The Real Numbers
The Real Numbers
√
1 The Irrationality of 2
“Real mathematics must be justified as art if
it can be justified at all.”
Hardy 1940 - A mathematician’s apology
p2 = 2q 2
p2 is an even number(it is divisible by 2) ⇒ p = 2r, where r is also an integer
2r2 = q 2
q 2 is even ⇒ p and q are both even (i.e., divisible by 2)
no common factor!!!!
Prior to the preceding discovery: two line segments AB and CD - always be possible to find a third
line segment whose length divides evenly into first two. Pythagoreans - interpreted any number to
mean rational number ⇒ number was a strictly weaker notion than length.
Modern terminology: length of CD is a rational multiple of the length of AB
1
Natural numbers perform addition
Integers
Z = {..., −3, −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, 3, ...}
additive identity (zero)
additive inverses necessary to define subtraction
multiplication and division
Rational numbers Q = { All fractions pq where p and q are integers with q 6= 0 } properties of Q:
make up the definition of what is called a field
Definition 1.1 (Field). Any set where addition and multiplication are well-defined operations (commu-
tative, associative, obey the familiar distributive property a(b+c) = ab+ac).
finite set 0, 1, 2, 3, 4 - considered field when addition and multiplication are computed modulo 5
R is obtained by filling in the gaps in Q
2 Some Preliminaries
2.1 Sets
E ∩ S = ∅ ⇒ E and S are disjoint
set ∅ - called the empty
apply the union and intersection operations to infinite collections of sets
A1 = N = {1, 2, 3, ...}
A2 = {2, 3, 4, ...}
A3 = {3, 4, 5, ...}
for each n ∈ N , define the set
An = {n, n + 1, n + 2, ...}
The result is a nested chain of sets
A1 ⊇ A2 ⊇ A3 ⊇ A4 ⊇ .....
where each successive set is a subset of all the previous ones
∞
[
An
n=1
or [
An
n∈N
or
A1 ∪ A2 ∪ A3 ∪ .....
2
any element that appears in at least one particular An
∞
[
An = A1
n=1
Intersection
∞
\
An = ∅
n=1
Explanation:
Suppose we have m that might satisfy m ∈ ∩∞
n=1 An ⇒ m/inAn f oreveryAn
But m is not an element of Am+1
2.2 Functions
Definition 2.1 (Function).
Given two sets A and B, a function from A to B is a rule or mapping that takes each element x ∈ A
and associates with it a single element of B. The set A is called the domain of f. The range of f is not
necessarily equal to B but refers to the subset of B given by y ∈ B : y = f (x) for some x ∈ A by Peter
Lejeune Dirichlet (1805-1859) in 1830s. His main motivation was to unravel the issues surrounding the
convergence of Fourier series.
|a + b| ≤ |a| + |b| ⇔
|a − b| = |(a − c) + (c − b)| ⇒
By the triangle inequality
|(a − c) + (c − b)| ≤ |a − c| + |c − b| ⇒
|a − b| ≤ |a − c| + |c − b|
3
Proof.
The converse statement: (⇐) If for every real number > 0 it follows that |a − b| < , then we
must have a = b.
first statement - direct proof
second statement - proof by contradiction
The conclusion is a = b we assume that a 6= b. “for every > 0”
a 6= b ⇒ 0 = |a − b| > 0
|a − b| < is true for every > 0 ⇒
|a − b| < 0
|a − b| < 0 and |a − b| = 0 cannot both be true ⇒
means that our initial assumption that a 6= b is unacceptable
Therefore, a = b
2.4 Induction
fundamental principle behind induction: if S is some subset of N with the property mathematics
S contains 1
whenever S contains a natural number n, it also contains n + 1, then it must be that S = N
Example: Let x1 = 1, and for each n ∈ N define
1
xn+1 = xn + 1
2
1 3
x2 = ( )(1) + 1 =
2 2
7
x3 =
4
...
it leads to definition of xn for all n ∈ N .
x1 ≤ x2 ≤ x3
first let’s show (2)
xn ≤ xn+1
for all values of n ∈ N .
n = 1, x1 = 1 and x2 = 3/2 ⇒ x1 ≤ x2
xn ≤ xn+1 ⇒ xn ≤ xn + 1?
xn ≤ xn+1 ⇒
1 1
xn ≤ xn+1 ⇒
2 2
1 1
xn + 1 ≤ xn+1 + 1
2 2
the claim is proved for all n ∈ N
4
3 The Axiom of Completeness
Augustin Louis Cauchy (1789-1857), Bernhard Bolzano (1781-1848), Niels Henrik Abel (1802-1829), Peter
Lejeune Dirichlet, KarlWeierstrass (1815-1897), and Bernhard Riemann (1826-1866). Nearly all of this
work was done using intuitive assumptions about the nature of R.
R - ordered field , which contains Q as a subfield.
R does not contain the gaps that permeate Q. Because this is the defining difference between the ra-
tional numbers and the real numbers, we will be excessively precise about how we phrase this assumption,
hereafter referred to as the Axiom of Completeness.
Definition 3.1 (Axiom of Completeness.). Every nonempty set of real numbers that is bounded above
has a least upper bound.
5
there is. Back in R, the Axiom of Completeness states that we may set = supS and be confident that
such a number exists. In the next section, we will prove that 2 = 2. But according to Theorem 1.1.1, this
implies is not a rational number. If we are restricting our attention to only rational numbers, then is
not an allowable option for sup S, and the search for a least upper bound goes on indefinitely. Whatever
rational upper bound is discovered, it is always possible to find one smaller. The tools needed to carry
out the computations described in Example 1.3.6 depend on results about how Q and N fit inside of R.
These are discussed in the next section. In the meantime, it is possible to prove some intuitive algebraic
properties of least upper bounds just using the definition. Example 1.3.7. Let A R be nonempty and
bounded above, and let c R. Define the set c + A by c + A = c + a : a A. Then sup(c + A) = c
+ supA. To properly verify this we focus separately on each part of Definition 1.3.2. Setting s = supA,
we see that a s for all a A, which implies c+a c+s for all a A. Thus, c + s is an upper bound for c
+ A and condition (i) is verified. For (ii), let b be an arbitrary upper bound for c + A; i.e., c + a b
for all a A. This is equivalent to a bc for all a A, from which we conclude that bc is an upper bound
for A. Because s is the least upper bound of A, s bc, which can be rewritten as c + s b. This verifies
part (ii) of Definition 1.3.2, and we conclude sup(c + A) = c + supA. There is an equivalent and useful
way of characterizing least upper bounds. As the previous example illustrates, Definition 1.3.2 of the
supremum has two parts. Part (i) says that supA must be an upper bound, and part (ii) states that it
must be the smallest one. The following lemma offers an alternative way to restate part (ii). Lemma
1.3.8. Assume s R is an upper bound for a set A R. Then, s = supA if and only if, for every choice of
¿ 0, there exists an element a A satisfying s ¡ a. 18 Chapter 1. The Real Numbers Proof. Here is a
short rephrasing of the lemma: Given that s is an upper bound, s is the least upper bound if and only if
any number smaller than s is not an upper bound. Putting it this way almost qualifies as a proof, but
we will expand on what exactly is being said in each direction. () For the forward direction, we assume s
= supA and consider s, where ¿ 0 has been arbitrarily chosen. Because s ¡ s, part (ii) of Definition 1.3.2
implies that s is not an upper bound for A. If this is the case, then there must be some element a A
for which s ¡ a (because otherwise s would be an upper bound). This proves the lemma in one direction.
() Conversely, assume s is an upper bound with the property that no matter how ¿ 0 is chosen, s is
no longer an upper bound for A. Notice that what this implies is that if b is any number less than s,
then b is not an upper bound. (Just let = sb.) To prove that s = supA, we must verify part (ii) of
Definition 1.3.2. (Read it again.) Because we have just argued that any number smaller than s cannot
be an upper bound, it follows that if b is some other upper bound for A, then s b. It is certainly the case
that all of our conclusions to this point about least upper bounds have analogous versions for greatest
lower bounds. The Axiom of Completeness does not explicitly assert that a nonempty set bounded below
has an infimum, but this is because we do not need to assume this fact as part of the axiom. Using the
Axiom of Completeness, there are several ways to prove that greatest lower bounds exist for nonempty
bounded sets. One such proof is explored in Exercise 1.3.3. Exercises Exercise 1.3.1. (a) Write a formal
definition in the style of Definition 1.3.2 for the infimum or greatest lower bound of a set. (b) Now, state
and prove a version of Lemma 1.3.8 for greatest lower bounds. Exercise 1.3.2. Give an example of each
of the following, or state that the request is impossible. (a) A set B with inf B sup B. (b) A finite set
that contains its infimum but not its supremum. (c) A bounded subset of Q that contains its supremum
but not its infimum. Exercise 1.3.3. (a) Let A be nonempty and bounded below, and define B = b R :
b is a lower bound for A. Show that supB = inf A. (b) Use (a) to explain why there is no need to assert
that greatest lower bounds exist as part of the Axiom of Completeness. Exercise 1.3.4. Let A1,A2,A3, .
. . be a collection of nonempty sets, each of which is bounded above. 1.3. The Axiom of Completeness
19 (a) Find a formula for sup(A1A2). Extend this to sup ( n k=1 Ak). (b) Consider sup (
k=1 Ak). Does the formula in (a) extend to the infinite case? Exercise 1.3.5. As in Example 1.3.7,
let A R be nonempty and bounded above, and let c R. This time define the set cA = ca : a A. (a) If
c 0, show that sup(cA) = c supA. (b) Postulate a similar type of statement for sup(cA) for the case c ¡
0. Exercise 1.3.6. Given sets A and B, define A+B = a+b : a A and b B. Follow these steps to prove
that if A and B are nonempty and bounded above then sup(A + B) = supA + supB. (a) Let s = supA
and t = supB. Show s + t is an upper bound for A + B. (b) Now let u be an arbitrary upper bound for
A + B, and temporarily fix a A. Show t u a. (c)
6
4 Consequences of Completeness
5 Cardinality
6 Cantor’s Theorem
7 Epilogue