Words in this section: 1 215
COMPLEXITY AND POSTMODERNISM
Understanding and Modelling Complex Systems
PAUL CILLIERS
ii
CONTENTS
Preface
Approaching Complexity 1
Introducing Connectionism 46
Post-Structuralism, Connectionism And Complexity 69
John Searle Befuddles 89
Problems With Representation 108
Self-Organisation In Complex Systems 165
Complexity And Postmodernism 206
Afterword: Understanding Complexity 260
Bibliography 264
iii
PREFACE
“Complexity” and “postmodern” are both controversial notions.
Contemporary society is readily described as being postmodern, but there are
divers reactions to this description. For some (like Zygmunt Bauman)
postmodernism creates the possibility for us to escape from the strictures of
modernism and to re-enchant the world. For others (like Ernest Gellner) it
exemplifies relativism – a theoretical framework in which anything goes – and
leaves them with a feeling of vertigo. Postmodernism can also be seen as
being parasitic on modernism, or as modernism’s underbelly. In such a case it
could be argued that we should drop the concept altogether if we want to move
beyond the oversimplified ideals of the Enlightenment.
The different responses to postmodern theory naturally have different
understandings of the word’s meaning. Even if it were possible to clarify this
debate, it is not my intention to do so in this book, nor do I attempt to provide
an apology for postmodernism. My main concern is with the notions of
complexity and complex systems. As far as postmodernism is concerned, the
argument is simply that a number of theoretical approaches, loosely (or even
incorrectly) bundled together under the term “postmodern” (e.g. those of
Derrida and Lyotard), has an implicit sensitivity for the complexity of the
phenomena they deal with. Instead of trying to analyse complex phenomena in
terms of single or essential principles, these approaches acknowledge that it is
not possible to tell a single and exclusive story about something that is really
complex. The acknowledgement of complexity, however, certainly does not lead
to the conclusion that anything goes.
The concept “complexity” is not univocal either. Firstly, it is useful to
distinguish between the notions “complex” and “complicated”. If a system –
iv
despite the fact that it may consist of a huge number of components – can be
given a complete description in terms of its individual constituents, such a
system is merely complicated. Things like jumbo jets or computers are
complicated. In a complex system, on the other hand, the interaction between
the constituents of the system is of such a nature that the system as a whole
cannot be fully understood simply by analysing its components. This feature of
complex systems is usually referred to in terms of emergent properties. The
brain, natural language and social systems are complex.
Secondly, it is necessary to say something about the relationship between
complexity and chaos theory. The hype created by chaos theory has abated
somewhat, but unfortunately the perception that it has an important role to play
in the study of complex systems is still widespread. Although I would not deny
that chaos theory could contribute to the study of complexity, I do feel that its
contribution would be extremely limited. When analysing complex systems, a
sensitivity to initial conditions, for example, is not an important issue. As a
matter of fact, it is exactly the robustness of complex systems that ensures their
survival. Although the metaphor of the butterfly’s flapping wings causing a
tornado on the other side of the globe is a good one for describing a sensitivity
to initial conditions, it has caused so much confusion that I feel it should not be
used at all. Chaos theory remains primarily of mathematical interest. Chaotic
behaviour results from the non-linear interaction of a relatively small number of
equations – whereas in complex systems there is always a huge number of
interacting components. Despite the claims made about the functioning of the
olfactory system, or the structure of ferns, I am unsure whether any behaviour
found in nature could be described as chaotic in the technical sense. This
might sound too dismissive, and I certainly do not want to claim that aspects of
chaos theory and fractal mathematics cannot be used effectively in the process
v
of modelling nature. My claim is rather that chaos theory, and especially the
notions of deterministic chaos and universality, does not really help us to
understand the dynamics of complex systems. That showpiece of fractal
mathematics, the Mandelbrot set – sometimes referred to as the most complex
mathematical object we know – is in the final analysis complicated, not
complex. Within the framework of the present study, chaos theory is still part of
the modern paradigm.
The objective of the book is to illuminate the notion of complexity from a
postmodern, or perhaps, more accurately, post-structural perspective. The most
obvious conclusion drawn from this perspective is that there is no overarching
theory of complexity that allows us to ignore the contingent aspects of complex
systems. If something is really complex, it cannot be adequately described by
means of a simple theory. Engaging with complexity entails engaging with
specific complex systems. Despite this we can, at a very basic level, make
general remarks concerning the conditions for complex behaviour and the
dynamics of complex systems. Furthermore, I suggest that complex systems
can be modelled. The models, however, will have to be at least as complex as
the systems they model, and may therefore not result in any simplification of
our understanding of the system itself. As an example of such models, I make
extensive use of neural networks – a approach also known as connectionism.
As a matter of fact, the significance of postmodern theory for the study of
complexity is underscored by arguing that there are structural similarities
between the operation of neural networks and Derrida’s descriptions of the
working of language.
Apart from introductory chapters on connectionism and post-structuralism,
and a dismissal of Searle’s contributions to the debate, the central issues
discussed are representation and self-organisation. A discussion, or perhaps a
vi
deconstruction, of the notion of representation exemplifies the contribution that
a primarily philosophical analysis can make to modelling techniques.
Conversely, the discussion of self-organisation – a notion usually (but certainly
not exclusively) encountered in a scientific context – helps us to make the
(philosophical) point that the behaviour of a system without a pre-determined or
fixed structure, is not necessarily random or chaotic, in other words, that
anything does not go.
The book does not engage with moral theory in a systematic way, but it is
impossible, of course, to operate in a value free space. Ethical issues therefore
do surface now and then, especially in the final chapter. The characterisation of
complexity and complex systems developed in the present book certainly has
implications for social and moral theory that demand to be developed further.
This will hopefully be a more central aspect of future projects.
I would like to thank the following people for the contributions they have
made towards the development of the ideas presented here: Johan Degenaar,
Mary Hesse, Jannie Hofmeyr and the members of the two interdisciplinary
discussion groups at the University of Stellenbosch, one based in the arts
faculty, the other in the sciences. The help of Esmarie Smit in the completion of
the manuscript was invaluable.
Previous versions of some of the material used in chapters two, three and
seven have appeared in the South African Journal of Philosophy. Permission to
rework that material is gratefully acknowledged.