Kant Reading Guide
Kant Reading Guide
Reading Guide
Kant is difficult to read. As you read, try to focus on key ideas and arguments, and don’t get
discouraged. You will not understand every nuance of Kant’s position; you will likely understand les sof
what he is getting at than most of the other philosophers we have read this semester (or that you have
ever read). That’s all right. But try to get the main points of his text.
1. Kant uses the terms perception, appearance, object, thing, and thing in itself throughout this
book. Many of the most common misinterpretations of Kant arise from mistakenly reading the
term “appearance” to mean something like “mere appearance,” that is, an illusion of a thing, or
just an idea of a thing, or a perception of a thing. For Kant, the term “appearance” is
synonymous with the term “object,” and means “a thing that can appear.” Thus, for example,
Kant emphasizes that appearances are “real (i.e. objectively valid)” (A28/B44) that calling
something an “appearance in space” is a way of referring to “external objects” in space
(A30/B45). What is complicated about all of this is that Kant emphasizes that these
appearances/objects are not “things in themselves.” Thus Kant sets up a trichotomy between
(to use his example from p. 733a):
a. Merely subjective properties such as the color of the rose, which are “not…properties of
things, but merely…changes in ourselves as subjects”.
b. The objectively real objects/appearances/things that have those properties (the
objectively real rose)
c. The “thing in itself,” that is, what would be left of the rose were one to abstract from it
everything that makes it possible for it to be an object of possible experience.
2. Kant uses the term “experience” as a synonym for “empirical cognition,” that is, anything that
we can know from experience. Thus we can “experience” subatomic particles or dinosaurs,
since we can have empirical cognition of them. But a mere flurry of sensations passing over one
(as when very dizzy, for instance) isn’t a real “experience,” since it involves no cognitions of
objects.
3. Kant uses the term “transcendental” in a variety of ways throughout this book. Don’t assume
that you know what the word means, and don’t assume that it means the same thing as
“transcendent.”
Introduction (pp. 724-729, and addendumi). READ THE ADDENDUM IN THE ENDNOTE OF THIS READING
GUIDE BEFORE READING THE REST OF THE INTRODUCTION.
As you read the introduction, your main task should be to understand (though not necessarily to
answer) the question,
“How are synthetic judgments possible a priori?” (727a).
To do this, first get clear on what Kant means by “a priori” (vs. empirical) judgments, and by
“synthetic” (vs. analytic) judgments. Give examples of each kind of judgment in the following
table:
A priori A posteriori
(empirical)
Analytic
Synthetic
What are the criteria by which one could determine whether a judgment is analytic or
synthetic? A priori or empirical?
Now let’s answer the easy questions:
o How (if at all) are analytic a priori judgments possible?
o How (if at all) are analytic empirical judgments possible?
o How (if at all) are synthetic empirical judgments possible?
Why is Kant’s question – How are synthetic judgments possible a priori? – more difficult than
these?
And why doesn’t Kant add the “if at all” caveat? Does he have a good reason to think that
synthetic judgments are possible a priori? What?
Finally, what are the stakes of answering this question? In particular, why is it important for
metaphysics?
The Transcendental Aesthetic (pp. 729-737). The transcendental aesthetic is where Kant begins to
answer his question of how synthetic judgments are possible a priori, and it’s also where we begin to
see his “Copernican turn” (described in the Preface on p. 721a). As you read this section, keep turning
back to p. 721a and rereading this key paragraph (especially the lines just below Bxvii relating to “our
intuition of object). Note too that this section discusses both Space (pp. 729-733) and Time (733-737).
For our purposes, we will not be focusing on any important differences between these treatments.
Other than knowing that Kant makes similar arguments for both forms of intuition, you needn’t
particularly attend to the details of the arguments in the case of Time. That is, focus your reading on pp.
729-733. Both space and time, for Kant, are going to be a priori “intuitions,” so pay some attention to
Kant’s definition of an intuition as “that by which a cognition refers to objects” (729b). Put briefly, when
I have an empirical cognition of a dog, what makes that empirical cognition a cognition of a dog is the
concept “dog.” What makes the cognition a cognition of a dog – that is, a cognition of real object rather
than a mere playing with a concept – is that the concept dog is applied to an intuition of an object.
Kant’s discussions of Space and Time offer five arguments with respect to each intuition, four
“metaphysical” and one “transcendental.”
In his metaphysical exposition, Kant aims to show that Space is both a priori (rather than
empirical) and an intuition (rather than a concept), and he offers two arguments for each aspect
of his claim. Lay out these arguments. Do they show what Kant wants them to show? What are
the stakes of showing that Space is a priori? That it’s an intuition?
In his transcendental exposition, Kant aims to show that understanding Space as an a priori
intuition provides an answer to at least one version of his key question, that is, is explain how at
least some sorts of a priori synthetic judgments are possible. Does he succeed here? What are
the implications of this transcendental exposition for the legitimacy of his account of Space? Is
this transcendental exposition an argument for his claim that Space is an a priori intuition? (If
so, what sort of argument? If not, what’s the point of it?)
Finally, in his “Conclusions,” Kant introduces and defends his view that space is “empirically
real” but “transcendentally ideal” (732b). What is “empirical realism”? What is “transcendental
idealism”? Has Kant proven both, at least with respect to space?
The Analogies of Experience, Second Analogy (pp. 768, 772-779) Between the transcendental
aesthetic and the second analogy of experience, Kant does a lot of philosophical work that we are
skipping. In particular, we are skipping four important background steps on the way to his arguments
here.
1. The Transcendental Analytic of Transcendental Logic (pp. 737-42). The Transcendental Logic is
correlate to the transcendental aesthetic. In the aesthetic, Kant laid out our a priori intuitions,
while in the logic he lays out a priori concepts, which he calls “categories.” (For his preview of
this, see the Preface, right at Bxviii.) The Analytic part of this Transcendental Logic is where Kant
simply says what the categories are, without proving that they are necessary a priori. To see
Kant’s list of categories (grouped into four sets of three), see the Table on p. 740-41, which he
gets from the table of logical relations on p. 739.
2. The Transcendental Deduction (pp. 742-756). This is the densest, most difficult, and most
studied part of the first Critique, and the one that underwent the most significant revisions
between Kant’s first and second editions of the book. In brief, though, the purpose of this
argument is to show that the a priori concepts laid out in the previous section really are
necessary conditions of the possibility of having any cognition of any objects at all. I’ve put
some explanation of this argument in an endnote,ii for those who are interested.
3. The Schematism (pp. 756-759). In the Schematism, Kant explains that in order for a cognition to
arise from the unification of intuitions and concepts, our (a priori) concepts need to be made
into the sorts of concepts that can be applied to objects of experience. Thus we need a
“transcendental schema,” a way of understanding a priori concepts such that they can be
applied to spatial and temporal intuitions. This general schematism thus paves the way for
Kant’s “System of All Principles of Pure Understanding,” which is his explanation of the various
ways that a priori concepts, when schematized to be applied to possible objects, give rise to
principles that must hold for any of those possible objects. The second analogy lays out one of
those principles. (To see how it fits in, see the table on p. 762.)
4. The First Analogy of Experience (pp. 769-772). The results of this first principle are summarized
in the first paragraph of the second (772a-b, “The previous principle…”). Briefly, Kant just
proved (or tried to prove) that there are unchanging substances that underlie all changes in
objects. (This is part of your reading, but not a part we’ll focus on in class.)
The Analogies of Experience, Second Analogy (pp. 768, 772-779)
Before reading this section of the Kant, review the following quotations from Hume. Note what Hume
says we do experience and what he denies we experience.
“Suppose a person, though endowed with the strongest faculties of reason and reflection, to be brought
on a sudden into this world; he would, indeed, immediately observe a continual succession of objects,
and one event following another; but he would not be able to discover anything farther. He would not,
at first, by any reasoning, be able to reach the idea of cause and effect; since the particular powers, by
which all natural operations are performed, never appear to the senses; nor is it reasonable to conclude,
merely because one event, in one instance, precedes another, that therefore the one is the cause, the
other the effect. Their conjunction may be arbitrary and casual. There may be no reason to infer the
existence of one from the appearance of the other. And in a word, such a person, without more
experience, could never employ his conjecture or reasoning concerning any matter of fact, or be assured
of anything beyond what was immediately present to his memory and senses.” (549a)
“When we look about us towards external objects, and consider the operation of causes, we are never
able, in a single instance, to discover any power or necessary connexion; any quality, which binds the
effect to the cause, and renders the one an infallible consequence of the other. We only find, that the
one does actually, in fact, follow the other. The impulse of one billiard-ball is attended with motion in
the second. This is the whole that appears to the outward senses. The mind feels no sentiment or
inward impression from this succession of objects: consequently, there is not, in any single, particular
instance of cause and effect, any thing which can suggest the idea of power or necessary
connexion.”(557-8)
“It appears that, in single instances of the operation of bodies, we never can, by our utmost scrutiny,
discover any thing but one event following another, without being able to comprehend any force or
power by which the cause operates, or any connexion between it and its supposed effect. The same
difficulty occurs in contemplating the operations of mind on body--where we observe the motion of the
latter to follow upon the volition of the former, but are not able to observe or conceive the tie which
binds together the motion and volition, or the energy by which the mind produces this effect. The
authority of the will over its own faculties and ideas is not a whit more comprehensible: so that, upon
the whole, there appears not, throughout all nature, any one instance of connexion which is conceivable
by us. All events seem entirely loose and separate. One event follows another; but we never can observe
any tie between them. They seem conjoined, but never connected.” (562b)
Now let’s turn to Kant. We’ll focus on the Second Analogy. Look closely at what the claim of this
analogy is (italicized on 772a). Think about this claim in relation to Hume. What is Kant saying to
Hume?
The Analogies of Experience, Second Analogy (pp. 768, 772-779), continued.
Much of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is a series of arguments for “conditions of the possibility” of
various forms of empirical knowledge. Thus Kant’s transcendental aesthetic argues, among other things,
that an a priori intuition of space is a necessary condition of the possibility of geometry. In order to
know geometrical truths, we need to impose an a priori spatial structure on the world. This analogy,
likewise, is an argument about the “conditions of possibility” of alteration.
The argument depends upon Kant’s claims (in the transcendental deduction) that in order to cognize an
object as an object, we need to have a manifold of different perceptions (ideas about the thing) that we
unify into a cognition of a single object in accordance with categories provided by the understanding.
Kant now is trying to figure out how that works in the case of objective rather than subjective
succession, that is, in the case where one thing happens after another.
Throughout this discussion, it’s important to remember that appearances/objects are distinct from mere
perceptions. Kant is interested in figuring out how a merely subjective series of perceptions becomes a
genuine cognition of an object independent of us. (These “objects” are not the same as things in
themselves, but for now, try to ignore things in themselves and focus on the difference between
perceptions and objects.)
Kant offers an overview of his basic argument in the long paragraph on p. 772b. Spend at least 15
minutes with this paragraph, breaking down how the argument goes. You won’t be able to get
everything here, but try to get a sense for
1. What the problem of objective succession is (see especially the two sentences starting “I am,
therefore, conscious only” and ending with “leaves indeterminate the objective relation of the
appearances following one another.”)
2. How would you solve this problem?
3. How does Kant think this problem gets solved?
After spending some time with this paragraph, read through the section as a whole. Much of Kant’s
later discussion fleshes out key aspects of his argument here, so use it to help you understand what the
problem of objective succession is and how a law of necessary connection (cause and effect) solves that
problem.
After reading through the section as a whole, take some time to look at Kant’s two examples of the
house and the boat (p. 773).
1. What does our experience of the house have in common with our experience of the boat?
2. What is different?
3. How does Kant explain the possibility of this difference?
4. How might Hume?
Overall, then, what is Kant’s argument against Hume’s claims about our experiences? What do Hume
and Kant agree about? What do they disagree about? Who is correct?
The Third Antinomy (and its Solution), pp. 798-800, 811-19.
First, go back to the B-Preface and read p. 722 carefully. Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason has two main
parts, an “Analytic” in which Kant puts “metaphysics on the secure path of a science…where it deals
with those a priori concepts for which corresponding objects…can be given in experience” (722a), and a
“Dialectic” in which Kant shows that “with this faculty to cognize a priori we will never be able to go
beyond the limits of possible experience” (722a). The Antinomies are part of that second part of the
Critique. So look closely at the rest of p. 722 to get a sense for how Kant aims to establish this latter
claim.
Now go to pp. 798-800. Note that these pages are formatted in such a way that there are really two
parallel arguments in the right and left columns of each page. Thus, at the top of 798a, there is a thesis,
which is defended and commented on in the “A” columns of pp. 798-800. At the top of 798b, there is an
antithesis, which is defended and commented on in the “B” columns of pp. 798-800.
And now, let’s look for the “Solution” to this Antinomy. Here, finally, “things in themselves” play an
important role in Kant’s philosophy.
Now go back (again) and reread the B-Preface, pp. 722-724. Has Kant successfully “den[ied] knowledge
in order to make room for faith” (724b)?
Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason, selections.iii
INTRODUCTION
I. THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PURE AND EMPIRICAL KNOWLEDGE
THERE can be no doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience. For how should our faculty of knowledge be
awakened into action did not objects affecting our senses partly of themselves produce representations, partly arouse the
activity of our understanding to compare these representations, and, by combining or separating them, work up the raw
material of the sensible impressions into that knowledge of objects which is entitled experience? In the order of time,
therefore, we have no knowledge antecedent to experience, and with experience all our knowledge begins. But though all
our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all arises out of experience. For it may well be that even
our empirical knowledge is made up of what we receive through impressions and of what our own faculty of knowledge
(sensible impressions serving merely as the occasion) supplies from itself. If our faculty of knowledge makes any such
addition, it may be that we are not in a position to distinguish it from the raw material, until with long practice of
attention we have become skilled in separating it.
This, then, is a question which at least calls for closer examination, and does not allow of any off-hand answer: --
whether there is any knowledge that is thus independent of experience and even of all impressions of the senses. Such
knowledge is entitled a priori, and distinguished from the empirical, which has its sources a posteriori, that is, in experience.
The expression 'a priori' does not, however, indicate with sufficient precision the full meaning of our question. For it has
been customary to say, even of much knowledge that is derived from empirical sources, that we have it or are capable of
having it a priori, meaning thereby that we do not derive it immediately from experience, but from a universal rule – a
rule which is itself, however, borrowed by us from experience. Thus we would say of a man who undermined the
foundations of his house, that he might have known a priori that it would fall, that is, that he need not have waited for
the experience of its actual falling. But still he could not know this completely a priori. For he had first to learn through
experience that bodies are heavy, and therefore fall when their supports are withdrawn.
In what follows, therefore, we shall understand by a priori knowledge, not knowledge independent of this or that
experience, but knowledge absolutely independent of all experience. Opposed to it is empirical knowledge, which is
knowledge possible only a posteriori, that is, through experience. A priori modes of knowledge are entitled pure when
there is no admixture of anything empirical. Thus, for instance, the proposition, 'every alteration has its cause', while an a
priori proposition, is not a pure proposition, because alteration is a concept which can be derived only from experience.
II. WE ARE IN POSSESSION OF CERTAIN MODES OF A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE, AND EVEN THE
COMMON UNDERSTANDING IS NEVER WITHOUT THEM
What we here require is a criterion by which to distinguish with certainty between pure and empirical knowledge.
Experience teaches us that a thing is so and so, but not that it cannot be otherwise. First, then, if we have a proposition
which in being thought is thought as necessary, it is an a priori judgment; and if, besides, it is not derived from any
proposition except one which also has the validity of a necessary judgment, it is an absolutely a priori judgment. Secondly,
experience never confers on its judgments true or strict but only assumed and comparative universality, through
induction. We can properly only say, therefore, that so far as we have hitherto observed, there is no exception to this or
that rule. If, then, a judgment is thought with strict universality, that is, in such manner that no exception is allowed as
possible, it is not derived from experience, but is valid absolutely a priori. Empirical universality is only an arbitrary
extension of a validity holding in most cases to one which holds in all, for instance, in the proposition, 'all bodies are
heavy'. When, on the other hand, strict universality is essential to a judgment, this indicates a special source of
knowledge, namely, a faculty of a priori knowledge. Necessity and strict universality are thus sure criteria of a priori
knowledge, and are inseparable from one another. But since in the employment of these criteria the contingency of
judgments is sometimes more easily shown than their empirical limitation, or, as sometimes also happens, their unlimited
universality can be more convincingly proved than their necessity, it is advisable to use the two criteria separately, each
by itself being infallible.
Now it is easy to show that there actually are in human knowledge judgments which are necessary and in the strictest
sense universal, and which are therefore pure a priori judgments. If an example from the sciences be desired, we have
only to look to any of the propositions of mathematics; if we seek an example from the understanding in its quite
ordinary employment, the proposition, 'every alteration must have a cause', will serve our purpose. In the latter case,
indeed, the very concept of a cause so manifestly contains the concept of a necessity of connection with an effect and
of the strict universality of the rule, that the concept would be altogether lost if we attempted to derive it, as Hume has
done, from a repeated association of that which happens with that which precedes, and from a custom of connecting
representations, a custom originating in this repeated association, and constituting therefore a merely subjective
necessity. Even without appealing to such examples, it is possible to show that pure a priori principles are indispensable
for the possibility of experience, and so to prove their existence a priori. For whence could experience derive its certainty,
if all the rules, according to which it proceeds, were always themselves empirical, and therefore contingent? Such rules
could hardly be regarded as first principles. At present, however, we may be content to have established the fact that our
faculty of knowledge does have a pure employment, and to have shown what are the criteria of such an employment.
Such a priori origin is manifest in certain concepts, no less than in judgments. If we remove from our empirical concept
of a body, one by one, every feature in it which is [merely] empirical, the colour, the hardness or softness, the weight,
even the impenetrability, there still remains the space which the body (now entirely vanished) occupied, and this cannot
be removed. Again, if we remove from our empirical concept of any object, corporeal or incorporeal, all properties
which experience has taught us, we yet cannot take away that property through which the object is thought as substance
or as inhering in a substance (although this concept of substance is more determinate than that of an object in general).
Owing, therefore, to the necessity with which this concept of substance forces itself upon us, we have no option save to
admit that it has its seat in our faculty of a priori knowledge.
ii
The key move in this argument is Kant’s claim that experience is possible only by virtue of a twofold “unity,” on
the side of both the “object” and the “apperception” of that object. For Kant, “apperception” refers to “the ‘I think’
[that] must be able to accompany all of my representations, for otherwise something would be represented in me that
could not be thought at all” (B131-2). Kant’s basic idea in this section of the Critique is to connect experience of
unified objects with a unified “I think” and thereby with the categories, as the principles of any such unity. First,
Kant argues that in order for one to unite different representations together into consciousness of a single object,
those different representations must be held together in a single consciousness. To have a cognition of a purple cow,
it will not do for one person to have a representation of the color purple and another to have a representation of a
cow. These different representations, to be united into a cognition of a single object, must be united by a single
consciousness.
[C]ognitions . . . consist in the determinate relation of a given representation to an object. But an object is that
in the concept of which the manifold of a given intuition is united. Now, however, all unification of
representations requires unity of consciousness. Consequently the unity of consciousness is that which alone
constitutes the relation of representations to an object. (B 137)
The relevant unity of consciousness here is not that “subjective unity of consciousness which is a determination of
inner sense” (B139), that is, it is not an introspective awareness of oneself as united throughout time. Rather, the
relevant unity is the from-within unity by virtue of which one becomes conscious of and makes justifiable claims
about objects in the world.
Now just as the table of judgment provided Kant’s “clue” to discovering a set of a priori categories, so he
argues that we see, in the form of judgment itself, a necessary appeal to this transcendental unity: “a judgment is
nothing other than the way to bring given cognitions to the objective unity of apperception. That is the aim of the
copula is in them . . . For this word designates the relation of the representations to the original apperception and its
[apperception’s] necessary unity, even if the judgment itself is empirical” (B 141-2). In other words, in making a
judgment such as “mangos are delicious,” one not only makes an empirical claim about the world but implicitly
asserts the necessary unity of the I that holds together “mangos” and “delicious” in a single “I think.” And now Kant
comes to his punchline:
Therefore the manifold [of different representations], insofar as it is given in one empirical intuition, is
determined in regard to one of the logical functions for judgment, by means of which . . . it is brought to a
consciousness in general. But . . . the categories are nothing other than these very functions for judging, insofar
as the manifold of a given intuition is determined with regard to them. Thus the manifold in a given intuition
also necessarily stands under categories. (B 143)
Thus if, e.g., I make the empirical intuition of a house into perception through apperception of its manifold, my
ground is the necessary unity of space . . . This same synthetic unity, however, if I abstract from the form of
space, has its seat in the understanding, . . . in the category of quantity. (B162)
Our “apperception” of objects is unified through organizing various representations together by means of a priori
concepts of the understanding such as unity, reality, or causation. Even spatial and temporal properties of an object
only become properties of an object when subsumed together by the understanding, under concepts such as
“property (of a substance).” These a priori concepts, or categories, provide a from-within structure by means of
which a human knower can connect representations in such a way that those representations remain part of a single
“I think,” and they provide the framework according to which a mere “manifold” can become a coherent object of
experience.
At this point, one clarificatory warning is needed lest one think that Kant’s transcendental anthropology
does (or claims) more than it really does. Rene Descartes, too, emphasizes the importance of the “I think,” claiming
that he could be absolutely certain of the claim, “I think therefore I am” and reasoning, even further, that the nature
of the “I think” implies the simplicity, unity, and ultimately immortality of the human soul. For Kant, however, such
inferences mistakenly treat the transcendental unity of apperception that makes (empirical) cognition possible as
itself a possible object of (such) cognition. In his transcendental deduction, Kant emphasizes that while the
“transcendental synthesis of the manifold” makes me conscious “that I am,” it reveals neither what “I am in myself”
nor how “I appear to myself” (B157). Kant criticizes attempts to get from the formal requirements of the “I think” to
substantive claims about such an I, calling such attempts “Paralogisms,” or invalid arguments (see A341/B399-
A404/B431). For example, the inference from the necessity of a unified “subject” of thought to a unified thinking
“substance” erroneously takes the formal category of “subject” to have objective meaning, when “pure categories
(and among them also the category of substance) have in themselves no objective significance . . . unless an intuition
is subsumed under them” (A348-9). Because one can have no intuition of the “I think” that unifies all intuitions, the
only possible objective cognition of oneself is of “our own subject only as appearance,” and this is available
“through inner sense” (B156). And Kant argues in a “Refutation of [Cartesian] Idealism” (B274-9) that knowledge
of this empirical self is secondary to knowledge of external objections, since “the determination of my existence in
time is possible only by means of . . . actual [persisting] things that I perceive outside myself” (B 275). Kant’s
appeal to the transcendental unity of apperception is an explanation of cognition from-within, one that shows that
objective empirical cognition requires unifying one’s representations by means of a priori categories. It thereby
shows that the objective world must be unified in that way, but it makes no objective claims about the apperception
that unified that world.
iii
Selection from Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Thomas Abbott,
available at http://philosophy.eserver.org/kant/critique-of-practical-
reaso.txt
V. PROBLEM I.
REMARK.