The Inconceivability of Zombies
The Inconceivability of Zombies
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical
Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition
Robert Kirk
Received: 12 August 2006 /Accepted: 5 March 2007 / Published online: 15 May 2007
© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007
1 Introduction
Zombies would be like us in all physical respects, but without phenomenal consciousness.
It is widely agreed that if zombies are possible, physicalism is false. A much debated
argument for the possibility of zombies starts from the claim that they are conceivable,
then urges that whatever is conceivable is possible. Many physicalists agree that zombies
are conceivable - even in a strong sense - but disagree that conceivability entails possi-
bility. Whatever may be the correct view on that last point, I think all are wrong about the
R. Kirk (El)
Department of Philosophy, University of Nottingham, 97 Westhorpe, Southwell, Notts NG25 ONE, UK
e-mail: [email protected]
£} Springer
conceivab
strong en
There are
idea is so
somethin
surely it i
involving
appeal the
which has
That is w
My appro
be explain
physical
which are
two stage
sense) bec
so is the
(A) The e
(B) If zom
Therefor
(A) is def
The idea of zombies suggests itself as soon as one accepts the causal closure of
physical. If every physical effect has a physical cause, all human behavior is explica
physical terms. But then how does consciousness - phenomenal consciousness, t
involved in there being 'something it is like' to have experiences - fit into the
Apparently it can only be a causally inert by-product, and epiphenomenalism or
lelism must hold. In that case, as G. F. Stout argued,
it ought to be quite credible that the constitution and course of nature would
otherwise just the same as it is if there were not and never had been any experien
individuals.4
What Stout envisaged is a 'zombie twin' of our world: a physical duplicate of the
world on the assumption that the physical world is closed under causation - s
everything physical goes on just the same - but without phenomenal consciou
Zombies must be understood to be complete physical systems in the sense that all ef
1 For the view that the zombie possibility entails the falsity of physicalism see e.g. Chalmers (199
Kirk (1974, 2005, pp. 7-23). For the conceivability argument see e.g. Kripke (1980), Chalmers (2
other essays in Gendler and Hawthorne (2002).
2 Indirect objections: Ryle (1949) and Wittgenstein (1953); direct ones: e.g. Dennett (1991, 1995)
(2005, pp. 37-57); Shoemaker (1981, 1999); Tye (2006).
3 This outline mirrors that of Kirk (2005, pp. 39-55). However, the arguments here are signi
different (and I think clearer and more cogent) and take account of objections not considered in t
4 Stout (1931, 138f).
£} Springer
£} Springer
(E2) of th
is our rel
Although
(E5), man
aims to sh
are incom
tions env
trouble ov
4 E-quali
By (E3), e
that the q
seem to h
a thorn in
caused pa
physical
physical
but in fac
this accou
note a co
Like all v
the metap
that is, in
them, an
notice, at
experienc
condition
qualities
must be a
their e-qu
Epistemi
and the s
changes a
points. If
effects la
these trac
about, att
retrieved
it depend
contribut
9 Chalmer
consider th
indicated.
10 It might
But the ne
capable of
£} Springer
£} Springer
an e-qual
included
slight exp
e-qualiast
into epist
my count
with that
An obviou
neural pr
an approp
sequence
be tempo
might no
argue tha
difficulty
6 The pr
It is agree
referent
be inert,
e-qualia s
epipheno
arguing a
depend on
epiphenom
The follo
(Q) How,
to anyon
hook the
I will arg
of an E-w
qualia bec
would ha
qualia. Th
if e-quali
epistemic
7 My cra
Suppose t
those of o
electrical
on them.
12 Epiphen
£l Springer
^ Springer
e-qualia a
counterfa
present s
remain ou
The crani
discussed.
insulated
ined) caus
cases have
properties
the detail
between e-
world cou
would equ
given the
cranial cu
(See also O
We have
able to esc
It is the o
less the d
world fro
generally
E-qualists
will reinf
8 The arg
1. E-qual
2. Being
attending
3. These a
structure
(Sect. 4).
4. That ra
contact w
5. One sug
physical p
e-qualia (
6. The exa
physical
7. It is als
physical
suggestio
preceding
£l Springer
9 Objections
13 It would not help e-qualists to say e-qualia are subjectless: that would only support my claim that no one
could be in epistemic contact with them. On the other hand, I see no objection to the notion of integrated,
nonrelational processes of having-qualia (see Kirk, 2005, pp. 154-158)- but that is obviously inconsistent
with the e-qualia story.
^ Springer
of conscio
counterfa
they have
notice, co
Reply 3:
physical p
contact w
4 acquaint
Evidently
hand and
the differ
know the
(b) intrin
those prop
(a) is ruled
the physi
cranial cur
related to
them.
The objection seems to envisage that (b) what underlies the relation is an intrinsic
property of e-qualia. But this thought was anticipated and dismissed in Sect. 7. My cranial
currents are a counter-example to the suggestion that if something - regardless of its
nature - were caused by and isomorphic to some of my physical processes (while not
affecting them), then these would put me into epistemic contact with that something in the
relevant sense (Sect. 7). It follows, as we saw, that the intrinsic properties of the item in
question make no difference to the argument. Whatever they may be, they are locked up
beyond the epistemic reach of my cognitive processing. So if what underlies the
acquaintance relation is an intrinsic property of e-qualia, then both that property and the
subject are marooned within that realm, and cannot put me into any relevant kind of
epistemic contact with e-qualia.
It is suggested that (c) acquaintance operates in combination with the counterfactual
dependence of underlying physical processes on relations among e-qualia. This depen-
dence, together with the effects of those physical processes on the stream of consciousness,
is supposed to put the subject 'in a position to notice, compare, and remember e-qualia'.
However, I argued in Sect. 7 that counterfactual dependence could not provide for that kind
of epistemic contact; and we have just seen that the suggested relation of acquaintance
does not block that argument.
Objection 4: 'You're construing the special epistemic access that e-qualists claim we
have to our qualia on the model of familiar kinds of epistemic access such as sense
perception. But according to e-qualists, our epistemic access to qualia is private in this
sense: to have them is to know them. The accessibility of electric currents is just
observability: they are observable by anyone suitably equipped. So the cranial currents
example doesn't work because patterns of electric currents are nothing like what e-qualia
are supposed to be.'
Reply 4: The argument shows there is no way anyone could 'have' e-qualia in the
relevant sense: no one could be their subject and know them. E-qualia are certainly very
Thanks to a reviewer for this and the preceding objection, and for the phrasing of the suggested per-
spective on consciousness in an E-world.
£} Springer
15 See n. 8 above.
16 'Logically' independent in the sense that its e
physical component.
£} Springer
I will now
very clos
argue tha
We can t
Now, epip
system, w
Just as th
componen
ceivably,
would res
epiphenom
lowing se
(C) A caus
world so
phenome
compone
Parallelist
non-phys
relations
that it should do so.
Zombist interactionists, however, may think they can escape commitment to (C), first
because they reject the causal closure of the physical; second because they insist that the
non-physical component of our world is causally active (ert?). I will argue that, even so,
they must concede that (C) is conceivable. Before defining zombist interactionism I will
refine the definition of a 'zombie twin' world. A world z is a zombie twin of ours just in
case:
(ZI) Zombies are conceivable and the actual world consists of a physical component and
a non-physical component. The latter includes (or consists of) something i/^* such
that: (i) ij/* makes us phenomenally conscious and keeps us in epistemic contact
with our experiences; (ii) i/^* has effects on the physical component of the world and
is affected by it.
I will argue that (ZI) entails that conceivably our world as thus characterized - I will refer
to it as i - could be transformed into a world like z*; hence that (C) is conceivable. What
forces zombist interactionists into this position is their peculiar conception of conscious-
ness. For (ZI) entails the following three propositions.
(1) Conceivably the laws of nature governing i (the world according to (ZI)) could
change at a certain time so that from that time on: (i) no non-physical items in i had
effects; (ii) whatever had been directly or indirectly caused by non-physical items
17 Conscification need not be thought of as zombies becoming conscious, but only as the coming into
existence of conscious subjects whose physical components had been zombies.
£} Springer
If (ZI) entails (1), (2), and (3), obviously it entails that (C) is conceivable. I will argue that
(ZI) does indeed entail those premisses.
Premiss (1): Condition (i) is unproblematic. Causation is contingent, so zombists cannot
deny that conceivably anything that actually has effects - including i/^* - might have ex-
isted without having effects.18
(ZI) also entails that condition (ii) is straightforwardly conceivable together with (i), at
least for the case of physical effects. For (ZI) has it that zombies are conceivable; and in a
zombie world all physical events in i would be caused physically. (One result would be that
our successors in i behaved exactly like us. Some interactionists might deny that physical
events could cause human-like behavior, but they could not be zombists.)
As to won-physical effects, the question is whether there are any which could not
conceivably be produced physically; and interactionists can have no a priori objections to
that. So (ZI) entails that conceivably conditions (i) and (ii) are jointly satisfiable.
(iii): since (ZI), being a variety of dualism, entails that the non-physical component of
reality is logically independent of the physical component, it entails that that all non-
physical items in i might conceivably cease to exist; a fortiori that conceivably all non-
physical items other than \j/* could cease to exist, leaving ^* (now inert) as the only
surviving non-physical item. (In that case, notice, if i//* ceased to exist the result would be
a zombie twin of our world.) Clearly there is no inconsistency between that and conditions
(i) and (ii); so (ZI) entails (1).
Premiss (2): Evidently, one consequence of the changes envisaged in conditions (i) and
(ii) of premiss (1) would be that the physical component of i was closed under causation.
Also, because all those kinds of physical items that had previously been caused non-
physically would continue to be caused (though physically), i would remain physically
similar to what it had been; in fact the physical component of i would be exactly like a
zombie twin of our world. The question now is whether (ZI) entails that conceivably i/f*
would continue to make the inhabitants of i conscious and keep them in epistemic touch
with their experiences, or whether the changes would absolutely19 prevent that.
Consider, then, what differences the changes would make to i. They are that (in i after
the changes) (i) no non-physical items have effects; (ii) physical items have all the kinds of
effects that were originally produced by non-physical items; (iii) the only non-physical
item is i/^*. (i) and (ii) are crucial, of course, since they stop i from being an interactionist
18 Cartesian zombists might demur. If thinking - a kind of activity - is essential to the soul's existence, then
i//* cannot cease to be a cause without ceasing to exist. Also, some interactionist zombists might maintain it
is a priori necessary that consciousness involves non-physical causes. See, however, the discussion of
premiss (2) below. (Note that zombists cannot resist condition (i) by invoking causal essentialism, according
to which a thing's causal dispositions are essential to it. For if that doctrine is taken to entail that what
physicalists count as physical items cannot conceivably exist without causing or being caused by conscious
states, then zombies are inconceivable for that reason; while if it lacks that entailment, then it lets in (i).)
19 It would not be enough to claim that conceivably the changes might prevent ij/* from continuing to make
our successors conscious; (2) says only that (ZI) entails it is conceivable that it should do so.
£} Springer
world and
contribut
(a) what {/
caused, wh
their natur
(a): what
preclude
zombist i
physically
(b): since
dismiss (b
Since \j/*
our experi
no non-ph
inhabitants of i conscious.
Thus there is at least a strong case for the claim that (ZI) entails the conceivability of
premiss (2). However, zombist interactionists might think I have not done them justice.
They might urge that it is not by merely nomic necessity that what provides for con-
sciousness is causally efficacious: they might claim it is a priori necessary; so that even if
\j/* continued to exist after the changes, its inertness would prevent its continuing to make
anyone conscious.20 Now, I agree with the widespread view that whatever makes us
conscious cannot be inert. But I will argue that zombists are committed to a conception of
consciousness which entails that the contrary is at least conceivable. (Interactionist
zombists might endorse the correct view about consciousness and causality; but if I am
right that would make them inconsistent: their zombism commits them to an incorrect view
as well. In that case, appealing to the correct view cannot protect their incorrect view from
the arguments of Sects. 3-9.)
Like most of us, zombists claim to know they are conscious. Unlike some of us, they
cannot justify this claim by reference to observation of physical facts such as behavior -
because they think zombies would be physically indistinguishable from us, at least
superficially. This means that interactionist zombists must think their knowledge that they
are conscious, hence their knowledge that i//* exists, comes from the fact that they have
conscious experiences themselves, not from knowing any physical facts. A consequence is
that they cannot consistently claim it is a priori that if/* must have effects in order to make
us conscious. If we can know we are conscious by actually having conscious experiences,
then we can know it without also knowing whether or not consciousness has effects. So
zombist interactionists cannot maintain it is inconceivable that \j/* should make us con-
scious in spite of being inert. They may point out that we observe what we take to be
effects of our being conscious. But we cannot observe that they are effects of i//*: that is
part of a theory which, for them, might conceivably be mistaken. (Consistently with our
experience, those effects and \j/* might be joint effects of some common cause, for
example.)
Zombist interactionists might raise another objection. They might accept that epistemic
contact requires consciousness to have effects, but maintain that even if ij/* continued to
make our successors conscious, its lack of causal efficacy would prevent it from continuing
to sustain epistemic contact.21 I find it hard to make sense of that suggestion. Significantly,
£} Springer
It is easy to see that the definitions of a 'zombie twin' world and of (C) ensure that the
conceivability of (C) entails the conceivability of a world z* satisfying the following
conditions, which mirror (E1)-(E5):
(Zl) z* is partly physical and its physical component is closed under causation: every
physical effect has a physical cause.
^ Springer
(Z2) The h
\j/ make
(Z3) \j/ i
physical
(Z4) The h
(Z5) The h
and (on o
So the co
conceivab
(E1)-(E5)
"human
qualia". T
(E5)are a
have been
which is
assumptio
conceivab
The third
conceivab
componen
makes z*
Chalmers
like to ha
sense of Q
for these
But then
(E2), (E3)
So the co
(E5). We
the conce
(B) If zo
But we a
(A) The
By contr
References
Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
Chalmers, D. (1999). Materialism and the metaphysics of modality. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 59, 475^96.
Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Con-
ceivability and possibility (pp. 145-200). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown.
25 Special t
comments,
£} Springer
£l Springer