C denote the set of all cats, F, felines, and Q, quadrupeds. Draw a circle
and label it C for the set of all cats. See Fig. 5.2. By the hypothesis, the circle
F must have at least one point in common with circle C. We are forced to
draw circle F with at least the overlap indicated.22. cH. 1 Logic
Figure 5.2. Cats.
Now (see Fig. 5.3), circle @ must be drawn completely surrounding
circle F. Two possibilities are shown. It is possible to draw these circles so
that the conclusion is not satisfied. The right-hand figure is such a case. This
argument, then, is invalid, regardless of the truth or falsity of the conclusion.
The conclusion, even though it is true, does not logically follow from the
hypothesis. We say the argument is invalid; we do not say that it is false.
0)
Ficure 5.3. More cats.
2
The argument:
All bats are rats.
All rats are mats.
«', All bats are mats.
is valid, as Fig. 5.4 shows. It is not possible to draw the circles to satisfy the
hypothesis and not satisfy the conclusion. Again, we are not in the least
Ficure 5.4. Bats.QUANTIFIERS SEC.5 23
concerned with the truth or falsity of the statements involved; our only
concern is with the logic of the argument, devoid of all real meaning.
EXERCISES
5-1. Write a negation for each statement.
a. Vx, p(x) A q(x).
b. Vx, p(x) V g(x).
ce. ¥x, px) > g(x).
Vx, a(x) g(x).
e. Wx, p(x).
5-2. Write a negation for each statement.
a. Ax D p(x) A g(x).
b. 3x D p(x) v g(x).
c. ax D p(x) q(x).
d. 4x3 p(x) g(x).
e. dx Dp'(x).
5-3. Write a negation for each statement.
a. All cats are felines.
b. Some dogs are not blue.
c. All birds are nonswimmers.
d. Some animals are quadrupeds.
In Exercises 5-4 to 5-17, test each argument for validity by means of
Euler diagrams.
5-4. All men are rich. Socrates was a man. Hence Socrates was rich.
5-5, Platinum is heavy. Nothing but platinum will satisfy him. Hence
nothing light (not heavy) will satisfy him.
5-6. Some freshmen are undergraduates. Some undergraduates are
students. Therefore some freshmen are students.
5-7. No dogs are fish. Some guppies are fish. Hence some guppies are
not dogs.
5-8. Some girls are teachers. Mary Jones is a teacher. Therefore,
Mary Jones is some girl.
5-9. Some horses eat hay. Henry eats hay. Hence Henry is a horse.
5-10. All lions are fierce. Some lions do not drink milk. Thus some
creatures that drink milk are not fierce.
5-11. All gerbles are glops. All glops are gurkles. Some gurkles are
geebers. Hence some gerbles are geebers.
5-12. All timid creatures are bunnies. All timid creatures are dumb.
Some cows are timid creatures. Thus some cows are dumb bunnies.24 cH. 1 LOGIC
5-13, All men are bipeds. Some wolves are bipeds. Some men are
carnivorous. Hence some wolves are carnivorous or some men are wolves.
5-14. All mathematics professors are absent-minded. All absent-
minded people are slightly crazy. Hence some mathematics professors are
slightly crazy.
5-15. All murders are immoral. Some murders are justifiable. Thus
some immoral acts are justifiable.
5-16. No apes are buttercups. No buttercups are whales. Thus no apes
are whales.
5-17. All horses are animals. Some animals are quadrupeds. Hence
some horses are quadrupeds,
5-18. For each of the eight possibilities of valid or invalid argument
and true or false hypothesis and conclusion listed below, construct a simple
argument, where possible, illustrating the situation.
1 2245 6 7 6
Arcument = Vo VY v1 tt
Hypothesis T T F F T T F F
Concusion T F T F T F T F
5-19. In Exercise 5-18, which case or cases cannot occur?
6 | THE LOGIC OF MATHEMATICS
Consider the problem of constructing a logical discourse. The ultimate
goal is the development of a body of true statements, theorems, or tautologies
about the objects in the discourse. Suppose, for example, one wanted to
write a Euclidean geometry textbook. First one might make a list of the
topics to be discussed, such as congruent figures, similar figures, circles, and
so forth. Next one might state specific theorems, such as the Pythagorean
theorem, to be established.
Consider how to prove a theorem in the discourse. How would one
Prove the Pythagorean theorem, Generally, one would expect to prove it
from other true statements (theorems) already established. But these state-
ments should also be proved from still other statements, and so forth.
Clearly this process must end. That is, there must be a body of initial
statements that are taken as true without proof. These are called the axioms
or postulates of the discourse and are statements about the objects of the
discourse that are accepted as true for the purposes of the discourse. An
axiom for Euclidean geometry might very well be:
Two distinct points determine exactly one line on which they both lie.THE LOGIC OF MATHEMATICS SEC.6 = 25
Returning to the Pythagorean theorem, let us consider the terms that
are involved. Obviously “triangle” is one of them. To be sure that the student
is fully aware of the meanings of such terms, they should be defined carefully.
One might say:
A triangle is the figure composed of three points not all lying on the
same straight line and the three line segments determined by pairs of
these points.
Observe that we have defined triangle in terms of point, line, line segment,
and figure. Now these terms must also have been defined. Any definition
presupposes a knowledge of the technical terms used in that definition. Our
definition of triangle assumed the understanding of each of the four terms
mentioned above.
It follows that not all terms can be explicitly defined, for we do not have
an endless supply of terms upon which to draw. And, of course, it is un-
thinkable to commit the “sin of circularity” by defining point in terms of
line (say, as the intersection of two lines), and then turning around and
defining line in terms of point (as a special collection of points). A dictionary
has to commit this sin of circularity, since it must assume the reader already
has a basic knowledge of the language. Therefore, an English dictionary is
of no help to a person who knows no English.
Thus some basic terms, called primitive terms, must be purposely left
undefined. No definitions are given for these primitive terms. They may be
informally explained to guide the reader’s thinking, but such explanations
are not to be confused with definitions. In his Elements, Euclid explained that
a point is “that which has no dimension.” This is not a definition; it serves
only to give the reader a partial understanding of the basis upon which the
discourse is to be built.
How, then, are the primitive terms to be given precise meanings? By
the postulates. These assumed statements involve the primitive terms and
state their properties implicitly. The statement,
two points determine exactly one line,
tells something about points and lines. It helps to clarify the meanings of
both these terms. By stating enough such properties, we narrow down the
possible meanings to just exactly what we intend. This is the only definition
given any primitive term. :
Logically, words are not necessary; all the axioms can be stated sym-
bolically, and the primitive terms can be merely symbols. Thus one can state
two x’s determine exactly one y
instead of
two points determine exactly one line.