COORDINATION FAILURES
by
Peter Howitt
Brown University
Revised December 4, 2001
Draft article for An Encyclopaedia of Macroeconomics, edited by Howard Vane and Brian
Snowdon, to be published by Edward Elgar.
Coordination Failures
During a depression economic activities are badly coordinated. Firms allow plant and equipment
to fall idle despite increasing numbers of able-bodied people willing to operate it in exchange for
less than the value of their marginal product. Savers continue as before to make provision for
extra future consumption while production of the new capital needed to produce more consumer
goods is reduced. Stocks of consumer goods pile up unsold even though the desire to consume
them is, if anything, intensified by rising poverty. Farmers are forced off their land while others
go hungry.
Many economists therefore think of depression as being a state of coordination failure; a
state in which market forces have failed to coordinate the millions of transactors that interact
daily through a web of interconnected markets. What Smith called the ‘invisible hand,’ or
Mummery and Hobson (disparagingly) called the ‘automatic machinery of commerce,’ has not
guided them to a state in which markets clear. Instead, people are somehow led to act at cross
purposes, failing collectively to take full advantage of potential gains from trade. As Keynes put
it, the system is not ‘self-adjusting.’
The first step in understanding how a mechanism can fail is to understand how it works.
Although contemporary economic theory is rather vague on how market forces work, the
beginning student is left in little doubt that they operate mainly through the adjustment of prices.
According to all undergraduate textbooks, a free market will quickly reach a coordinated
(market-clearing) state, because prices rise when there is an excess demand and fall when there is
an excess supply. Analytical accounts of coordination failure therefore focus on why something
might go wrong with the process of price adjustment.
1
The classical tradition from Thornton through Marshall was to blame prolonged
unemployment on impediments to price-adjustment, particularly impediments to adjusting the
price of labor. This was also the approach of mainstream Keynesianism, which from Modigliani
through Fischer was based on the assumption of sticky wages. But Keynes himself believed that
coordination failure had a deeper reason, namely that wage and price adjustment, which classical
theory pictured as corrective forces, are actually destabilizing. If given full rein they would lead
an economy even further into depression, because a general decrease in wages and prices would
produce ‘debt deflation’ (to use Fisher’s term, which Keynes did not), destabilizing expectations
of further price decreases, and adverse distributional effects.
Patinkin (1948) elaborated on Keynes’s account of coordination failure by portraying the
process of wage and price adjustment as a dynamical system that fails to converge to its (full-
employment) equilibrium. Clower (1965) pointed out another possible reason for non-
convergence, namely that transactors will respond not just to the price-signals of classical theory
but also to quantity signals they receive when their attempts to trade are frustrated by existing
imbalances between supply and demand. Thus excess supply in one market can lead frustrated
sellers to curtail their demands in other markets, causing the excess supply to spread. As
Leijonhufvud (1968) later elaborated, the cumulative decline in effective demand resulting from
this process will tend to amplify deviations from full employment equilibrium rather than
dampening them.
The approach taken by these writers, of analyzing coordination failure in terms of
disequilibrium price adjustment, gained support from the demonstration by Scarf (1960) that
price-adjustment in a Walrasian general-equilibrium setting does not always converge to a
general equilibrium; in effect, adjustments in one market may be continually thwarted by
2
independent adjustments in other related markets. However, work on disequilibrium dynamics
fell out of fashion in the 1970s, largely because its proponents offered no conceptually coherent
account of the many logistical problems that arise when expectations are mutually inconsistent
and markets are not clearing, or of the institutions (firms, shops, money, markets, etc.) that deal
with these logistical problems in real life. The final blow was dealt by Lucas (1972) who showed
that one can provide a conceptually coherent account of at least transitory coordination problems
within a framework of rational expectations with clearly specified informational imperfections, a
framework in which none the awkward problems of disequilibrium theory are visible.
After a decade of relative neglect, the theory of coordination failure re-emerged in the
1980s, when various authors found a way to model it using the rational-expectations-equilibrium
approach which by that time had become de rigueur in macroeconomic theory. Since then, the
term “coordination failure” has taken on a different meaning, with no reference to disequilibrium
dynamics. Specifically, as elaborated by Cooper and John (1988) and later by Cooper (1999), it
now means the existence of multiple equilibria, often Pareto-ranked, of the kind that exist in
games with strategic complementarity.
Suppose for example that there is a strategic complementarity that works through “thin-
market externalities” in the process of search and matching. (See Diamond, 1982 and Howitt,
1985.) That is, when people on one side of a market put more effort into the matching process,
this makes it more worthwhile for those on the other side to do the same thing, because it makes
transacting less costly for them. Then the general expectation on the part of firms that it will be
difficult to find customers can be self-fulfilling. It leads firms to cut back their hiring effort,
which leads to a fall in job vacancies, which makes it harder for unemployed workers to find
jobs. As a result unemployment rises, and the consequent fall in incomes makes people generally
3
less willing to buy goods. This completes the vicious circle by confirming the original
expectation that it will be harder for firms to find customers.
On the other hand, the same chain of reasoning can often be applied to show that the
expectation that customers will be easy to find would also be self-fulfilling. Thus there are
multiple equilibria, some with optimistic expectations, high income and low unemployment, and
others with pessimistic expectations, low income and high unemployment. The latter might be
interpreted as depressions. They persist because they are non-Walrasian equilibria in which
people are interacting not just through prices but also through such non-price variables as the
difficulty of finding customers, or the difficulty of finding a vacancy in the labor market. In a
low-level equilibrium it would be pointless for firms to try lowering their prices since their
problem is not that they have overpriced their goods but that the cost of marketing products is
too high; similarly it would be pointless for workers to offer to work for lower wages since their
problem is not that they are asking too much but that they can’t find a potential employer with an
opening.
Such low-level equilibria imply a coordination failure, in the sense that if only everyone
would get together and raise their expectations in coordinated fashion, they could potentially
reach a high-level equilibrium where everyone is better off. They remain in a depression
because no mechanism exists for bringing about such a coordinated change in beliefs. Thus,
according to this approach, the process of price adjustment fails to coordinate activities because
it fails to deal with the root problem, namely that of pessimistic expectations with respect to non-
price variables.
The contemporary notion of coordination failure as multiple non-Walrasian equilibrium
thus shows the need to go beyond wage and price adjustment if we are to achieve a deeper
4
understanding of depressions. There are however two important, related problems with this
notion. The first is that although, as explained above, multiple-equilibrium models do illustrate a
kind of coordination failure they evade the task of analyzing the coordination process. A
rational-expectations equilibrium is by definition a highly coordinated state of affairs, in which
each transactor has managed somehow to anticipate, as fully as possible given informational
constraints, the actions of others. By focusing exclusively on such equilibria, the modern
coordination-failure literature thus presumes that coordination is managed costlessly by some
unspecified mechanism. This begs the question of how people can achieve such precise
coordination and yet fail in the seemingly simpler task of agreeing that the equilibrium they
coordinate on should be a good one.
The second problem is that any model of multiple equilibrium without some mechanism
for describing which if any equilibrium the economy will be led to lacks empirical content.
Indeed the problem is greater than it might seem at first glance, because the model will have not
just a high-level equilibrium and a low-level equilibrium but also a large number of other
equilibria, in which people randomize between the high-level and low-level equilibrium in
correlated fashion, according to the realization of some extraneous random variable. Because of
this second problem, standard comparative-statics analysis applied to the model cannot predict,
even qualitatively, how the economy will respond to variations in exogenous variables or policy
instruments that impinges on the economy, because the system might respond by changing from
one equilibrium to another.
In short, the rational-expectations-equilibrium theory of coordination failures is
incomplete without an account of the disequilibrium dynamics that the older literature sought to
provide. For it is only by studying what happens out of equilibrium that one can understand
5
which equilibrium will be arrived at, if any, by what route, and with what time delays. Howitt
and McAfee (1992) show how one might add such an account in a highly stylized example, in
which Bayesian learning can lead people to oscillate between a high-level and low-level
equilibrium on the basis of an extraneous random variable that they interpret as “animal spirits.”
Finally, none of the above-mentioned contributions attempts to identify and analyze the
agents that perform the role of coordinating markets in actual economies. A tradition going back
at least to J.B. Say identifies them as commercial enterprises – retailers, wholesalers, brokers,
jobbers, etc. These “shops” are the visible counterparts of Smith’s invisible hand. Howitt and
Clower (2000) show how a coherent network of shops can emerge from competitive evolution.
In their analysis no one has any understanding of the whole economy, yet the adaptive
adjustments made by shops seeking to profit by serving their individual markets often combine
to guide the whole system to a fully coordinated state. Ongoing theoretical research into the
dynamics of such a self-organizing network may provide further clues as to how coordination
normally works in a decentralized free-market economy, and why it occasionally fails.
Peter Howitt
Brown University
Providence, Rhode Island
6
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Clower, R. (1965), ‘The Keynesian Counter-revolution: A Theoretical Appraisal’ in F. Hahn and
F. Brechling (eds.) The Theory of Interest Rates, London: Macmillan.
Cooper, R. (1999), Coordination Games: Complementarities and Macroeconomics, New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Cooper, R., and A. John (1988), ‘Coordinating Coordination Failures in Keynesian Models’,
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 103, August, pp. 441-63.
Diamond, P. (1982), ‘Aggregate Demand Management in Search Equilibrium’, Journal of Political
Economy, 90, October, pp. 881-94.
Howitt, P. (1985), ‘Transaction Costs in the Theory of Unemployment’, American Economic
Review, 75, March, pp. 88-100.
Howitt, P. and P. McAfee (1992), ‘Animal Spirits’, American Economic Review, 82, June, pp.
493-507.
Howitt, P. and R. Clower (2000), ‘The Emergence of Economic Organization’, Journal of
Economic Behavior & Organization, 41, January, pp. 55-84.
Leijonhufvud, A. (1968), On Keynesian Economics and the Economics of Keynes: A Study in
Monetary Theory, New York: Oxford University Press.
Lucas, R. (1972), ‘Expectations and the Neutrality of Money’, Journal of Economic Theory, 4,
April, pp. 103-24.
Patinkin, D. (1948), ‘Price Flexibility and Full Employment’, American Economic Review, 38,
September, pp. 543-64.
Scarf, H. (1960), ‘Some Examples of Global Instability of the Competitive Equilibrium’,
International Economic Review, 1, September, pp. 157-72.