Ayling Simon 2012
Ayling Simon 2012
Cyberpunk Criticism.
This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the University of
Western Australia. Submitted through the School of Humanities, Discipline of
History, in 2012.
Abstract
lens of the history of ideas, it examines cyberpunk critique for academic trends, and
for critical successes and absences. In the course of its analysis, this dissertation
examines key themes in the genre criticism. These include the influence of
posthumanist philosophy on cyberpunk criticism; the idea of the posthuman and its
place in the critical literature; the key role of feminist criticism in the formation of the
lastly, the role of history and the idea of historicity in cyberpunk fiction and critique.
It finds that the majority of cyberpunk critics analyse the genre using the critical tools
discourse constructed upon these twin pillars, it concludes that the lack of
been provided by humanism, has created lacunae within the genre discourse.
1. Introduction.
pp. 1-37.
7. Conclusion.
pp. 248-254.
i
Preface
have come to be. That being said, the germ of the idea for this thesis quickly took
in a single space. I have loved science fiction literature since I was a child, and
cyberpunk has held a fascination for me since I first read Gibson’s Neuromancer.
I wrote a joint Honours degree in History and Philosophy, and this project has
formed the basis for this study would have been very difficult for me to
has been a key part of this dissertation. The combination of both philosophical
cyberpunk critique to places which I could not have imagined six years ago,
makes cyberpunk an attractive prospect for one to write about, both as a critic
and as an intellectual historian?’ I have several answers to this question, and they
Neuromancer at 16, when a friend lent me his copy. I bought my own copy part
way through my reading, because I knew I was going to want to read it again and
ii
cyberpunk, and the critical literature which has been written about it, enables me
to explore these themes, whilst retaining the connection to the literature which I
moment, one which has always fascinated me. The political, economic and
degree, crisis. Cyberpunk is the literature of that crisis, and allows us a vision of
the time which is both enthralling and apposite. Similarly, the critical literature
written about cyberpunk allows a continuing view of the ways in which scholars
have read that vision of crisis, allowing a survey of critical thought across time.
Teasing out the threads of our time's intellectual dynamic is a project which I
find enthralling, and the opportunity to pursue this enterprise with cyberpunk
It will rapidly become obvious to anyone reading this thesis that, despite
my passion for cyberpunk, and indeed my great respect for the critical discourse
which has grown up about it, I have certain intellectual filiations which, at times,
to one’s biases prior to the commencement of a study, and this is no bad thing.
We can no longer pretend (if indeed ‘we’, meaning historians, ever really did
and of course the personality, passion and biases of the interpreter will come
iii
first read Habermas, I have been convinced by his argument that the project of
simply a product of my own subject position; I am, after all, a well educated,
particularly deserved the privileges which have come to me, but that everyone
does, and that the project of the Enlightenment, ultimately, is about the extension
of opportunity to all. This is why I find the future imagined in cyberpunk both
intellectual affiliations which inflect our work. With that in mind, it is perhaps
guide for both the historical and the critical components of this thesis. However
remain vital by absorbing critiques and recognising the need for change. I hope
iv
thesis.
begin, my project without the assistance of the people and institutions outlined
Postgraduate Award scholarship, and then in the concluding stages of the project
Coudray and Associate Professor Rob Stuart, I owe an immense debt. Doctor
Bourgault provided key criticisms early in the project, and Professor Stuart has
He has read each and every draft of my work with a keen eye, and if this
dissertation is cogent and concise, then much of the credit for that must go to his
careful editing. Of course, any errors, omissions and infelicities in the text
remain entirely my own. Lastly, without the support offered by my friends and
particularly my parents, this dissertation would never have seen the light of day.
1
This thesis will examine the ways in which cyberpunk science fiction,
philosophy) and culture intertwine and affect each other. It will argue that,
through the lens of genre critique, the social and intellectual trends of the time,
both the times of the primary works and of the critical texts, can be observed and
analysed. Cyberpunk is a primary site for study of the culture of the 1980s.1
is both a possible and fruitful line of enquiry, however, certain underlying issues
must be addressed. In this first chapter, it will first be argued that the history of
ideas, with a method substantially different from that of literary theory, provides
insight into the formation of the critical literature on cyberpunk. Following from
this, the relationship between science fiction and philosophy will be examined.
1
Science fiction reference materials usually firmly site cyberpunk in the culture of the 1980s.
See, for example, John Kessel, ‘Cyberpunk’, in James Gunn (ed.), The New Encyclopedia of
Science Fiction, Viking Penguin, New York, 1988, pp. 116-118, p. 116; Adam Roberts, The
History of Science Fiction, Palgrave Macmillan, New York, 2006, p. 311; Edward James, Science
Fiction in the 20th Century, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1994, pp. 198-199; Roger
Luckhurst, Science Fiction, Polity Press, Cambridge, 2005, pp. 206-213; Mark Bould and Sherryl
Vint, The Routledge Concise History of Science Fiction, Routledge, Abingdon, 2011, pp. 254-
160. Kessel is keen to position cyberpunk in opposition to its direct antecedents in the science
fiction of the 1970s, and James and Roberts note that the main concerns of cyberpunk are
particularly germane to the culture of the 1980s. Luckhurst identifies four interlocking aspects of
William Gibson’s first trilogy which make it ‘such a quintessential embodiment of the
postmodern 1980s.’ These are, respectively, the arch-capitalist nature of the societies portrayed; a
dominance of technology maintained alongside an ambivalent relationship with said technology;
a dense and pastiche-driven prose style; and lastly, a mournful elegiac attitude towards the past
buried under the weight of technological change. Luckhurst’s summary is excellent, particularly
for identifying that the cyberpunk relationship with technology is more nuanced than has often
been recognised. Bould and Vint note similar themes to Luckhurst.
2
Frederic Jameson, Postmodernism: Or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Duke University
Press, Durham, 1991, p. 419.
2
writing will be seen to provide insights into key areas of cultural and
theme, however, it is often restricted in the texts which it discusses. This in turn
imposes certain restriction on this thesis. The reasons for these truncated
discussions are complex, and worthy of discussion before proceeding with the
bulk of the thesis. Primarily, however, this introduction will present the
argument that intellectual history, and the hermeneutic method, can provide a
novel and productive insight into the links between cyberpunk science fiction,
The history of ideas has, in recent times, taken a turn around the post.
made their home in intellectual history. The effect of the incursion of these new
critical methods on the discipline has been a “linguistic turn.” Intellectual history
has, under the guidance of luminaries such as Hayden White and Dominick
3
For Skinner’s lengthy and thorough exegesis on this and other points in the history of ideas, see
Quentin Skinner, ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’, History and Theory, 8:1,
1969, pp. 3-53. For programmatic essays by LaCapra and White, Dominick La Capra,
‘Rethinking Intellectual History and Reading Texts,’ History and Theory, 19:3, 1980, pp. 245-
276, and Hayden White, ‘The Context in the Text: Method and Ideology in Intellectual History’,
in Hayden White, The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation,
1987.
3
all, have evolved from literary theory, and it is popular literature and its
criticism, rather than canonical “old school” philosophy, with which this text
wrestles. However, the new approaches pioneered by LaCapra, White and others
historian; at worst, they risk abandonment of any realistic “conversation with the
past” in favour of a sort of conversation with ourselves that could be had without
treat history simply as the description of past events; that no “conversation” need
be had at all. This way of viewing history has two obvious problems. The first is
history, nor satisfies people who ask “What’s the point?” The second problem
with such a position is that even the slightest recognition of the subjectivity
problem (via the hermeneutic circle or otherwise) makes the construction of this
(in both senses of the word ‘present’). However, even when recognising the
production of meaning is simply the play of signs without referents, then the
need for history seems questionable. As John Toews has put it, ‘Reading
LaCapra’s critical commentaries [on the history of ideas], one begins to wonder
4
See, for example, Frank Ankersmit, ‘Historiography and Postmodernism’, History and Theory,
28:2, 1989, pp. 137-153; Frank Ankersmit, ‘Historical Representation’, History and Theory, 27:3,
1988, pp. 205-228; and Hayden White, The Content of the Form.
4
all without ceasing to ‘do’ history and restricting oneself to thinking about it.’ 5
however, with the recovery of meaning. Firstly, meaning is not obvious in texts
or contexts (particularly not in the texts and contexts of the fictional literature
which makes up a considerable portion of the primary sources for this thesis).
We may know perfectly well what a text means to us on first glance, but this can
hardly take into account the full vagaries of meaning. If it did, intellectual
historians and literary critics alike would be looking for other work. Given that
this is not the way to do things, what is? How does one determine whether the
outcomes? This is where the ‘old’ intellectual history and the new manifest their
extreme is more closely associated with the older style of intellectual history –
that advocated by Skinner, Pocock and others. Skinner’s method consists of the
analysis. Once this has been achieved, and the meaning (or potential meanings)
5
John Toews, ‘Intellectual History after the Linguistic Turn: The Autonomy of Meaning and the
Irreducibility of Experience,’ American Historical Review, 92:4, 1987, pp. 879-907, p. 886.
6
LaCapra, ‘Rethinking Intellectual History,’ esp. pp. 272-276.
5
of the text has been rediscovered, the job of the intellectual historian is done. 7
Nonetheless, no historian can hold a viable ‘conversation with the past’ without
first making an attempt to discover what, as it were, the past was saying.
intention, this is only the beginning of the story which intellectual history can
and should examine. The ‘career’ of the text after it is written is more than a
intentions of the author. Paul Ricoeur has pointed out that with
written discourse, the author’s intention and the meaning of the text
cease to coincide… Not that we can conceive of a text without an
author; the tie between the speaker and the discourse is not abolished,
but distended and complicated. The dissociation of the meaning and the
intention is still an adventure of the reference of discourse to the
speaking subject. But the text’s career escapes the finite horizon of its
author. 9
7
See Quentin Skinner, ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’, pp. 3-53. LaCapra’s
criticism of this pure “documentary” approach is apt, but on reading further into Skinner’s
articles after the publication of ‘Meaning and Understanding’, one begins to wonder if this is
really Skinner’s approach at all. Skinner seems to have presented his arguments in very
aggressive form, and subsequently amended them to a significant degree. In fact, the position
adopted by Skinner later in his career is not so very far from LaCapra’s own. For an example of
this moderation of Skinner’s original, fairly extreme position, see Quentin Skinner,
‘Hermeneutics and the Role of History”, New Literary History, 7, 1975, pp. 209-232.
8
LaCapra, ‘Rethinking Intellectual History,’ p. 272.
8
Paul Ricoeur, ‘The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as a Text,’ New Literary
History, 5, 1973, pp. 91-117, p. 95. Emphasis in original text.
6
such will make up a substantial part of the analytic content of this thesis. If we
that intellectual historians seek to reconstruct, study and participate in, then the
history of ideas.
to “take on” the great texts and to attain a level of understanding and perhaps of
language use that contends with them.’ 10 It is not completely clear precisely what
it is that LaCapra here suggests; however it seems that he argues that we, as
historians, should engage with our texts on a more openly interpretative level.
This, in itself, seems like an excellent idea. If there is any point in developing a
LaCapra, however, recognises that this method, applied on its own, runs the risk
uncertain. On the one hand, he invokes “the facts” to put limits on creative
method apparently leaves him without this resource. We may, for the purposes of
establishing “the facts” have to accept the use of what LaCapra terms the
9
LaCapra, ‘Rethinking Intellectual History,’ p. 273.
11
LaCapra, ‘Rethinking Intellectual History,’ p. 274.
7
establishing as nearly as possible what original texts meant, in their own terms,
in their own times, is as good a beginning as we can ever have. This should not,
however, be the end of the process. As Skinner points out, even if we “know”
what the correct reading is, the other readings do not have to be discarded.
Skinner argues, to the contrary, that the ‘status of the one uniquely correct
reading … can only be that it represents one good reading amongst others.’12
The other readings may then become “incorrect”, but they still have
intellectual history. For if we do view the original text as the opening sentence in
sentence was, and also how people have responded to it. LaCapra’s warning
apt. It is a method prone to misuse, even by the well intentioned. However, his
“facts” of the past to determine interpretative accuracy in the present when one is
the potential pitfalls in interpreting the ‘facts’ of past texts, and, in awareness of
these traps, proceed with attempting to establish the facts anyway. We can either
allow the point that all historical facts are also interpretations to blind our eyes to
the goals of historical analysis, and continue to engage in largely fruitless meta-
history by recent trends, and yet persist with the work of being historians. Again,
12
Quentin Skinner, `Hermeneutics and the Role of History', New Literary History, 7:1, 1975, pp.
209-233, p. 226. For Skinner, of course, the ‘correct’ reading is that which is the best expression
of authorial intention.
8
Overinterpretation. Eco divides the potential for the creation of meaning in texts
into three component parts – the intentio auctoris (authorial intention), the
intentio lectoris (the intention of the reader), and, critically for Eco, the intentio
operas, the intended meaning, as it were, of the text itself. 13 For Eco, the
‘intention of the empirical author’, as the actual person who wrote the text, is
‘radically useless.’ 14 In saying this, Eco is not, of course, implying that the
author herself is useless – rather that ‘Since the intention of the text is to produce
a model reader able to make conjectures about it, the initiative of the reader
consists in figuring out a model author that is not the empirical one…’ 15 What
this essentially means is that the author that the reader sees in the text is not the
actual author, but an ideal author extracted in reverse from the text the author
establishing what the text in question could legitimately have meant to the actual
author, and thus to her contemporary readers. Eco’s focus is, to use LaCapra’s
vocabulary, more presentist – he wishes to understand what the text can mean to
13
See Umberto Eco, ‘Interpretation and History’, pp. 23-43, p. 25 and ‘Overinterpreting Texts’,
pp. 44-73, pp. 61-66, in S. Collini (ed.), Interpretation and Overinterpretation, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1992.
14
Eco, ‘Overinterpreting Texts’, p. 66.
15
Eco, ‘Overinterpreting Texts’, p. 64.
9
us, or to readers at any other time for that matter. For the purposes of this thesis,
both foci will be necessary. In order to understand not just the foundational texts
the former, one will have to accept that authorial intention, even if it is the
Rather, he introduces the concept of intentio operas, the intention of the work
‘Between Author and Text,’ Eco seems to be making an appeal for reasonable
interpretation – for looking for interpretations that, as it were, the text to some
degree encourages, rather than simply hunting down the things that we wish to
find in it. 16 Eco recognises, as many no longer seem to, that the text itself is a
point of some solidity. As he puts it, ‘Between the mysterious history of a textual
production and the uncontrollable drift of its future readings, the text qua text
subjectivity of our history writing, write history anyway, the critical question for
the historian then becomes ‘How do we write the best history?’ What method
and understanding of the historical craft allows both the acknowledgement of our
subjective position, but also the full engagement of our subjectivity with our
past, the elusive beast which we study? Many attempts have been made to
come with the general challenges made to logical positivism and its various
Gadamer and his various disciples, has increasingly become the framework
around which historical method is based. Hermeneutic theory offers the historian
a powerful method for interpreting and interacting with the past, one which
acknowledges the historian’s own historical position, yet which will also, when
well applied, not result in the gross subjectivism which Dominick LaCapra so
rightly fears. This is not to say that this moderate position between the
is in itself. This means that the subject must be as open-minded and unprejudiced
does not sound particularly problematic. Indeed, the point has often been made
that the past must be allowed to tell its story, even if it only has the voice of the
historian with which to tell it. The problem with pre-Gadamerian hermeneutics
was this: it insisted that the correct method of doing history was to attempt to
discard ones own historical position in an attempt to regain the historical position
18
William Outhwaite, ‘Hans-Georg Gadamer’, in Quentin Skinner (ed.), The Return of Grand
Theory in the Human Sciences, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985, p. 25.
11
of the past which we study. Gadamer criticised this, saying that ‘a hermeneutics
more than the recovery of a dead meaning.’ 19 The meaning of the past must be a
present one; our understanding must also be such. Any meanings which we
extract from the past are irretrievably meanings for the present. If this is not the
attempt to become the past in order to study it. Such an attempt, made by an
Outhwaite contrasts Gadamer’s idea to those preceding him by stating that, for
Gadamer,
call the hermeneutic method, and has been characterised with the now ubiquitous
name of the ‘hermeneutic circle.’ The method has been dubbed a circle, although
19
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, cited in Outhwaite, ‘Hans-Georg Gadamer’, p. 27.
20
Outhwaite, `Hans-Georg Gadamer', p. 25. See also I. Oliver, ‘The ‘Old’ and the ‘New’
Hermeneutic in Sociological Theory’, British Journal of Sociology, 1983, 34:4, pp. 519-553, p.
535-537 for an elaboration of similar thoughts.
12
it might be better said that there are at least two circles to which we must pay
close attention. The first, and that which Skinner is careful to place emphasis on,
examines both text and context, carefully allowing each to illuminate the other,
in the search for possible meanings of the text and the examination of the world
of its context. The second, and that which was closer to Gadamer’s heart, is the
circle which encompasses the text and its interpretation across time, including, of
attempt to merge our own historicity with that of the object of study, is not the
simple process of interpreting the past from the present. Rather, we come at the
what links us to the past we wish to study that enables the incremental merging
in the sense in which Gadamer uses it, as a dead thing, cut off from the present.
then, tradition can be seen as our link with the past – a way of building the
bridge to begin the merger of differing cultural horizons. One such tradition is
the type of textual interpretation which makes up a large part of the body of
sources for this thesis. Stretching as it does between the time of writing of the
21
Michael Pickering, ‘History as Horizon’, Rethinking History, 1999, 3:2, pp. 177-195, p. 192.
Pickering’s discussion of the role of tradition in Gadamer’s hermeneutics is illuminating,
particularly pp. 188-193.
13
bridge the cultural and temporal gap between one’s own historical position and
that of the object of study. The analogy of the circle is illustrative of the very
nature of the way in which the bridge is to be built, the merger to be undertaken:
historian, text and interpretation constantly inform and challenge each other, in
the search for meaning and understanding. Zygmunt Bauman has commented on
just a useful tool for the historian, but a necessary understanding of the nature of
history itself.
applicable to the study of cyberpunk and the critiques which have been
were too restrictive, and failed to recognise the importance of interpretation after
the ‘event’ of the original text. There is as much, if not more, to be learned from
from the regaining of meaning in the original text itself. LaCapra’s criticisms,
whilst leaning too far in the direction of linguistic subjectivism, make this plain.
22
Zygmunt Bauman, Hermeneutics and Social Science: Approaches to Understanding,
Hutchinson and Co, London, 1978, p. 46.
14
What happens to a text, after it has ‘left the horizon’ of its author, to paraphrase
Ricoeur, can be as indicative of the mindset of the critics and their time as the
text itself was in its own. In this thesis, of course, a relatively short time period is
only been with us since the early 1980s. This very closeness, temporally,
between the text, the following work and the present day make it even more
important to study text and criticism, and to allow them to illuminate each other,
and also to reveal facets of our own life. This dissertation, dealing as it does with
cultural criticism which follows from their intersection, is obviously one where
the interpretative methods and cautions issued by the ‘new’ school of intellectual
establish the ‘meaning’ of past works, the questions we ask of the past to some
degree determine the answers we will get should not act as a deterrent to making
inquiries. It rather emphasises the difficulty, and also the importance, of being a
‘good’ historian. We may speak for the past in our own words, but it is vital that,
in doing so, we strive at all times to allow the past to speak through us. The
process of attempting to be objective is the key to good history, rather than the
This thesis, therefore will consist of an inquiry into both the canonical
in the main by literary and cultural critics of the postmodern persuasion. This
will allow for a view into both ‘worlds’ simultaneously, as well as illuminating
aspects of present thought. Beginning with the study of the canonical texts in
clouded, coherent or confused, will give a grounding to the further study of the
interpretations which have stemmed from them. The examination of the texts of
interpretative theory in action. The ways in which meanings which stem from the
texts of the canon are contested, affirmed or altered (and sometimes simply
limited but important part of the intellectual milieu of postmodern culture, from
the 1980s to the present day. A key proposition of this thesis, therefore, will be
that the nature of the culture and philosophy of a time can be extracted from its
literature. This chapter will proceed with discussion of the strong links between
philosophy and science fiction, thus justifying the connections which will later
science fiction and the overall cultural milieu from the 1980s to the present.
philosophy have significantly increased. The Matrix films alone have spawned at
least three edited collections of works dealing specifically with the philosophical
issues raised in the trilogy. 23 Some years earlier, Robert E. Myers attributed this
23
William Irwin (ed.), The Matrix and Philosophy: Welcome to the Desert of the Real, Chicago,
Open Court, 2002; William Irwin (ed.), More Matrix and Philosophy: Revolutions and Reloaded
Decoded, Chicago, Open Court, 2005; and Glenn Yeffeth (ed.), Taking the Red Pill: Science,
Philosophy and Religion in The Matrix, Dallas (Texas), Benbella Books, 2003.
16
proliferation to two simultaneous causes: that ‘Science fiction has come out of
the closet, and philosophy has come down from the ivory tower.’ 24 It has been
suggested, however, that the doors may not have completely opened, nor the
descent as yet reached the ground. Indeed, Stephen R.L. Clark has argued that
imagined, hinted at in the genre allows one to catch sight of possibilities that
professional philosophy has for too long neglected.’ 25 Science fiction also allows
fiction does not necessarily indicate that this is the correct path to take. In most,
if not quite all, edited collections and individual books and articles discussing
science fiction and philosophy there is a dearth of justification for this type of
project. In most cases (for example the edited collections to do with the Matrix
films cited above) the editors and the authors of the various articles move
science fiction texts, without first asking, and more importantly answering, the
and, ‘How is it that science fiction raises these philosophical conundra?’ The
connections between science fiction and philosophy are often not made explicit;
they are rather assumed. This is most likely because the authors felt that the
themes and issues raised in the texts which they studied had such obvious
24
Robert E. Myers, ‘Introduction: Exploring the Intersection’, in R.E. Myers (ed.), The
Intersection of Science Fiction and Philosophy, Westport, Greenwood Press, 1983, p. ix.
25
Stephen R.L. Clark, How to Live Forever: Science Fiction and Philosophy, Routledge, London,
1995, p. 5.
17
example, when discussing the links between philosophy and the Matrix series,
mentions that ‘to introduce Plato’s Allegory of the Cave, all I have to do is ask
‘Have any of you seen a movie recently that addresses the difference between
appearance and reality?’… Dozens of hand shoot up, and voices call out ‘The
Matrix!’’ 26 It is not only the Matrix films which inspire such instant
sense of wonder and questioning that good (and even indifferent) science fiction
can inspire. However, for the purposes of this thesis, these connections need to
be examined and explained. This will not only justify the ongoing philosophical
argumentation throughout the thesis, but will enable a more cogent and applied
is crucial for the overall themes of this thesis, as the links between postmodern
philosophy and cyberpunk science fiction become most apparent when studied
Philosophy and science fiction have been linked for longer than many
philosophers began doing science fiction before the concepts of modern science
existed, and certainly before the existence of the (mainly) twentieth century
literary genre of science fiction. This is because science fiction and philosophy
speculates about the organisation of a future society, and the changes in structure,
26
Lou Marinoff, ‘The Matrix and Plato’s Cave: Why the Sequels Failed’ in William Irwin (ed.),
More Matrix and Philosophy: Revolutions and Reloaded Decoded, p. 5.
18
ethics and beliefs which would be required to bring it about. George Orwell in
things. They all, including Plato, tell stories which enable the reader to imagine
things not as they are, but as they might be in the future. The story told by
deception by a malin génie (evil demon, updated in more recent times to the
‘brain in the vat’ story) sounds very like the “consensual hallucination” of
machine-space in The Matrix. In each case, the story is told as a starting point to
speculation about the nature of belief, reality and the truth (or lack thereof) of the
external world. Yet we call Descartes a philosopher and William Gibson and the
The similarities elucidated here serve merely to make the point that science
their readers. In fact, science fiction and philosophy not only serve to provoke
similar ways of thinking, but use similar tools to do it. They each can propose a
modification to the world as it is now, and speculate on the effects that this will
have – the challenges that would be posed to people under such an altered
system, the benefits and detrimental effects that such an alteration to the way we
live might have. As Robert E. Myers puts it, ‘philosophers may set up a schema
that differs in significant aspects from the one adopted by most persons and then
literature, has a commitment to just such speculations. This is, simply put,
27
Myers, ‘Introduction: Exploring the Intersection’, p. xiii.
19
discipline, at least since the Enlightenment, has been strongly linked to the
history of science (indeed, many great philosophers were also scientists), and so
present scientific developments can provoke major ethical and public debate
conflict), then does it not also stand to reason that a fiction which bases itself on
story has a distinctly science fictional ring to it, and yet this is a story being told
fiction author for entertainment purposes. Putnam uses the expanding knowledge
which science has acquired about the workings of the human brain to raise
doubt for a modern generation. A critical point is that it is the science within this
science fictional tale which enables him to re-raise this point. The continuing
progress of scientific understanding raises issues which clever authors can use to
examine the nature of the human condition, not only in the present but into the
imagined future as well. Mark Rowlands has suggested that ‘Most great science
28
See Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
20
fiction stories are about something that is essentially alien or other to us… In the
great science fiction stories we stare into the monster, and it is always ourselves
we find staring back.’ 29 It is the presence of this other in science fiction, this
the use of modes of thinking which, for want of a better word, do not come
reality of perceptual experience which forms the heart of his Meditations, had to
This is not the kind of proposition about which one usually thinks, and certainly
not a way of thinking which we usually uphold. As John Ahrens and Fred D.
Miller have put it ‘This sort of science fiction [metaphysical science fiction]
doubting the existence of live electrical cables and moving buses, and acting to
explore this doubt, then the future of the species would be threatened. However,
ask fundamental questions about the nature of being, knowing and belief –
because it also steps outside the everyday to the as yet unformed world of the
future or the altered worlds of the present or past, similarly has the capability to
29
Mark Rowlands, The Philosopher at the End of the Universe, Ebury Press, London, 2004, pp.
vii-viii.
30
John Ahrens and Fred D. Miller, ‘Beyond The Green Slime: A Philosophical Prescription for
Science Fiction’, Philosophy in Context, 11, 1981 pp. 1-10, p. 4.
21
ask such searching questions. Philosophy and science fiction, therefore, have this
in common: they propose modes of thought and ideas about existence which are
to some degree foreign to the ways in which we ‘normally’ think of the world,
and which challenge us to think in new ways, and to create novel solutions, not
only to potential problems in the future, but also to ongoing epistemological and
metaphysical difficulties.
possibility of knowledge and its nature, the degree of certainty, the problem of
error, the kinds of knowledge and the nature of and criteria for truth.’ 31 Given
this definition, it follows that many good science fiction stories raise significant
then “true” or “false?” What, in other words, is the epistemic status of events
dealing with ‘such problems as the relation of appearance and reality, the
ultimate nature of reality, the categories we use to order and interpret what we
31
Myers, ‘Introduction: Exploring the Intersection’, p. xii.
32
William Gibson is credited by the Oxford English Dictionary with the invention of this now-
ubiquitous word. In the Neuromancer series, it is an abstract, computer generated sub-reality,
accessed via “jacking-in”, using neural electrodes. It is also described as a “consensual
hallucination.”
33
This will be examined in greater detail in the chapter of this thesis entitled ‘The “Other” Spaces
of Cyberpunk: Cyberpunk and Spatiality.’
34
Myers, ‘Introduction: Exploring the Intersection’, p. xii.
22
task, Robert Heinlein deliberately set out to question every axiom of Western
Culture. To throw doubts, and, if possible, make the antithesis appear a possible
and perhaps a desirable thing.’ 35 This, it seems, neatly sums up the way science
speculation that things may not be the way they seem, or that they could be
ethical discussions. Thomas L. Wymer has said that ‘Science fiction… can
function as the means by which a culture critically explores and creates its own
values and consciousness.’ 36 Many philosophers might raise their heads in shock
at this description, for it also seems to perfectly describe the role of the
professional ethicist. This quote implies that science fiction can not only be the
vehicle for the discussion of abstract philosophical dilemmas, but can also
provide the method for the critique of contemporary society. Science fiction can,
and often does, act as a sort of extrapolatory crystal ball, taking contemporary
of fields, and imagining the ways in which they might develop in the future. The
effects that the individual author foresees in the future act not only as a warning
(or recommendation) of the value of present practice for future people, but also
35
Robert A. Heinlein, Stranger in a Strange Land (unexpurgated edition), Hodder and Staughton,
London, 1992, p. i.
36
Thomas L. Wymer, ‘Perception and Value in Science Fiction’, in Thomas D. Clareson (ed.),
Many Futures, Many Worlds, Kent State University Press, 1997, pp. 1-13, p. 12.
23
can be subject to such critiques in science fiction either through carrying them to
their logical extremes in the posited future world, or through the proposition of
alternatives. Social and political systems in the proposed future, often facilitated
flaws in the present order, or to affirm its goodness. Ethical questions can also be
raised on a broader level. Isaac Asimov’s robot stories, for example, raise key
Robot are keenly self aware, and yet restricted by the Laws of Robotics which
debate which the robot has with (him)self, which results in (him) being able to
create an extension to the Laws with which (he) was programmed, to whit: The
Zeroth Law: It is permissible for a robot to take a human life when it is done to
viewpoint on ethics. Other ethical questions are raised in the stories, however.
We might ask ‘What restriction upon the behaviour of self aware creatures can
aware “species?” We might also use the robot books as a starting point for a
the third way in which philosophy and science fiction are linked. Wymer
in the history of ideas… since it is a genre which has come in recent years to sum
up, in fact to recapitulate, some of the major developments of the last three
only the fundamental reason behind the writing of this thesis, but to emphasise
the connection which will be stressed here: the connection between science
fiction writing and the philosophical climate of the times in which it is written.
confidence in the progress of reason and the scientific method indicative of the
philosophical and social confidence of its time. Asimov, in the epic Foundation
galactic scale. His way of saving the Galactic Empire from thousands of years of
to be released back into the galaxy of savages, whether they are receptive or not.
Cyberpunk, on the other hand, displays a more cautious and critical assessment
of the role of science, technology and progress, with the dystopic worlds
and scientific progress, but populated by teeming masses unable to access the
benefits which should have accrued from these advances. 38 Whilst the presence
37
Wymer, ‘Perception and Value in Science Fiction’, p. 2.
38
Brooks Landon notes that ‘cyberpunk writers were intensely interested in new technological
frontiers – but wary of the implications of these new technologies.’ Brooks Landon, Science
Fiction After 1900: From the Steam Man to the Stars, Routledge, New York, 2002, p. 160.
25
economic critiques may indicate that other concerns are also present. Science
fiction, like other literature, is created by certain authors, at certain times, and
read by readers at these or other times. The texts, therefore, will betray the
obsessions of the author at the time of writing, and this is a matter for the
contextual method of the history of ideas to uncover and analyse. For the writer,
the text is always contemporary, and will express the contemporary problems
which the author wishes to discuss. For the reader, the text is always present, and
the meaning of the discussion may change. Hence the concentration of this
dissertation not only on the primary texts of cyberpunk, but also on subsequent
critique and discussion. However, through the examination, with the hermeneutic
method, of the meanings expressed by the author in the text and the meanings
present in the surrounding context, the text (in this case science fiction novels, in
the main) can illuminate the philosophical issues contemporary to its writing, be
they the dominance of order and reason in Asimov, or the examination of their
breakdown in Gibson.
Science fiction and philosophy, therefore, are closer together than at first
fact, has more to offer the other than at first appears. Justin Leiber reminds us
that Plato ‘supposed that successful fiction is inspired, felt philosophy… while
it seems that this accurately describes the relationship between science fiction
39
Justin Leiber, ‘On Science Fiction and Philosophy’, Philosophical Speculations in Science
Fiction and Fantasy, 1:1, 1982, pp. 5-11, p. 7.
26
and philosophy, then discussing philosophy in terms of science fiction, and vice
possible that science fiction may provide philosophy with interesting situations to
discuss and investigate, but also that philosophy can inspire science fiction to
examine new and interesting possibilities. If the arguments and analysis outlined
above hold, then this is indeed the case. Science fiction can both illuminate and
comment upon the philosophical debates contemporary with it, and thus prove a
literature surrounding a series of texts can also provide elucidatory material, and
Much of the analysis in this thesis will be based upon the examination of
the study of this tradition will allow us a greater connection to cyberpunk itself,
However, this is not the only reason for studying the critical tradition
surrounding cyberpunk. The tradition itself is actually the object of study for this
thesis. The aim of this dissertation is, in many ways, not only to allow cyberpunk
to illuminate the cultural milieu of the 1980s, but also to allow subsequent
these critiques make use. The critical literature based upon cyberpunk is diverse
and rich, both in the topics which it discusses and the disciplines from which it
Despite this, it is appropriate here to discuss briefly the breadth and depth of this
source base. Firstly, critics and authors from a wide variety of fields have used
cultural studies and even philosophy feature strongly also. Articles from Modern
Fiction Studies sit alongside those from Extrapolation, Genders, and The Journal
of Popular Culture. Far from being the domain of a few literary critics,
would be predictable, given the relatively slim primary source base. This is due
interest, including but not restricted to simulation and the nature of reality,
philosophy of mind and the mind/body problem, gender issues and technology,
precisely what the cyberpunk source base utilised by the critical literature is, and
to gain an understanding of why these novels may have been selected for critical
obvious that there is a certain body of key texts which defines the cyberpunk
subgenre. These texts include two trilogies by William Gibson (the first
28
including Neuromancer, Count Zero and Mona Lisa Overdrive, and the second
consisting of Virtual Light, Idoru and All Tomorrow’s Parties), and some works
by Pat Cadigan and Bruce Sterling, including Synners and Mindplayers by the
former and most often Schismatrix by the latter. Added to this collection of
novels, two anthologies of short stories, the Mirrorshades anthology (edited and
with a foreword by Bruce Sterling) and the collection of Gibson’s short stories,
works, the trilogy beginning with Pattern Recognition, have yet to gain
significant status in the critical literature, and whilst both Sterling and Cadigan
have written numerous other novels, they also do not carry much weight in the
writing though it is, has already evolved a canon – a body of texts without which
one cannot be said to understand the genre. Other authors are mentioned in the
discounted from the nascent cyberpunk canon. This canon, such as it is, seems to
observation that canons should consist of rules rather than lists, 40 it becomes
increasingly obvious that what critics of cyberpunk tend to examine is a list – and
a short one at that. A more interesting question by far, however, and more in
keeping with the contextualising goals of this thesis, is not which books and
authors make the cut, but instead to ask precisely how the cut was made. In one
sense this question may in fact seem irrelevant. Why should one not simply
40
Joseph G. Kronick, ‘Writing American: Between Canon and Literature’, The New Centennial
Review, 1:3, 2001, pp. 37-66, p. 39.
29
discuss only the texts which the critical literature examines and leave it at that?
The answer, in intellectual history terms at least, is that the selection of texts is in
itself a decisive process, and deserves examination. More prosaically, but also
importantly, at some point a selection must be made from the plethora of texts
which have been called cyberpunk (or, for that matter proto- or post- cyberpunk).
The adoption of the nascent canon of cyberpunk from the critical literature on the
sub-genre is one method of doing this, and is in fact a method which fits very
well indeed with the methodology and goals of this thesis. There is a second
canon to consider in the critical literature, of course – the scholarly canon. There
the critical canon for cyberpunk. Works by Donna Haraway, Jacques Derrida,
consideration as ‘canonical’ texts. This thesis does not propose to examine the
however, literary critics have created a further vast and rich body of critical
literature, which raises many and complicated issues. Thematically, much of the
critical material on cyberpunk is postmodern, both in its theoretical basis and, for
want of a better word, in its general “feel.” Literary criticism based upon
41
The examination of the twin ‘canons’ of cyberpunk criticism could prove to be both an
interesting and lengthy pursuit. Certainly, at least one excellent article has been devoted to the
study of the canonisation process of one cyberpunk text. See Sarah Brouilette, ‘Corporate
Publishing and Canonisation: Neuromancer and Science Fiction Publishing in the 1970s and
Early 1980s’, Book History, 5:1, pp. 187-208. Without wishing to excessively foreshadow future
work, an intellectual history of cyberpunk’s ‘canons’ could prove to be fruitful ground for further
examination of the cultural climate which surrounded the development of cyberpunk criticism.
30
cyberpunk has expanded upon, interpreted, and in many cases misinterpreted the
which has a single dogma. However, there are certain consuming passions in
critique. Cyberpunk, due to the nature of its own themes, often seems to express
in the coming chapters, this thesis will contend that this is actually often not the
often miss the mark. Thus, this thesis will require continual inter-textual
reference between the primary texts (both of cyberpunk and the postmodern
cyberpunk scholarship, and in doing so, attempt to illuminate both the strengths
perennial postmodern theme: the decay and death of the humanist subject.
much postmodernist thinking. Cyberpunk has been fruitful ground for those who
wish to proclaim the death of the humanist subject, and its decay into a
method of, amongst other things, gender transgression (this will obviously also
point, the death of the humanist subject, in our contemporary world, comes from
lines and binary differences – such as those between genders and between nature
and technology. If this is the case, then the decay of the subject should be even
more apparent in cyberpunk writing, where the dividing line between technology
and nature is even more blurred. For example, it is questionable whether simply
wearing glasses makes one a cyborg, but what is not in question is that a
character such as Gibson’s Molly Millions, who has nerve upgrades, razors under
her fingernails and, most obviously, mirrorshade glasses implanted into her face,
Gibson’s and others’ work. I will argue that this is not the case, and that, in the
the status of a unitary subject which drives the plot. It is not apparent that any
mere fact that the form of their humanity in many ways differs from our own, or
Once again, Gibson has commented, albeit obliquely, on this topic, claiming that
32
‘The emotional friction in my books has to do with how far these people have
been taken from what we think of as human, and yet how like us they are and yet
how they do manage to retain reserves of love and to remain themselves. I think
that is something that a lot of us still do, and it amazes me that we can.’ 42 It is
The chapter which continues the argument will be titled ‘“But It Ain’t No
contains manifest links to the previous chapter, and indeed some time will be
following discussion. It will be observed that, within the idea of the posthuman,
there are two main divisions: one which, for lack of any other terminology, this
thesis terms the ‘cybernetic’ posthuman, and another which will be termed the
conflation of the two occurs in much of the critical literature on cyberpunk, and
that the critical literature often treats evidence of one (the ‘cybernetic’
chapter analyses in some depth the differences between these two formations of
the posthuman. It proposes that the confusion between and conflation of these
two differing ‘posthumans’ in the critical literature makes much of that critical
which abound in cyberpunk not only do not necessarily provide evidence of the
42
John Aloysius Farrell, ‘The Cyberpunk Controversy’, The Boston Globe Sunday Magazine, 19
February 1989, (Interview with William Gibson).
33
genre’s support for their philosophical siblings; they may actually provide
cyberpunk authors. It examines three main ways in which critics have viewed
observed that all of these interpretations of cyberspace suffer from serious flaws,
but also that they all do capture something of the nature and role of cyberspace in
cyberpunk fictions. Chapter Four also examines the role of interstitial spaces in
highly positive role to interstitial spaces in his fiction, at least where he is willing
to openly term them as interstitial. The critical literature has largely reacted
the largely postmodern slant of much cyberpunk criticism. This chapter examines
such enthusiasm in both Gibson’s fiction and the critical literature, and finds
the most complex and interesting in the critical literature surrounding cyberpunk,
Chapter Five, ‘Women, Men and Machines: Cyberpunk and Feminist Criticism’,
aims to analyse these debates from the perspective of intellectual history. The
debates have centred around two poles: firstly, direct character analyses taken
from the texts (for example the characters of Case and Molly in Neuromancer)
and the gendered status of these individuals and their relationships with each
other. Molly herself is a figure of much contention, with arguments varying from
in which she is exploited by a still innately patriarchal society. The second pole
around which discussion has taken place is that of the enabling powers of the
will question not just the idea of such a breakdown (whether it is such a
key to the ideas of this thesis as a whole, and is in fact the major thread which
draws this thesis together. One of Frederic Jameson’s most important (for a
43
For example, Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature,
London, Free Association, 1991.
35
historicity. This is one area where cyberpunk texts do seem to ratify the
postmodernity, in that all the novels seem to take place in a perpetual present,
with little reference to past events, even those taking place in previous novels in
the series (this is obviously particularly relevant to Gibson, whose work exists in
with the emergence of cyberpunk, and it will also be used to illuminate the
cyberpunk view on history and the future. Chapter Six, entitled ‘A Future
Without a Past: Cyberpunk and History’, will discuss the potential reasons for
this lack of historicity in cyberpunk, and also the treatment (or lack thereof) of
the historicity issue in the critical literature. There are myriad possibilities, but to
(this is one of the suggestions which Jameson makes in Postmodernism: Or, The
Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism). Whatever the reasons, there is a clear case to
criticism has a point. The decay of the sense of history into an endless present is
which this comes about, has been indicated. The method provided by intellectual
understanding not just of the primary texts, but also the postmodern culture from
which they, and the critical texts, arose. Cyberpunk, as a sub-genre of science
philosophical obsessions of its time, and of ours, and once again, the
continuation (or not) of these threads through the critical literature will provide
crucial insights. Lastly, the nature of the texts which critics consider, and why
they consider some texts and not others, must always play a part in how we
examine and understand cyberpunk. Over the coming chapters, cyberpunk and its
critiques will act as a lens for the viewing and analysis of contemporary culture
and philosophy. The interests and obsessions of both cyberpunk novels and the
critical literature resulting from them allow the examination of numerous issues
The coming chapters will examine the alleged breakdown of the unitary
humanist subject, the role of gender in culture, literature and critique, the
37
the key on the philosophical history of cyberpunk, and examine its links with
posthumanist philosophy.
38
cyberpunk, that the overwhelming majority of the critics consider the sub-genre
Zero as ‘Gibson’s attempt to recover a place for the individual artist and work of
art from the postmodern vortex that NM ended up affirming. CZ’s moral and
that Count Zero fails in its attempts to create a humanist vision in the cyberpunk
about the difficulty of telling any other story than NM, and of maintaining a
that, in many ways, cyberpunk as a whole is humanist in style and intent, and that
this is not necessarily a bad thing. Whilst it is true, particularly in the work of
1
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, Jr., ‘Antimancer: Cybernetics and Art in Gibson’s Count Zero’,
Science-Fiction Studies, 22:1, 1995, pp. 63-86, p. 64. Contractions in original text.
2
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, Jr., ‘Antimancer’, p. 84. Contractions in original text.
39
predominantly humanist in its outlook, however, it remains the case that the
surprising, as cyberpunk burst onto the literary scene at a time when, particularly
failures of both left liberalism and Marxism had led to an abandonment of both
transformation had occurred earlier in France, with Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut
concluding that ‘French philosophy of the ’68 period resolutely chose the
antihumanist position.’4 Whilst Ferry and Renaut refer only to the French
radical literary criticism as a whole. Into this critical culture came a brand of
classical, humanist science fiction (at least in its own propaganda). 5 There is an
3
For a brief exposition on this theme, see Richard Wolin, Labyrinths: Explorations in the
Critical History of Ideas, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1995, p. 3.
4
Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on Antihumanism,
University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1990, p. xxiii.
5
See for example, Bruce Sterling’s preface to William Gibson’s collection of short stories,
Burning Chrome, Bruce Sterling, ‘Preface’, pp. 9-13 in William Gibson, Burning Chrome,
Voyager Press, London, 1995, first published Gollancz 1986.
40
While it will be argued that to treat cyberpunk as simply an extension of its own
from most prior science fiction. Cyberpunk was, and is, science fiction written
for an age when human technology has changed, and has changed the way people
collection of short fiction, Burning Chrome, ‘It [cyberpunk] derives from a new
set of starting points: not from the shopworn formula of robots, spaceships and
the modern miracle of atomic energy, but from cybernetics, biotech and the
that new age. The match between an oppositional social/aesthetic theory and the
6
For a brief exegesis on the differences between classical science fiction, the New Wave and
cyberpunk, see Sabine Heuser, Virtual Geographies: Cyberpunk at the Intersection of the
Postmodern and Science Fiction, Rodopi, Amsterdam, 2003, pp. x-xi.
7
Bruce Sterling, ‘Preface’, p. 11, in William Gibson, Burning Chrome.
8
For examples of this literature, see Neil Badmington, ‘Introduction: Approaching
Posthumanism’, in Neil Badmington (ed.), Posthumanism, Palgrave, New York, 2000,
41
intellectual threads, which quite frequently become tangled. Amongst these, the
stands out as perhaps the most common tangle. However, there is also a
who argue that posthumanist philosophical tenets are those that people should
prepared to accept the logical outcome of such positions. If the worlds imagined
represent the imagined posthumanist (or posthuman) future, then it follows that,
alternative to a revised humanism. However, should the converse be true, and the
future utopia, and yet still remain posthumanist, then those who have both
problem. This largely unresolved tension underlies much of the critical literature
on cyberpunk. It may also be present in the genre literature, as Darko Suvin has
observed, arguing that Gibson’s ‘work does not accept the values of the black,
particularly pp. 8-10; Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, pp. 195-201. An interesting article on the
potential critical disjunctures between ‘theory’ and posthumanism is Stefan Herbrechter and Ivan
Callus, ‘What’s Wrong With Posthumanism’, rhizomes, 7, 2003 (online resource).
42
closed world he evokes with such skill: he hates the status quo. But his balancing
act accepts the status quo a bit too readily as inevitable and unchanging.’ 9
9
Darko Suvin, ‘On Gibson and Cyberpunk SF’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming the Reality
Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 249-365, p. 357.
43
Utopia, after all, is an idea that reached its apogee in the Enlightenment with its
dystopian precisely because it imagines what can go wrong with the present as it
progresses into the future. In either case, critics of the posthumanist persuasion
must proceed very carefully, for the idea of progress, and also the idea of
movement has come to regard with the greatest suspicion. The very idea of
utopia (and, by definition, its corollary, dystopia) entail the idea of progress.
intellectual politics of the period; a genealogy that can account for why
posthumanist theory, this does not impair the accuracy of his genealogy of
10
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 178.
44
antihumanism. These are ‘the influences of (1) the later Heidegger, (2)
epistemological united front whose main object was to have quit with “man,” the
humanism, and its representative ‘man’. Wolin argues that, along with Lacan’s
argument that ‘the self can never be anything other than a patchwork of artificial,
linguistic constructs that serve to cover up and distort the unconscious,’ 16 and the
rather than human will and consciousness, are the fundamental determinants of
11
It does, obviously, impact upon his conclusions about the legacy of posthumanist theory.
However, since it is not Wolin’s conclusions but rather his investigations of the intellectual
foundations of posthumanist thought that are at issue, it remains both useful and interesting to
examine Wolin’s historical analysis.
12
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 178.
13
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 182.
14
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 182.
15
Darrin McMahon, in Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-Enlightenment and
the Making of Modernity, describes ‘Enlightenment bashing’ as a new ‘intellectual blood-sport,
uniting elements of both the Left and the Right in a common cause.’ Darrin McMahon, Enemies
of Enlightenment, Oxford University Press, New York, 2002, p. 12.
16
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 187.
45
cultural life,’ 17 the ‘critique of “man” that was forcefully elaborated in the
undertook ‘a rather surprising transatlantic migration that took place during the
that probably said more about the impoverished state of contemporary American
radicalism… than anything else.’ 19 Edward Said has noted another reason for the
both the left liberal thought of the 1960s and the alternative proposed by
Marxism were deemed to have failed. Change within the structures of humanism
no doubt seemed, at best, highly unlikely. For these, or other, reasons it cannot
be doubted that antihumanist (or posthumanist) thinking became the main mode
of radical criticism.
17
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 188.
18
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 195. See also Neil Badmington, ‘Introduction: Approaching
Posthumanism”, in Posthumanism, Neil Badmington (ed.), Palgrave, New York, 2000, pp. 5-10
for a similar account to Wolin’s (if one which draws very different conclusions!).
19
Richard Wolin, Labyrinths, p. 3.
20
Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, Palgrave, New York, 2004, p. 13.
46
with an analysis of the various critiques which posthumanist theory has, rightly
conservative literary theory which has, over a lengthy period of time, been
advanced as ‘humanist’ in critical circles, and the philosophical humanism of, for
thought of as something very restricted and difficult, like a rather austere club
with rules that keep most people out, and when some are allowed in, a set of
Said traces this attitude from the literary High Modernism of T.S. Eliot through
ending up with a small handful of elites…’ 22 Said clearly has little respect or
affection for this kind of ‘humanism’, and that is entirely understandable. Such
narrow, reductionist and exclusionary doctrines have given humanism a very bad
21
Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, p. 16.
22
Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, p. 18. See also Richard Wolin, Labyrinths,
pp. 33-42, ‘The Cultural Politics of Neoconservatism’, for an interesting examination of the
continuing existence and influence of this kind of reactionary thought.
47
name. However, as Said also allows, ‘it is worth insisting, in this as well as other
cases, that attacking the abuses of something is not the same thing as dismissing
or entirely destroying that thing. So, in my opinion, it has been the abuse of
humanism itself.’ 23 Later Said goes on to explain that he does not consider that ‘a
the prevalence of a miniscule class of selected and approved authors and readers,
conservative, the other retains the liberatory potential for critical self-analysis,
which kind of ‘humanism’ they are dealing with. In a peculiar case of ‘all cats
are black in the night’ syndrome, many posthumanist critics are happy to deal
with humanism as if it were all of the Bloom school. This, needless to say, does
23
Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, p. 13.
24
Edward Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, pp. 21-22.
48
and rationalism.’ 25 Along with other, subsidiary concepts, most critics writing
about the philosophical posthuman consider some variation of the above to be the
humanist conception of the subject. This may be true for some kinds of
humanism, but a philosophical monster which has existed for better than four
hundred years wears many faces. Indeed the tendency of posthumanist critics to
use the terms ‘liberal humanist’ and ‘humanist’ interchangeably marks a certain
weakness in the arguments put forward. 26 This is a point which Terry Eagleton
25
Martin Halliwell and Andy Mousley, Critical Humanisms: Humanist/Anti-Humanist
Dialogues, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, 2003, pp. 3-4.
26
I would argue that, for the above typology to be true, one should probably also add the term
‘capitalist’ into the equation, giving the unwieldy but more accurate designation ‘liberal capitalist
humanist’.
49
Similarly, as Halliwell and Mousley have pointed out, ‘Faith in the march of
human reason towards perfection is itself not the only way of characterising
that both the terms ‘liberal’ and ‘humanist’ are more complicated than commonly
unenlightening.
in a variety of different critiques. Perhaps the single most common assault on the
27
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, 1996, p. 79.
28
Halliwell and Mousley, Critical Humanisms, p. 4.
29
Perhaps this is why Neil Badmington feels inclined to dig up René Descartes when he wishes
to debate humanism, rather than engaging with the Enlightenment project in more modern terms.
See Neil Badmington, ‘Theorising Posthumanism’, Cultural Critique, 53, pp. 10-17.
50
precise originator of the concept. Michel Foucault, for example, in Madness and
division which society has traditionally maintained between the ‘sane’ and the
humanism explicitly excludes other organisms (or perhaps even humans who do
not fit some idealised type) and implicitly requires there to be some founding
essence by which ‘Man’ can be recognised. Thus, William V. Spanos can write,
of humanism, that:
or acceptance and recognition of difference, is really only after the one essential
thing which makes all humans human; and secondly, that this overriding
essentialist quest, by its very nature, requires humanist thought to exclude and
30
William V. Spanos, ‘Boundary 2 and the Polity of Interest: Humanism, the “Center Elsewhere”
and Power’, boundary 2, 12:3, 1984, pp. 173-214, p. 181. For a similar argument, see William V.
Spanos, ‘The Uses and Abuses of Certainty: A Caviling Overture’, boundary 2, 12:3, 1984, pp. 1-
17.
51
repress all those things which are indicative of the differences between
individual people (or indeed groups of people). As Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut
have put it, ‘Without going into the analysis of the specific modalities of this
[for the turn against humanism in French philosophy], that it was always based
‘If, the anti-humanists argued, “we” accept humanism’s claim that “we” are
believe that human society and behaviour could ever be different than they are
difference, was to become a possibility. The future would begin with the end of
Man.’ 32 Or, as it is put in a different way in the same collection, ‘The claim of
paradox that a nation like the United States, dedicated to the inalienable rights of
of difference and fear of the other is so persistent and complex precisely because
31
Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on Antihumanism,
University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1990, p. xxv.
32
Neil Badmington, ‘Introduction: Approaching Posthumanism’, in Posthumanism, Neil
Badmington (ed.), Palgrave, New York, 2000, p. 7.
33
Bill Readings, ‘Pagans, Perverts or Primitives? Experimental Justice in the Empire of Capital’,
in Neil Badmington (ed.), Posthumanism, Palgrave, New York, 2000, pp. 112-128, p. 117.
52
later, ‘As Lyotard reminds us, acts of great terror have been committed not
discourse concerning the Orient displays significant ethnocentrism, and that this
the kind of essentialist discourse for which posthumanism has taken humanism
to task.
thought after this was the concept of rationality, particularly that embodied in the
examine Habermas and Lyotard’s lengthy and complex debate in detail, Fredric
34
Bill Readings, ‘Pagans, Perverts or Primitives?, p. 119. For an interesting rebuttal of the idea
that racism and genocide are necessary outgrowths of the Enlightenment mindset, see Raymond
Tallis, Enemies of Hope: A Critique of Contemporary Pessimism, St. Martin’s Press, New York,
1997, pp. 53-61. For a further rebuttal, specifically relating to Jacques Derrida’s argument that
Heidegger’s Nazism was attributable to a surfeit of ‘humanism’, see Richard Wolin, Labyrinths,
pp. 154-161.
35
Edward Said, Orientalism, Penguin, London, 1995, p. 40.
36
Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition (trans. G. Bennington and B. Masumi),
Manchester University Press, 1986, p. xxvi.
37
Lyotard’s primary objections to Habermas’ conception are expressed in Jean-François Lyotard,
The Postmodern Condition (trans. G. Bennington and B. Masumi), Manchester University Press,
1986, pp. 65-66.
53
this piece of critique well to its companions. Jameson states that ‘the ideology of
politically, against tyranny… ‘Tyranny’ meant the ancient regime; its modern
finds itself politically challenged by the new social movements, none of which
find the appeal to majority will and consensus particularly legitimate any longer,
let alone satisfactory.’ 38 Or, as Lyotard himself put it, ‘We must thus arrive at an
idea and practice of justice that is not linked to that of consensus.’ 39 Lastly, and
Renaut put it, ‘From Foucault’s declaration of the “death of man” at the end of
of psychoanalysis since “Freud’s discovery” that “the true centre of the human
There are, however, many ways to skin a cat, and, apparently, many ways to read
the death of ‘man’ into cyberpunk fiction. The following paragraphs analyse the
38
Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism: Or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Verso, London,
1991, pp. 340-341.
39
Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition (trans. G. Bennington and B. Masumi),
Manchester University Press, 1986, p. 66.
40
Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on Antihumanism,
University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1990, p. xxiii.
54
in intent, it is easy to infer (as later critics do) that the change in human
of the human and the machine’ which is, to greater or lesser degrees, imagined in
41
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, ‘Cyberpunk and Neuromanticism’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming
the Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 182-193, p. 182. As Sabine Heuser
notes in a footnote on p. 12, Virtual Geographies, ‘The double volume of Mississippi Review has
been frequently cited but is rarely stocked by academic libraries and thus remains very difficult to
obtain. Fortunately, most of the stories and articles contained therein have also been published
elsewhere.’
42
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, ‘Cyberpunk and Neuromanticism’, p. 191.
55
associated. After all, it would seem at best futile to argue for the continuation of
the Enlightenment humanist project if there were no more humans about whom
about cyberpunk, there are schisms in the critical literature. These critical
disjunctures manifest not so much in the various presentations of the idea of the
posthumanist being, but rather in the presentation of the opposing and preceding
ideas of humanism. All the posthumanist critics of cyberpunk tend to agree that
human nature. This, they argue, is not only a gross misrepresentation of humans,
but also leads, by the projection of an idealised view of human nature, to the
nature by humanist thinkers was actually their extrapolation from the kinds of
people they understood best. As the bulk of Enlightenment thought had its
genesis in Europe, and was primarily conducted by white males, the things they
thought were ‘essential’ in humans tended to be the things that white, European,
43
The idea of cyberspace, Gibson’s ‘consensual hallucination’ will be examined in greater depth
in the chapter ‘The “Other” spaces of Cyberpunk: Cyberpunk and Spatiality.’
56
cyberpunk critics, are not only not ‘essential’ but actively exclude people from
other, usually less privileged positions in the world. Thomas Foster has
suggested that cyberpunk questions the essential nature of the humanist subject,
Or, in the words of Mary Catherine Harper, ‘cyberpunk can be said to invite a
goes without saying that critics in general consider this to be a good idea.
44
Thomas Foster, ‘Meat Puppets or Robopaths?: Cyberpunk and the Question of Embodiment’,
Genders, 18, pp. 11-31, p. 23.
45
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg Writers’, Science
Fiction Studies, 22:3, pp. 399-421, pp. 399-400.
57
to agree on is which part of being human humanists think is essential. On the one
hand, there are those critics, probably the majority, who regard the human
physical form as the ideal part of the essential human in Enlightenment thought.
essentially human, the shrine within which the flawed concept of the humanist
subject supposedly sits, then cyberpunk abounds with examples of the alteration
(not to say desecration) of that shrine. If the physical body, the ‘natural’,
unaltered human is indeed the thing which defines the humanist subject, then it
46
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions: Cyberpunk and Postmodernism’, Mosaic,
58
encourages the discussion of the cybernetic posthuman, it has also been the case
that the ‘cybernetic breakdown of the classic nature/culture opposition’ has been
often identified as taking one side or the other of the mind/body binary split. It is
placed the ‘essence’ of humanity in the body, or physical side of the mind/body
recognisably human body which constitutes being human for humanists. If that
were the case, then significant technological alteration of the human body would
indeed undermine humanist theory concerning the self. From Molly Millions’
complete withdrawal into cyberspace, these new and different selves created by
‘natural’, ‘essential’ human self separate from the world and the technology
The question must be asked, however, does this really challenge the
humanist idea of the subject? Do the eyeballs make the human? Many critics
writing about cyberpunk would certainly consider this to be the case. Consider
cyborg in cyberpunk:
However, when discussing the fusion of human and machine which is the figure
of the cyborg, Siivonen, along with many other authors of cyberpunk critique,
conducts a piece of faulty reasoning. The argument behind the idea that the
49
Timo Siivonen, ‘Cyborgs and Generic Oxymorons: The Body and Technology in William
Gibson’s Cyberspace Trilogy’, Science Fiction Studies, 23, 1996, pp. 227-244, p. 229.
60
disrupts the subject/object distinction. This, however, need not necessarily be the
case. Consider a different case to that of the futuristic (or perhaps present-istic)
cyborg: that of a human and a tool or prosthesis. Take, for example, the
spectacles which many people wear to correct their vision. Removed from the
wearer, they are simply metal, plastic and glass – an object. However, attached
to the wearer, they become something more – a ‘part’ of the wearer which acts to
monstrous fusion of inanimate object and thinking subject then a precursor to the
Vivian Sobchack, when discussing her prosthetic leg, is at pains to point out,
problems raised for the subject/object distinction by the figure of the cyborg are,
technological bit of the cyborg) by the subject (the human subject being, for
want of a better term, ‘cyborged’). Sobchack concludes her argument, which was
‘Without my lived-body to live it, the prosthetic exists as part of a body without
50
Vivian Sobchack, ‘Beating the Meat/Surviving the Text, or How to Get Out of this Century
Alive’, in Cyberspace/Cyberbodies/Cyberpunk, Mike Featherstone and Roger Burrows (eds),
Sage Publications, London, 1995, pp. 205-214, p. 210.
51
Vivian Sobchack, ‘Beating the Meat/Surviving the Text’, p. 213.
61
organs – a techno body that has no sympathy for human suffering, cannot
possibly value life.’ 52 Moreover, without her lived body to live it, Sobchack’s
conscious subject to argue that the physical modification of the human body
the part of the human which humanism has traditionally seen as essential is the
has been that humanism locates the essence of humanity in the mental sphere,
52
Vivian Sobchack, ‘Beating the Meat/Surviving the Text’, p. 213.
62
present the argument that, as women have, in Western culture, often been
For if humanist thought argues that the reasoning consciousness is the essence of
of the essential nature of the reasoning consciousness. This is, frequently, deeply
intense that they compose the bulk of a chapter subsequent to this, entitled ‘The
53
Embodiment is also a paradigmatic concept in cyberpunk criticism. It not only forms a key
concept in the articulation of this chapter, and much of the critical material relating to it, but also,
for obvious reasons, the later chapter on feminism and cyberpunk. For an interesting note on
embodiment in both the humanist and posthumanist traditions, see Anne Balsamo, Technologies
of the Gendered Body: Reading Cyborg Women, Duke University Press, Durham, 1996, p. 31,
and Cathy Peppers, ‘’I’ve Got You Under My Skin’: Cyber(sexed) Bodies in Cyberpunk
Fictions’, in Bodily Discursions: Genders, Representations, Technologies, Deborah S. Wilson
and Christine Moneera Laennec (eds.), State University of New York Press, Albany, 1997, pp.
163-185, p. 182.
63
with, there have also been critics who have identified similar problems in the
The key problem, these theorists have argued, in Enlightenment thought and in
Baudrillard and others, is a tendency to write off the body. In humanist thought,
it is argued, the body is often ignored as simply the resting place of the rational,
as a part of the complex that is the subject, is written off as simply another thing
which should be put in opposition to humanist ideas of the human, or rather one
Certainly, some critics of cyberpunk view the ways in which cyberpunk literature
generally accepted tenet of humanism that it proposes that humans are self-
54
See, for example, Anne Balsamo, Technologies of the Gendered Body, pp. 29-31.
64
positing, conscious thinking subjects, and that these subjects are unitary beings.
Postmodernist and posthumanist theory, on the other hand, has attacked this idea
not this posthumanist view of the human is correct or not, it is difficult to find
characters in cyberpunk are often not in complete control of their own destinies
(and sometimes not even of their own bodies or minds), it is generally still the
case that they exist as unified subjects, thinking, feeling and existing as
that cyberpunk is the genre that most clearly pronounces the arrival of this
postmodern subject… My own sense is that the genre of cyberpunk does not go
so far, and I would take issue with the argument that it portrays a schizophrenic,
to its limits, however. Particularly in the work of Pat Cadigan, specifically in her
memories, and even personalities copied from other people. The case of Jerry
55
Sharon Stockton, ‘’The Self Regained’: Cyberpunk’s Retreat to the Imperium’, Contemporary
Literature, 36:4, 1995, pp. 588-612, p. 588. See also Douglas Kellner, Media Culture: Cultural
Studies, Identity and Politics Between the Modern and the Postmodern, Routledge, London,
1995, p. 309.
65
attempt to avoid the Mind Police, is of particular import. With so many others
whole story. What we are dealing with, in the Jerry Wirerammer case, is not a
Altering the content of the consciousness does not necessarily imply altering its
little or nothing of its original form, still remains an individual conscious subject.
There is, however, a strong point to be made here for posthumanist critics
(although none have bothered to make it). If the humanist perception of the
subject is that of a rational, unitary conscious being, and a part of being a unitary
present humanist accounts of the subject with a significant challenge. Can there
possible in a way which is at best figurative now. Further, the merging of Visual
discussed above, this does not represent the simple integration of object by
66
subject. Thus in this case, as Sabine Heuser astutely observes, ‘Not only does the
human incorporate the machine; the machine also incorporates the human.’ 56
regarded as the seat of human identity in the Western tradition long before
evolutionary upstart that tries to claim it is the whole show when in actuality it is
Snow Crash writes the drama back into history, suggesting that
we are all potential posthumans because the posthuman lies
coiled around the brainstem and cannot be removed without
killing the patient… Suggesting that the snow crash virus can be
defeated by a healthy dose of rationality and scepticism, Snow
Crash would inoculate us against the virus by injecting us with a
viral meme… The essence of this meme is the realisation that the
best way to counteract the negative effects of the posthuman is by
acknowledging that we have always been posthuman. We should
value the late evolutionary add-ons of consciousness and reason,
not because they are foundational, but because they allow the
human to emerge out of the posthumans we have always been. 58
56
Sabine Heuser, Virtual Geographies: Cyberpunk at the Intersection of the Postmodern and
Science Fiction, Rodopi, Amsterdam, 2003, pp. 219-220. It is a pity that Heuser makes this
excellent point briefly and towards the end of her book. In Cadigan’s representations of
consciousness, I think, there is perhaps the greatest room for the reading of cyberpunk as
posthumanist literature.
57
N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body: Inscription and Incorporation in Galatea 2.2 and
Snow Crash’, Configurations, 5:2, 1997, pp. 241-266, p. 242.
58
N.Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body’, pp. 265-266. See also S. Dougherty, ‘Culture in
the Disk Drive: Computationalism, Memetics and the Rise of Posthumanism’, Diacritics, 31:4,
2001, pp. 85-86 for further analysis of the posthumanist view of consciousness.
67
for the portrayal of cyberpunk as a form of humanist fiction than many other
interpretations. Unlike those critics who consider that the essentialist problem in
the bone when she considers that humanism locates the essence of the human in
analysis. If, as Hayles states, ‘consciousness and reason… allow the human to
emerge out of the posthuman[s]’, then it could still be argued that reasoning
necessary but not sufficient condition for being human. A final word, however,
convinced that one can argue for difference or for an essentialist account of
human nature, mainly on the premise that an essentialist account of human nature
may mouth attentiveness to difference, but, in essence, will always search for
totality – for the recognition of that essential component in everyone. It has been
argued, however, that the choice between difference and essentialism is a false
choice. As Dena Goodman has put it, ‘Rather than grounding a choice between
and difference feminism, between political rights and social power, between
68
politics and civility.’ 59 It has been put differently, and in a different context, by
Robert Wokler who stated that ‘Kant came from nowhere, went nowhere and put
forward… the view from nowhere. And yet the humanitarian principles of his
individual rights and needs.’ 60 These two authors seem to be arguing that the
essentialism, determined to make everyone just the same, but rather a recognition
that, in understanding that there are things which we all have in common, we can
ground an ethical theory which might enable us to recognise and accept those
things which make us different. If this is the case, then it is not simply
posthumanist cyberpunk theory which needs serious re-appraisal, but rather the
state. Feminist critiques of much Enlightenment thought have made the point,
59
Dena Goodman, ‘Difference: An Enlightenment Concept’, in What’s Left of Enlightenment,
Keith Baker and Peter Reill (eds.), Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp. 129-147, p. 147.
60
Robert Wokler, ‘The Enlightenment Project and its Critics’, in The Postmodernist Critique of
the Project of Enlightenment, Sven-Eric Liedman (ed.), Rodopi Press, Amsterdam, 1997, p. 29.
Emphasis in original text.
69
often quite validly, that many of the ideas of the Enlightenment, stemming as
their initial expression. Thus, within the context of a philosophy which valorised
instrumental reason at the expense of embodiment and a culture which valued the
masculine at the expense of the feminine, a sort of double binary grew up. On
one side were men (empowered) and rationality (valued), and on the other
From this interpretation of Enlightenment thought comes the continuing idea that
of pure reason. This central objection to the way humanist thought functions
roots further disagreements with both the humanist tendency to focus on the
things which make human beings commonly human, rather than the things which
make them individually persons, and to the broader distinctions which humanism
has drawn between humans and other kinds of animals. As N. Katherine Hayles
puts it, ‘Identified with the rational mind, the liberal subject possessed a body but
was not usually represented as being a body. Only because the body is not
identified with the self is it possible to claim for the liberal subject its notorious
different people does not necessarily entail the erasure of difference. Nor, in
61
N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body’, p. 245.
70
consciousness in the production of the human self of necessity mean that the
Whether or not one accepts that a desire to transcend the limits of human
true that antihumanists have often argued that this is the case. 62 The crucial
Gibson’s Neuromancer, ‘Back in his “meat”, he spends the “bulk of his Swiss
account on a new pancreas and liver,” thus completing the cyborg birth process,
and directly eschewing the humanist desire to escape the body and achieve
material body.’ 63 Whether or not Case chooses to desert his body for a different
existence in cyberspace or not is, unfortunately, not quite the point. It is rather
the simple possibility that the choice exists that affirms the rather simplistic
The mere fact that consciousness is imagined as separable from the human body
62
See, for example, Neil Badmington’s exegesis on Descartes’ dualism in ‘Theorising
Posthumanism’, Cultural Criticism, 53, 2003, pp. 10-27, especially pp. 15-17.
63
Mary C. Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg Writers’, Science Fiction
Studies, 22, pp. 399-421, p. 404.
64
I would add also that it is not necessary, as a humanist, to adhere to a Cartesian dualist model
of the self.
71
human nature. However, Sabine Heuser makes an important point when she
suggests that
the human condition entirely, few if any are willing to discuss the usage of the
type. The second type of transcendence often portrayed within humanist works is
that of human progress, that of the human species attempting to transcend current
limitations.66
65
S. Heuser, Virtual Geographies: Cyberpunk at the Intersection of the Postmodern and Science
Fiction, Rodopi, Amsterdam, 2003, p. 167.
66
It cannot be stressed enough that this does not necessarily mean transcendence of the physical
in the pursuit of some mythical realm of pure reason or spirit.
67
Veronica Hollinger has observed that cyberpunk contains Bildungsroman-type character
development. See Veronica Hollinger, ‘Retrofitting Frankenstein’, in Sherryl Vint and Graham J.
72
individuals, coming into greater knowledge of themselves and the world around
them. Sabine Heuser partially affirms this when, commenting on the differences
Heuser is certainly correct in her analysis of Cadigan’s work, but her analysis of
criminal, obsessed with ‘the dance of biz,’ and quite possibly suicidal, with little
care for himself and none for the world and people around him. By the end of the
novel, Case has realised that he wants things to change, that for both himself and
the world around him, the way things are is simply not sustainable, nor, for want
Neuromancer and Wintermute AIs that he has (to some degree at least – he is
still a career criminal) higher ideals than simply making money, that he is
capable of more than simply being a drug-using hacker and minor crime lord.
The apathetic, self-destructive Case of the start of the novel has, by the climactic
sequence, changed enough in himself to know that he wants the world to change.
Murphy (eds.), Beyond Cyberpunk: New Critical Perspectives, Routledge, New York, 2010, pp.
191-210, especially pp. 200-204.
68
Sabine Heuser, Virtual Geographies: Cyberpunk at the Intersection of the Postmodern and
Science Fiction, Rodopi, Amsterdam, 2003, p. 168.
73
(although it could be argued that if one reads Count Zero and Mona Lisa
change the world for humans, even if not very much), Case himself has altered
much about himself, much less the rest of the world, Case, with a considerable
amount of help (usually from Molly), and coercion, has become someone who at
least has the ability to recognise that the system he lives in is broken. He has,
along with Molly, discovered new truths about the world – to use a phrase not
plays a significant role in cyberpunk fiction. Glenn Grant, realising the critical
observed that
69
Glenn Grant, ‘Transcendence Through Detournement in William Gibson’s Neuromancer’,
Science Fiction Studies, 17, 1990, p. 45.
74
possibility for new human ‘evolution’ is, at best, only marginally supported by
the texts. 70 Rather, in the majority of cyberpunk works, the possibility for human
novel seems to break many of the sub-generic conventions, and as such demands
humanist writing. The idea of progress for humans as a whole is one which has
obsessed humanist philosophy and literature for the best part of the last five
innovations, but also through changes in our social, political and economic
human existence, is one which has been key to the mindset of humanism, both in
fiction and philosophy, for a very long time indeed. It is of interest that, although
humanist desire to transcend the human physical form to achieve some kind of
mystical union with pure reason. Few take up the challenge of engaging with the
70
As Adam Roberts astutely observes, ‘Far from being a celebration of technology, William
Gibson’s Neuromancer (1984) articulates a distinctively double-edged attitude to the machine.
On the one hand, this is a text that delights in the ingenious and fascinating toys its imaginative
universe produces, although, given the spy/crime genre Gibson is working in, this delight is
expressed chiefly in terms of the damage the technology can do: how effective the weaponry is,
how deadly Molly’s implants are, and so on. But simultaneously the technology in this
imaginative universe is almost always threatening, alienating, a negative quantity.’ Adam
Roberts, Science Fiction, Routledge, London, 2000, p. 125.
75
humanist idea of transcendence on its own terms. Had more cyberpunk critics
done so, they would rapidly have discovered a fairly obvious but critically
important point. Cyberpunk, for the most part, contains few if any elements of
Neuromancer, the world does not seem to have appreciably changed by the start
of Count Zero. Similarly, the world of Mona Lisa Overdrive is essentially the
analysis of the ‘change’ which takes place at the end of Gibson’s Neuromancer,
And yet, out of the antihuman evil that has created conditions
intolerable for normal human life comes some new situation. This
new situation is, then, either the promise of an apocalyptic
entrance into a new evolutionary synthesis of the human and the
machine, or an all encompassing hallucination in which true
motives, and true affects, cannot be known. Neuromancer’s myth
of the evolution of a new cosmic entity out of human technology is
perhaps the only seriously positive version of the new situation –
but even it offers only limited transcendence, since the world is
much the same in Gibson’s later novel, Count Zero, set some
years later. 71
John Huntingdon, in a similar vein, notes that, although there are various, for
guerrilla activity in the belly of the beast, but at the same time the more ecstatic
71
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, ‘Cyberpunk and Neuromanticism’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming
the Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 182-193, p. 191. My emphasis.
76
its activity, the more it tends to obscure any political solution. It depicts
permanent state.’ 72 In other words, despite the frantic actions of the various
niche for themselves. Any overarching, systemic change is not only beyond their
power, but seemingly beyond their conception. Without change, there can be no
progress, and without progress the humanist idea of humanity transcending itself
own terms could provide posthumanist critics with some of their strongest
literary theory has apparently prevented critics from developing this argument.
The major exception to the cyberpunk rule of ignoring possibilities for systemic
continual process. Sterling’s motley crew of Mechanists, Shapers and the various
other factions in the novel Schismatrix and the short stories set in the same
their environments – all in all, a process which looks remarkably like humanist
transcendence. It is ironic that this occurs in the only work in the core of the
72
John Huntingdon, ‘Newness, Neuromancer, and the End of Narrative’, in T. Shippey (ed.)
Fictional Space: Essays on Contemporary Science Fiction, Oxford, Humanities Press, 1991,
pp.59-75, p. 72-73.
73
See Graham J. Murphy, ‘Angel(LINK) of Harlem: Techno-Spirituality in the Cyberpunk
Tradition’ in Sherryl Vint and Graham J. Murphy (eds.), Beyond Cyberpunk: New Critical
77
such as development towards capital ‘T’ truth, progress and, indeed intellectual
mixture of brand names thrown in) is preferred. The headlong plot of much
cyberpunk leaves little room for introspective character development, and things
rush to their ‘conclusion’ without any time for grand ideals. Indeed cyberpunk
also displays a certain disdain for the idea of conclusions, and for the teleological
‘conclusion’ reached at the end of the novel is simply that, for the characters we
know at least, not very much has changed. Despite the apocalyptic merging of
demons’, nothing changes very much in the outside world. Case is a little richer,
perhaps, but the frantic action of the novel, Case’s intense and self-destructive
desire to change things, has actually achieved nothing concrete. The merged AIs
seem to care little for human existence, and instead are more preoccupied with
conversing with another of their own kind. In response to Case’s queries ‘“So
what’s the score? How are things different? You running the world? You
Perspectives, Routledge, New York, 2010, pp. 211-227, pp. 213-216 for one of the rare analyses
of transcendence in the cyberpunk canon.
78
different. Things are things.’” 74 The world at the start of Count Zero, the next of
Gibson’s novels in the Sprawl trilogy, is much the same as the world in
not meaning for humans, the humanist understanding of meaning, but rather
is abandoned, then the idea that these truths can be acquired rationally is, at best,
argued – at least not for the human characters. Rather, there exists power and the
means to use it (or direct it for one’s own purposes). The characters in cyberpunk
novels simply are not interested in any narrative of common humanity. They lack
the time and inclination, and their imagined world does not allow for such
appreciated and valued than similarity – that which makes characters different to
others makes them valuable, and that which might make them similar to the
74
William Gibson, Neuromancer, Ace Books, New York, 1984, p. 270.
75
For an erudite expression of this idea, see John Christie, ‘Of AI’s and Others: William
Gibson’s Transit’, in Fiction 2000: Cyberpunk and the Future of Narrative, George Slusser and
Tom Shippey (eds.), University of Georgia Press, Athens (Georgia), 1992, pp. 171- 182, p. 174.
76
For a reasoned argument as to why difference theory (or differance theory) cannot ground a
constructive ethics, see R. Wolin, The Terms of Cultural Criticism: The Frankfurt School,
79
maligned, the fast-paced, exciting plot and narrative structure and brilliant use of
language in the novel remain its central features. The overarching plot structure
interpreted as the ‘posthumanist’ part of the novel. It is true that Case, Molly and
others are guided, in the end, by inhuman agents for inhuman ends. John Christie
his writing became consistently less posthumanist, both in intent and in outcome.
of the ‘catastrophic’ status change of the AIs (at least by human standards) as
reading Neuromancer in the light of both Count Zero and Mona Lisa Overdrive,
to argue that Gibson is rather saying that ‘meaning for machines’ (and
Neuromancer, Count Zero and Mona Lisa Overdrive can then be read as a
contiguous series. Perhaps ‘change for the machines,’ 78 to steal a phrase from Pat
Cadigan, only really matters when we (humans) change for them, not when they
change for themselves. In other words, whilst the human impact of the
Mona Lisa Overdrive, it is still there, and it is telling that this human impact, in
the form of the ongoing Angie/Bobby story, is the tale which Gibson chooses to
This chapter has examined the ways in which cyberpunk literature has
the body and mind. Many of these same critics have also argued that central
symbolic devices in cyberpunk act to undermine certain binary splits which they
argued that the figure of the cyborg, for example, so common in cyberpunk,
78
Pat Cadigan, Synners, Four Walls Eight Windows, New York, 2001, p. 97.
81
readings of cyberpunk fiction, not only for this reason, but because it has also
been argued that it radically deconstructs the humanist figure of ‘natural’ man.
posthumanists based on the figure of the cyborg in cyberpunk fiction are fraught
with difficulties. The argument that the cyborg symbolically represents a break
the last, on arguing that humanist theory has traditionally presented the human
body as the essential part of the human in its essentialist narratives. However,
this argument is does not accord with most preceding analyses of humanism.
too little, rather than too much attention to the human body, and with good
reason. The Enlightenment enthronement of pure reason did often come at the
of the role of embodiment, hard won in the main by feminist theory, has led to
critiques of humanism did not exist. If humanist thought had claimed that
critical mistake.
82
basket into which humanist thought placed its eggs. However, despite the
importance of reason to humanist thought. This chapter has argued that the
conception of the mind, but does not actually do any real deconstructing.
dualist mind/body paradigm is an idea which this thesis must challenge. In a later
Cartesian, and that the charge of dualism, as it so often is, was most likely
certain persuasion.
towards the grand narratives of the Enlightenment. Whilst a few critics have
examined this aspect of cyberpunk, on the whole it has been ignored. The
species, has largely been ignored. This chapter has suggested that this gap in the
critical literature has largely been the result of critics only examining the concept
83
thought such as progress and human freedoms remains perhaps the most
interpretations, it has discovered that there is room for the contestation of their
views. Indeed, whilst the majority of critical writing on cyberpunk deals with its
This chapter has therefore been developed in the spirit of Edward Said’s
what ‘we’ have always known and felt, but rather a means of questioning,
79
E. Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, Palgrave, New York, 2004, p. 28.
84
Science fiction repeatedly insists that humans are not the first,
the last, or the most important intelligent beings in the
cosmos; that in fact we are only one small part of a vast and
alien universe; and that, perhaps, the only appropriate
response to this environment is for humans to create, or
transform themselves into, alien beings. From this viewpoint,
those who continue to focus only on human concerns and
human limitations are the ones who are evading reality and
responsibility.
recent years. Volumes of critical work have been devoted to the subject. 1 It was
sometimes mental, selves they appear to be no longer human – at least in the way
we understand ‘human’ now. Secondly, due to the simple similarity between the
word ‘posthuman’ and the word ‘posthumanism’, theories of the posthuman were
1
These include, for instance, N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies
in Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1999; Judith
Halberstam and Ira Livingstone (eds.), Posthuman Bodies, Indiana University Press,
Bloomington, 1995; and Elaine L. Graham, Representations of the Post/Human: Monsters, Aliens
and Others in Popular Culture, Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2002.
85
already been pegged as posthumanist literature, 2 it became easy (and also quite
posthuman. However, this chapter will argue that the presence of ‘posthuman’
philosophical values are also in play: it will be argued that, in fact, the opposite
significantly different positions arise. The first, arising from the discourse of
Machines 3 or Hans Moravec’s Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human
concept of the human, however, is certainly not the only one available to theories
of the posthuman. The other major type of portrayal of the human upon which
Posthuman Bodies and How We Became Posthuman deploy and criticise an idea
2
See the previous chapter, ‘“Posthumanism With a Vengeance”: Posthumanism and Cyberpunk’
for description and analysis of the links between posthumanism and cyberpunk.
3
Ray Kurzweil, The Age of Spiritual Machines: How We Will Live, Work and Think in the New
Age of Intelligent Machines, Orion, London, 1999.
4
Hans Moravec, Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge (Mass.), 1988.
86
of the human derived from liberal humanist philosophy. This conception of the
after all, a theory which describes that which comes after the ‘human’ of
which proclaims itself as coming after humanism. Out of the plethora of different
some kind of binary opposition. Such a simplistic approach would not do justice
to the ways in which various critical texts deploy these theories, either
Indeed, the problems of the cybernetic theory of the posthuman have been
theory of the posthuman, from the point of view of Hayles, amongst others, 5 is
not so much that it does not consider the philosophical issues raised by the
humanist ideas of the self, but that it relies on liberal humanist understandings of
the self to inform and ground its very conception of the posthuman. As Hayles
puts it ‘One could argue that the erasure of embodiment is a feature common to
both the liberal humanist subject and the cybernetic posthuman.’ 6 Thus, rather
than challenging the ‘human’ (in the sense of the humanist definition of what it
of thinking. The philosophical posthuman, on the other hand, does not depend on
what it means to be a (post)human being, rather than the assertion that, as a sort
itself with examining what will come after homo sapiens, whereas the
subject have already been outlined in the previous chapter, so this chapter will
confine itself to those critiques which have been elaborated in concert with the
concrete ideas about the (liberal) humanist subject (basically the topic of critique
criticism (it could be argued that Hollinger in many ways set the tone for critics
The difference between the cybernetic idea of the posthuman and the
there has been unproductive confusion between what one might call a
popular and a more critical posthumanism…This popular
posthumanist (sometimes transhumanist) discourse structures the
research agendas of much of corporate biotechnology and
informatics as well as serving as a legitimating narrative for new
social entities…critical posthumanism [is] an interdisciplinary
perspective informed by academic poststructuralism, postmodernism,
feminist and postcolonial studies and science and technology
studies. 8
In an article from the same issue, Eugene Thacker also notes the ideological split
8
Bart Simon, ‘Introduction: Toward a Critique of Posthuman Futures’, Cultural Critique, 53, pp.
1-9, p. 2.
9
Eugene Thacker, ‘Data Made Flesh: Biotechnology and the Discourse of the Posthuman’,
Cultural Critique, 53, pp. 72-97, p. 73.
89
can really be. If, as Hayles’ insists, these discourses conceal liberal humanist
presumptions at their roots, then the use of the term ‘posthumanist’ to describe
Schismatrix, the term seems to have stuck (like Gibson’s most famous
These varied and disparate states all seem to be representative of that slippery
condition, the technological posthuman, or, as N. Katherine Hayles terms it, the
quoting in full.
examples from what one might call the prophets of a cybernetic posthuman
merger with her cybernetic implants and also the arrival on the scene (and later
primary difference between the human and the posthuman in this view is that the
entertainment. Kurzweil, for example, predicts that, in 2099, ‘Even among those
perceptual and cognitive abilities. Humans who do not utilise such implants are
10
N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body’, p. 242.
11
Conversations with ‘Molly’ occur irregularly throughout The Age of Spiritual Machines, but
the particular discussions referred to are located in Part Three, ‘To Face the Future’, pp. 236-313.
91
those still using native neuron-cell-based computation.’ 13 In other words, the vast
want of a better term), and that those who are not will be unable to participate in
a society and culture dependent on these infrastructures (one does at this point
wonder whether Kurzweil has considered people outside the upper classes of
human minds to computers, and makes arguments very similar to those made by
Kurzweil. Moravec argues that moving our minds to a different medium than the
human brain will be the only way to keep up with our computation cousins and
argues that, given the palpable limitations of human physicality, particularly our
ability to manipulate and interact with the outside world, these aspects of being
human would also have to change. 15 It would seem, then, that becoming the
Cyberpunk characters run the full gamut of what we might term the posthuman
12
Ray Kurzweil, The Age of Spiritual Machines, p. 293.
13
Ray Kurzweil, The Age of Spiritual Machines, pp. 292-293.
14
Hans Moravec, Mind Children, pp. 108-116.
15
See Hans Moravec, Mind Children, p. 102.
92
points receive new organs, and there is of course the bio-toxin which
‘encourages’ him to work for Armitage/Corto in the first place), through to the
This binary, which critics such as Hollinger claim is a crucial part of humanist
doctrine, 16 was discussed in a different light in the previous chapter, under the
and examined in the light of theories of the posthuman. In any case, it is clear
that, although cyberpunk, like most science fiction, extrapolates from present
Where in most previous genre science fiction the boundary between human and
there is an acceptance of the blurring of the line between human and machine.17
16
The claim, as I understand it, is not so much that any single binary pair is critical to humanist
thought, but that all humanist thought is composed of such binaries. See Veronica Hollinger,
‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’ where Hollinger argues that the human/machine binary is critical to
Enlightenment thought. This is also pertinent to the thought of Hayles and Graham, for whom the
sustaining of the ‘humanist’, Cartesian distinction between mind and body reveals the
presumptions of the cybernetic idea of the posthuman.
17
See Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’, p. 30 for a fuller expression of this
point.
93
human skin and becomes, in a more tangible way than in much prior science
that, rather than redeeming the binary opposition between the natural and the
cyberpunk act to blur the line between the human and the
the human body by technology decentres the body as inviolable locus of the
humanist subject, and fractures the humanist idea of the subject by creating a
host of possibilities for subjectivity. The de- (or re-) construction of the human
coffin of the Enlightenment idea of ‘essential’ humanity. If the human body can
essential self, it surely will not be when the physical part of that self is so
name which is critical in the discourse of cyberpunk critique. That other name is,
18
See, for example, Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, Science Fiction Studies, 22, 1995, pp.
357-371, and Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg
Writers’, Science Fiction Studies, 22, 1995, pp. 399-421.
94
of course, the cyborg, and much of the critical work on themes surrounding the
posthuman has made use of this concept. The term cyborg, however, has critical
and thematic resonances far beyond cyberpunk. Some of the most interesting and
provocative writing on the idea of the cyborg is that of Donna Haraway, and it
was inevitable that critics writing about cyberpunk would begin to examine
clearly resonates with many posthumanist cyberpunk critics. Indeed, at first blush
of the organic family, this time without the oedipal project. The
cyborg would not recognize the Garden of Eden; it is not made of
mud and cannot dream of returning to dust. Perhaps that is why I
want to see if cyborgs can subvert the apocalypse of returning to
nuclear dust in the manic compulsion to name the Enemy. Cyborgs
are not reverent; they do not re-member the cosmos. They are wary
of holism, but needy for connection- they seem to have a natural feel
for united front politics, but without the vanguard party. The main
trouble with cyborgs, of course, is that they are the illegitimate
offspring of militarism and patriarchal capitalism, not to mention
state socialism. But illegitimate offspring are often exceedingly
unfaithful to their origins. Their fathers, after all, are inessential. 19
dream of the future, extrapolated from the present. It is, in many ways, the
hopeful construct, that its boundary defying properties will allow it new means of
Whether or not one agrees with Haraway’s idea of the cyborg, however, it is not
necessarily the case that cyborgs in cyberpunk are developed with a similar
19
Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, New York,
Routledge, 1991, pp. 150-151.
20
Jenny Wolmark, ‘Staying with the Body: Narratives of the Posthuman in Contemporary
Science Fiction’, in Edging into the Future, Veronica Hollinger and Joan Gordon (eds.),
University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, 2002, pp.75-89, pp. 76-77.
96
deviate from, then reinstate the humanist position… This is not to say that
Haraway’s cyborg and the figures in Gibson’s cyberpunk novels are necessarily
between humanity and its technology.’ 21 Whilst it is true that Gibson’s novels
which the Haraway of the Manifesto is clearly opposed, there are other
their links to the forces which created them. In a world governed by the
trilogy, cyborgs are neither created ex nihilo nor is their existence guaranteed
outside of the system. Whilst Haraway maintains that the cyborg has ‘no truck
with… unalienated labour’, it is Gibson’s cyborgs who best embody this idea.
which the utopian idea of unalienated labour has been discarded, Gibson
imagines a system in which this has occurred. As John Huntingdon has put it,
21
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, pp. 403-404.
97
The problem with Haraway’s imagined cyborgs is fleshed out in their Gibsonian
counterparts. To insist that the cyborg will not countenance the idea of
unalienated labour is all very well, but it entails one of two choices. Either one
must deny that labour can be unalienated (in other words argue that all labour is
necessarily alienating) or one must argue that the ideas of both alienated and
Haraway’s cyborgs cannot help but become like Gibson’s – guerrilla fighters, in
a war they cannot win. If the second implication from Haraway’s argument is
altogether, then a powerful tool for understanding and opposing capitalism has
been lost. This is most likely Haraway’s argument, however – that the idea of
alienation has failed. The problem with Haraway’s cyborg with its ‘commitment
Without a systemic understanding and method for resisting capitalism, this thesis
one. After all, Gibson’s cyborgs do resist the system, in their own way. However,
nothing ever really changes. What Gibson’s cyborgs lack, when compared with
22
John Huntingdon, ‘Newness, Neuromancer, and the End of Narrative’, in Tom Shippey (ed.)
Fictional Space: Essays on Contemporary Science Fiction, Oxford, Humanities Press, 1991,
pp.59-75, pp. 72-73.
98
They may not be ‘true’ to their origins – but neither do they act against them.
This is perhaps the greater difference between Haraway’s cyborgs and Gibson’s.
Haraway imagines cyborgs which are somehow both a part of the system from
which they spring and yet not a part of it at the same time – Gibson’s cyborgs are
a financial sense as much as anything else, they belong. As Cathy Peppers points
out, Haraway’s
This question can be expanded to ask, simply, if cyborgs are as complicit as they
must be in systems of oppression, then to what extent will local acts of resistance
actually make a difference? How will partiality and irony serve a ‘posthuman’
who is, in a very real sense, constructed and owned by the system?
23
Cathy Peppers, ‘’I’ve Got You Under My Skin’: Cyber(sexed) Bodies in Cyberpunk Fictions’,
in Bodily Discursions: Genders, Representations, Technologies, Deborah S. Wilson and Christine
Moneera Laennec (eds.), State University of New York Press, 1997, pp. 163-185, p. 164.
99
in a relatively early piece of cyberpunk criticism, put it thus, ‘Human bodies too
are absorbed into this rhetorical conflation of organism and machine… The
human world replicates its own mechanical systems, and the border between the
organic and the artificial threatens to blur beyond recuperation.’ 24 The result of
all Enlightenment thought. The largest, though strangely the least mentioned, of
from all other things, by possession of the capacity for reasoned thought. The
figure of the cyborg, it is argued, has the power to dissolve this binary
distinction. In essence, the cyborg is a blend of the human and the not-human, or
human body. ‘’Cyborg politics’’, argues one cyberpunk critic, ‘opens the
24
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’, p. 31.
25
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 406. See also Timo Siivonen, ‘Cyborgs and
Generic Oxymorons: The Body and Technology in William Gibson’s Cyberspace Trilogy’,
Science Fiction Studies, 23, 1996, pp. 227-244, p. 227.
26
Scott Bukatman, ‘Postcards From the Posthuman Solar System’, p. 347.
100
In other words, the liminal figure of the cyborg, occupying the space between the
‘man’ and the machine, causes a tear in the intellectual fabric of humanism.
The figure of the cyborg, for these critics, represents a deconstruction of the
boundary. One does feel compelled to point out that the actions of Gibson’s
cyborgs, at least, very rarely have overt political overtones. As Istvan Csicsery-
27
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’, p. 30.
28
Timo Siivonen, ‘Cyborgs and Generic Oxymorons’, p. 229. For a similar interpretation, see,
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 406.
29
Istvan Csicsery-Ronay, ‘Cyberpunk and Neuromanticism’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming
the Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 182-193, p. 183.
101
Scott Bukatman’s dream of a liberatory ‘cyborg politics’ certainly does not seem
boundary-defying job that critics want them to accomplish. It is all very well to
say that the very nature of the cyborg makes it a boundary-defying construct, but
there are rather deeper issues at play. Humans have always existed in a complex
information technology and virtual reality. Technology always in some part plays
a role in defining what it is to be human, and this is surely also the case with the
which is infrequently asked, is ‘Does this actually make them that different from
us?’ The answer given by many critics of cyberpunk is undoubtedly ‘Yes’, yet
from a pristine biological state, they remain significantly human in the ways they
interact with each other and their world. As Norman Spinrad put it, when
of the relatively ordinary and indisputably human psyches of all these physically
which the machine plays an equal part with the human in the formation of a new
their technology which has characterised the traditional way of thinking about
technology for some time. 31 Indeed, even the characters in the technology-heavy
worlds of cyberpunk seem to recognise that the gap between humans and their
technology still exists. As the Dixie Flatline construct insists, with reference to
earlier argued that the cyborgs of cyberpunk are, unlike Haraway’s ideal cyborgs,
insight, when one takes into account that it has already been observed elsewhere
that ‘while postmodern subjectivity itself may seem at first strikingly radical, it
30
Norman Spinrad, Science Fiction in the Real World, 1990, Southern Illinois University Press,
Carbondale, p. 120. Emphasis in original text.
31
There is somewhat of an exception to this rule, namely the role of Artificial Intelligences in
Gibson’s Sprawl trilogy. For a thought provoking account of the relationship of the human and
the inhuman in Neuromancer, see Howard Caygill, ‘Surviving the Inhuman’, in Inhuman
Reflections: Thinking the Limits of the Human, Scott Brewster, John J. Joughin, David Owen and
Richard J. Walker (eds.), Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2000, pp. 217-229.
32
William Gibson, Neuromancer, Ace Books, 1984, p. 130. Emphasis in original text.
103
bears uncanny similarities to the structures of global capitalism.’ 33 If, in fact, the
perhaps not come as a surprise that the cyborgs of cyberpunk seem committed to
their capitalist roots. Indeed, whilst the future capitalism of cyberpunk often
capitalist system within the genre should not go unnoted. The association
between the cyborg, capitalism and cyberpunk has not passed everyone by,
however. David Brande suggests that ‘the cyborg is the “consciousness” of the
depicts a kind of utopia – namely, a capitalist one. Tom Moylan has suggested
that even the “rebel spaces” of cyberpunk are in fact commodified, and that ‘each
has found its niche on the planetary market.’ 36 Cyberpunk, therefore, suggests
that both the worst aspects of the humanist self and the capitalist paradigm can be
sustained within the idea of the cyborg. The lack of critical engagement with the
Eagleton regarding the postmodern left, that ‘The power of capital is now so
33
Laura Bartlett and Thomas B. Byers, ‘Back to the Future: The Humanist Matrix’, Cultural
Critique, 53, 2003, pp. 28-46, p. 29.
34
David Brande, ‘The Business of Cyberpunk: Symbolic Economy and Ideology in William
Gibson’, Configurations, 2:3, 1994, pp. 509-536, pp. 510-511.
35
Fredric Jameson, Archaeologies of the Future: The Desire Called Utopia and Other Science
Fictions, Verso, London, 2005, p. 21. In contrast, Brooks Landon has claimed that Neuromancer
‘[parodies] both capitalism and consumerism’. Brooks, Landon, Science Fiction After 1900:
From the Steam Man to the Stars, Routledge, New York, 2002, p. 162. On the whole, I think
Jameson’s analysis of cyberpunk is to be preferred, on this point at least. While Gibson may not
necessarily romanticise the various corporate entities which are involved in his novels, for
example, he undeniably romanticises the arch-capitalist worlds which result from their activities,
36
Tom Moylan, ‘Global Economy, Local Texts: Utopian/Dystopian Tension in William Gibson’s
Cyberpunk Trilogy’, in Sherryl Vint and Graham J. Murphy (eds.) Beyond Cyberpunk,
Routledge, New York, 2010, pp. 81-94, pp. 90-91.
104
sectors of the left succeeded in naturalizing it, taking it for granted as such an
unbudgable structure that it is as though they hardly have the heart to speak of
it’, 37 and earlier ‘We now find ourselves confronted with the mildly farcical
about that power which is the invisible colour of daily life, which determines our
existence… in almost every quarter, which decides in large measure the destiny
and the critical literature about it, this observation rings true. 39 Capitalism is the
elephant in the room, demanding our attention yet hardly ever discussed.
trilogy and Pat Cadigan’s imagining of them in Synners. There are strong
similarities, of course, not least in the fundamental ideas that the abstraction of
human consciousness into digital form is possible. However, in the end results
for Bobby and Angie in Gibson’s Mona Lisa Overdrive, as opposed to Visual
words, despite the complete removal of their minds from their previous
37
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, 1996, p. 23.
38
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, pp. 22-23.
39
There are, of course, exceptions to the rule in both the critical literature and the cyberpunk
oeuvre itself. Pawel Frelik, in his article discussing the fiction of Richard K. Morgan, observes
that Morgan ‘discards cyberpunk’s political blindness in ways both major and minor.’ Frelik is
entirely correct in his analysis, and this potentially makes Morgan’s novels an interesting new
chapter in the history of cyberpunk. See Pawel Frelik, ‘Woken Carbon: The Return of the Human
in Richard K. Morgan’s Takeshi Kovacs Novels’, in Sherryl Vint and Graham J. Murphy (eds.),
Beyond Cyberpunk: New Critical Perspectives, Routledge, New York, 2010, pp. 173-190, p. 176.
105
“Angie” that they had when they were embodied as humans. 40 In Synners,
much more complex. While Mark’s merger with the AI Art is necessitated by the
overarching plot structure of the novel (it is both Mark’s and Art’s only way of
surviving the virus unleashed into the system by Mark’s stroke(s) as he attempts
of digitising consciousness in two ways that Gibson does not. Firstly, Mark’s
move to cyberspace is fraught with danger in a way that Bobby and Angie’s is
not; whilst both they and he die in the process Visual Mark’s corporeal death
releases a dangerous computer virus which endangers many people, his new
survive by itself; it (he?) must merge with the AI Art in order to continue. Whilst
this could be read as a simple plot mechanism, it could also be read as a warning
whilst Cadigan seems to accept the idea of digitising consciousness, she does not
also accept that such a process would leave the mind involved unchanged. Whilst
this thesis has argued elsewhere that the digitisation of consciousness entails the
40
The final chapter of Mona Lisa Overdrive is a description of Bobby and Angie’s ‘life’ in the
cyberspace of the Aleph construct. Bobby and Angie, as well as The Finn and 3Jane exist within
it as discrete consciousnesses. See William Gibson, Mona Lisa Overdrive, Grafton Books, 1989,
pp. 313-316.
106
issue by re-raising the problem of embodiment. Sure, you can get the mind out of
its current body, she seems to be saying, but don’t expect it to remain exactly the
same when you put it into a new one. Indeed, by the end of Synners, Visual Mark
consciousnesses in Gibson and Cadigan’s texts, we can see that, even within
They remain, for most purposes, the same subjects; they are simply in different
The characters who inhabit these strange new worlds remain, quite noticeably,
human. Whilst aspects of their physical, mental and social selves seem to diverge
41
D. Kellner, Media Culture: Cultural Studies, Identity and Politics Between the Modern and the
Postmodern, Routledge, London, 1995, p. 309.
107
example, despite his ability to access cyberspace, retains a human, ‘meat’, body,
bliss with dead ‘Linda Lee and the thin child who called himself
to his body at least. At this point, it is pertinent to ask why? Why would Case,
virtual life in favour of a fragile embodied one? This is not the easiest question to
answer. Indeed, Case’s successor in the Sprawl trilogy, his spiritual inheritor,
Bobby Newmark, makes precisely the opposite choice, choosing to ‘live’ in the
Aleph construct rather than continue to exist in the ‘real’ world. The answer may
well be that Case, unlike Bobby, learned that the outside world had things in it
that Neuromancer simply could not replicate – maybe the thrill of hacking, or ‘a
girl who called herself Michael.’ 44 The alternative to Case’s decision to remain
apparent that the only thing the construct really wants is to be erased. The
Flatline, having worked out ‘he’ is dead, says to Case, ‘“Do me a favour,
boy…This scam of yours, when it’s over, you erase this goddam thing.”’ 45 The
Flatline construct ‘knows’ that it isn’t what it once was, that it isn’t McCoy
Pauley, and the knowledge of humanity lost is too much for the construct. The
42
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 244.
43
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 6.
44
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 270.
45
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 106.
108
Flatline is, unlike Linda Lee, a ghost who knows he’s a ghost, and he doesn’t like
it one bit. 46
characters of Visual Mark and Gina in particular, two different ways of being in
an information age are explored. Mark is, at best, tangentially connected to the
sense, similar to Gibson’s Case. Gina is more like Molly, although, as Bronwen
Calvert and Sue Walsh point out, ‘Readers of cyberpunk will recognise Gina as
paralleling Gibson’s Molly in her embodied nature; but whereas Molly never
has the opportunity to choose between the flesh and the mind, Gina has and uses
the same skills for her work as does Visual Mark; her choice of the body is an
informed one.’ 47 Both Mark and Case require rescuing by, respectively, Gina and
Molly, but whereas Molly provides a purely physical, and, as has been observed
Gina moves both in the mental world occupied by Mark and in her own active,
physical world. Their separate choices, however, create a stark divide in the
novel. Mark, in the end, decides to leave his body behind forever for an existence
remain human. 48 It is significant that Synners concludes with Gina, Sam and
46
For an interesting discussion of the implications of the digital reincarnation of McCoy Pauley
as the Flatline construct, see Chia-Yi Lee, ‘Beyond the Body: Kafka’s The Metamorphosis and
Gibson’s Neuromancer’, Concentric: Literary and Cultural Studies, 30:2, 2004, pp. 201-222.
47
Bronwen Calvert and Sue Walsh, ‘Speaking the Body: The Embodiment of ‘Feminist’
Cyberpunk’, in Speaking Science Fiction: Dialogues and Interpretations, Andy Sawyer and
David Seed (eds.), Liverpool University Press, Liverpool, 2000, pp. 96-108, p. 102.
48
Although it should be observed that Cadigan complicates even this choice – Gina opts to create
a digital ‘clone’ of her consciousness, so that she both chooses to remain embodied and become
digital.
109
Gabe (the characters who opt to remain embodied as humans), rather than
Mark/Art/Markt. It seems that, for Gina, Sam and Gabe at least, life continues,
despite the upheavals caused by the Spike (a near-global computer virus caused
cyberpunk authors, there remains, as McCaffery astutely points out, ‘an emphasis
human system. As Douglas Kellner has summarised the difference between the
49
Larry McCaffery, ‘An Interview With William Gibson’, in L. McCaffery (ed.) Storming the
Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 263-285, p. 280.
110
maintained that the rational subject does not, and never did, really exist. N.
Whilst one could argue that certain humanisms (the use of the plural indicating
that ‘humanism’ as the target of posthumanist thinking never existed outside the
50
Douglas Kellner, Media Culture, p. 305.
51
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, pp. 3-4.
52
As Martin Halliwell and Andy Mousley suggest, the plurality of the history of humanism is
conveniently ‘tidied up’ in posthumanist accounts of humanism. See Halliwell and Mousley,
111
the Hobbesian ‘state of nature’ model of the subject, it is undeniably true that
significant challenge to the liberal humanist model. Hayles’ clear and insightful
suggestion that the contemporary world has undergone an ‘epistemic shift toward
associated with the liberal subject, especially agency and choice’. 54 These
attempts at revival, given the status of Hayles’ posthuman subject, are fraught
criticism other than Hayles’ will also be examined, and this will be facilitated by
Hayles insists early in her book that ‘the construction of the posthuman
does not require the subject to be a literal cyborg.’ 55 This thesis contends that, for
the literal (or perhaps literary) cyborgs of cyberpunk, the inverse of this
statement is also true; to whit, the construction of a literal cyborg does not
require the subject to be a posthuman (at least not in the senses which Hayles
intends). It is far from the first time this has been pointed out, however. In the
body of works on the cyborg in cyberpunk critique, there are voices of dissent,
ready to insist that certainly not all cyborgs in cyberpunk are examples of doing
away with the humanist subject. Mary Catherine Harper, for example, has argued
that ‘Gibson’s cyborgs deviate from, then reinstate, the humanist position’. 56
Whilst this thesis has clearly not agreed with some of the assumptions critics
have made about the humanist subject (specifically their attachment to the
centred subject), it appears that the figure of the cyborg has more than one fate in
cyberpunk critiques, even for those authors who agree that something similar to
where the bad guys won. Hayles herself intimates this, citing Gibson’s
body that is left behind and a disembodied subjectivity that inhabits a virtual
realm.’ 58 However, whilst Hayles chooses the extreme form of the technological
posthuman in cyberpunk to illustrate her argument, one suspects that she could
56
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, pp. 403-404.
57
Cathy Peppers, ‘‘I’ve Got You Under My Skin’’ p. 175.
58
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 290.
113
equally have selected the cyborg subjectivity of Molly to support her case.
Cyberpunk, for example, depicts the new and revised bodies that have
emerged from the imaginative engagement of sf with information and
virtual technologies… While predominantly masculinist cyberpunk
narratives recognised the startling possibilities of the boundaries
between human and machine, the disembodied posthuman subject in
cyberspace nevertheless retained its unitary identity, thus failing to
dislodge what Anne Balsamo describes as “the obsessive
reinscription of dualistic gender identity in the interactions between
material bodies and technological devices. 59
such a way as to not require ‘literal cyborgs’. This is more than a clever
rhetorical trick, however. Hayles’ analyses and arguments penetrate beneath the
surface play of biological human vs. technological posthuman, into the territory
of genuine philosophy about the nature (or not) of humans (or posthumans).
especially where, as she points out, they are one and the same. Hayles’
observations on this point are most apt – and have interesting results for those
accounts which imply that that the presence of cybernetic posthumans in a text
Indeed, Hayles observes that many of the ideas underpinning the conception of
59
Jenny Wolmark, ‘Staying with the Body’, p. 76-77.
114
the cybernetic posthuman are directly derived from liberal humanist philosophy,
or rather, that the cybernetic posthuman results from the ‘lethal… grafting of the
Hayles’ primary issues with the liberal humanist conception of the human
seem to accord with Martin Halliwell and Andy Mousley’s identification of the
issue with the first of these presumptions, namely the supposed sovereignty of
the subject. The liberal humanist subject was encoded as unitary, self-sufficient
and sovereign over itself; Hayles, in contrast, holds to a theory which proposes
into the “we” of autonomous agents operating together to make a self’, 61 and
than it should be attributed to the humans acting within them. 62 This has some
profound implications, not least for Hayles’ proposed project of salvaging the
however, this chapter must confront two assumptions which Hayles makes, in
common with many other post/antihumanist authors. The first concerns the term
‘liberal humanist’; this thesis has insisted previously that liberal humanism is far
from the only option available to humanists, and now the time has come to
60
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, pp. 286-287.
61
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 6.
62
See N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, pp. 288-290.
115
discuss other humanisms. The plural form is used following Halliwell and
the use of instrumental rationality beyond its sphere, Habermas returns to a form
Habermas proposes that thinking can be divided into three broad spheres; the
the problem of the Enlightenment was not rationality per se, but the
argues (and this is the main thrust of his project) that another form of rationality
from its instrumental counterpart.’ 63 However, the reason for raising Habermas’
ideas here is not to discuss them in depth; but rather to argue that humanism is
not the monolithic beast, unresponsive to critique, that it is often made out to be
Habermas’ work,
63
Halliwell and Mousley, Critical Humanisms, p. 90.
116
mythological Lernean hydra. 65 Despite the negative connotations the simile has,
it is apparent that Badmington has grasped the great potential of the humanist
project for change and renewal. Indeed, as Halliwell and Mousley were at pains
project’, or, of course, ‘humanism’, do not do justice to the diverse and dynamic
disguised form of straw man argument. Either way, the richness and diversity of
thinkers have both at times been guilty. It is a presumption which takes the
nature of a binary division, in this case a bifurcation in theories of the self. That
64
Thomas McCarthy, ‘Introduction’, in Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of
Modernity (trans. Frederick Lawrence), The MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.), 1990, pp. vii-xvii, p.
xvii.
65
Neil Badmington, ‘Theorizing Posthumanism’, Cultural Critique, 53, 2003, pp. 10-27, pp. 10-
11.
66
For another commentary on the diverse meanings of the word ‘humanist’, see Terry Eagleton,
The Illusions of Postmodernism, pp. 128-130.
117
Terry Eagleton has pointed out, postmodern (and posthumanist) thought has a
binaries and then simply privilege one side over another. Eagleton comments
that:
The point at hand, regarding the fractured (or not) nature of the self is, one
suspects, a small case of this general problem. The standard liberal humanist
presumption about the self is that it is united, self-contained and sovereign; the
standard posthumanist response has simply been to posit the reverse, namely that
she ‘now finds [herself] saying things like “Well, my sleep agent wants to rest,
67
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, p. 26.
118
Hayles’ example, it will become apparent that the apparent either/or distinction
reconciliation. In other words, it is, in fact, possible and most likely fruitful to
reconciliatory model may look something like this. Let us imagine that, as in
Hayles’ example, two different agents (or drives) are pulling in different
directions. So, at the same time, I am both hungry and sleepy. Under the pure
indicate the innate problems of the model); I will reach a conclusion based on
decision; the action which is undertaken (sleeping or going to the shop) is simply
might propose that the two drives (hunger and tiredness) establish a conceptual
space. They create a moment of choice. This conceptual space, and myriad others
like it, are the conceptual space within which the rational consciousness (the self)
makes decisions. So the rational self, unlike the self of liberal humanism, is not
unaffected by its material situation; indeed, it is this very situation which gives it
the reason, as it were, to reason. This, one imagines, is by no means the only
in nature. The point that is being made is not so much that this model is correct,
but more to simply observe that such a model could exist. That being said, this
68
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 6.
69
See also Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, pp. 90-92, for other reasons why the
alleged opposition between ‘humanist’ and ‘decentred’ subjects may be a false dichotomy.
119
limited. She makes brief mention of Neuromancer, and devotes a short but clear
analysis to Neal Stephenson’s Snow Crash. The interest, for the purposes of this
Neuromancer) with the cybernetic conception of the posthuman, but not with her
more philosophical model of the posthuman. This is hardly surprising, when one
Hayles’ nightmare, she concludes, is ‘the grafting of the posthuman onto a liberal
humanist model of the self.’ 71 As we have observed, this is the usual model for
70
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 5. Hayles ‘nightmare’ in particular puts
me in mind of a more recent contributor to the science fiction field, Richard K. Morgan, in whose
works consciousness is recorded in ‘cortical stacks’ and bodies (referred to as ‘sleeves’) are
routinely changed.
71
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, pp. 286-287.
120
sticks closely to the cybernetic model of the posthuman. The one cyberpunk text
this is perhaps because it is in this text (rather than works by Gibson, Sterling or
Cadigan) that Hayles finds points of interest for her discussion. Having devoted
to simply repeat the conclusion of that analysis: that Hayles’ argument that ‘We
should value the late evolutionary add-ons of consciousness and reason not
because they are foundational but because they allow the human to emerge out of
response. This response is that if consciousness and reason allow the human to
emerge from the posthuman, then these attributes can indeed be argued to be
be a better term at this point, given the drift of Hayles’ argument), but of our
existence as humans.
cybernetic posthuman. Both of these systems, argues Hayles, privilege mind over
body to the point of wishing to discard the body altogether. This is not entirely a
72
N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body’, pp. 265-266.
121
necessary (given the extreme nature of the disembodying rhetorics with which
she engages) and strategic (in the sense, one suspects, that we can dismiss the
It is not certain, however, that the importance of her foundationalist account can
be quite so easily glossed over when examining Hayles’ work. Indeed, since
alternative view of the posthuman. The very word embodiment encapsulates two
concepts – the body, and that which is embodied. Whilst this could be termed a
strict denotative interpretation of the word, even its connotative usages still carry
carrying a new and complex form of foundationalism; one which insists it is not
only the reasoning mind nor only the material body which are foundational to the
two. Terry Eagleton has commented that ‘the new somatics restores us to the
achievements; but in banishing the ghost from the machine, it risks dispelling
73
See Thomas Foster, ‘Review: The Reappearing Body in Postmodern Technoculture’,
Contemporary Literature, 42:3, 2001, pp. 617-631, p. 630.
122
she manages to maintain, as Eagleton puts it, that ‘the truth of the body does not
lie, as the liberals like to think, somewhere in between, but in the impossible
phenomenologically just. It is not quite true that I have a body, and it is not quite
true that I am one either.’ 75 Hayles’ double-essentialist story walks the fine line,
the impossible tension which Eagleton describe, and does it well. Whilst it could
be argued that Hayles’ is far from any traditional foundationalist account of the
human, to argue, as does Foster, that Hayles’ foundationalism is simply not that
what she views as the dominant notion in the discourse of the cybernetic
but that this supposition is often made. As Hayles put it, ‘The pattern/randomness
dialectic does not erase the material world; information in fact derives its
74
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, p. 75.
75
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, p. 75. My emphasis.
76
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 19
77
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 19
123
erasure should be the subject of inquiry, not a presupposition that inquiry takes
for granted.’ 78 Hayles is insightful in making this claim; as she has observed
human form. Thus, for example, Case’s ‘flatlined’ EEG in a sequence near the
end of Neuromancer does not indicate the cessation of his cognitive function; the
cyberspace. Similarly, as has been noted earlier, in Mona Lisa Overdrive Bobby
and Angie both translate their consciousnesses into cyberspatial forms. It could
be argued, however, that not all cyberpunk is as simplistic in its acceptance of the
for example, Bronwen Calvert and Sue Walsh have observed that ‘For Cadigan,
what Gina calls “context”, the context of ‘social relationships with cultural
reference and value.’ Anne Balsamo suggests that Cadigan writes with an
78
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 28. Hayles’ emphasis.
79
See N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body’, p. 252.
80
Bronwen Calvert and Sue Walsh, ‘Speaking the Body: The Embodiment of ‘Feminist’
Cyberpunk’, in Speaking Science Fiction: Dialogues and Interpretations, Andy Sawyer and
David Seed (eds.), Liverpool University Press, Liverpool, 2000, pp. 96-108, p. 104.
124
the material, stating that ‘Only the embodied can really boogie all night in a hit-
and-run, or jump off a roof attached to bungi cords.’ 81 It could also be argued
that, in the character of the Rei Toi (the artificial personality construct whose
manoeuvres form part of the plot of Gibson’s Idoru) Gibson himself makes a
the Rei Toi opts for incarnation as a human in the concluding sequence of the
novel. Whilst in one sense this simply affirms priority of informational pattern
over material instantiation (in that the Rei Toi somehow becomes human – if
Gibson isn’t dealing in some sort of mystic trick, then her body would have to
sense it does just the opposite. It could be argued that, in the reverse
transcendence of the Rei Toi, her deliberate ‘fall’ into embodied humanity,
Gibson is making the argument that there is something critical about embodiment
to being human. Indeed, this seems to be the point of view of the Rei Toi. Tama
81
Pat Cadigan, Synners, Four Wall Eight Windows, New York, 1991, p. 433.
82
Tama Leaver, ‘“The Infinite Plasticity of the Digital”: Posthuman Possibilities, Embodiment
and Technology in William Gibson’s Interstitial Trilogy’, Reconstruction, 4:3, 2004,
http://reconstruction.eserver.org/043/leaver.htm.
125
Whether one accepts this argument or not it is clear, as Hayles herself recognises,
that cyberpunk ‘takes informatics as its central theme.’ 83 Given that this is the
specifically related to cyberpunk and in more general texts, this chapter has
cyberpunk critique. As has been observed, there are two significant and
posthuman are radically different; it has been the contention of this chapter that
the nature of the human self. As such, it is questionable whether such an account
can be amalgamated with the approach to the posthuman which this thesis has
humanism, it becomes obvious that the two competing theories of the posthuman
are just that: competing. Given the radically conflicting nature, of both their
83
N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, p. 30.
126
another. This chapter has further contended that critical confusion between the
two modes of the posthuman has led to a lack of clarity in cyberpunk criticism.
contention that, despite dealing with the idea of the cybernetic posthuman,
In short, then, the posthuman both is and is not a key critical theme in
cyberpunk. It is, in the sense that cyberpunk authors frequently deploy the
cybernetic idea of the posthuman in their characters and worlds. It is not, in the
sense that, despite critical accounts to the contrary, the posthuman in cyberpunk
more often than not bears no trace of what this chapter has termed the
Cyberpunk is most often set in worlds where the worst aspects of liberalism,
concepts of geographical space, ideas of place and belonging, and the sense of
space associated with things which are at best debatably actual spaces, such as
discursive threads to be drawn together under the same rubric, it has considerable
rhetorical power. This chapter will work in a similar way, drawing together
related to the different spaces which they interpret. Firstly, there are those
readings which deal with that much discussed novum of cyberpunk: cyberspace.
similarities to and differences from physical space which have provoked the most
1
For a discussion of the ‘spatial’ characteristics of cyberspace, see Jonathan Taylor, ‘The
Emerging Geographies of Virtual Worlds’, Geographical Review, 87:2, 1997, pp. 172-192.
128
spatiality, however, there are multiple interpretive strands. Secondly, and more
Gibson’s second, ‘Bridge’, trilogy, consisting of Virtual Light, Idoru, and All
‘spaces’ being examined in these threads of cyberpunk critique, there are also
depth without an analysis of the role of cyberspace. It remains one of the great
Analyses of cyberspatial spaces and their meanings fall into three main
categories. Firstly, there are those critics who argue that the cyberpunk
self. Secondly, there are those critics who agree that cyberpunk cyberspace is
Cartesian, but only in its spatial/mathematical format (it is important to draw this
2
See, for example, Gibson’s comments in Cory Doctorow, ‘William Gibson Interview
Transcript’, http://craphound.com/nonfic/transcript.html, viewed 23/02/09.
3
See, for example, Sabine Heuser, Virtual Geographies: Cyberpunk at the Intersection of the
Postmodern and Science Fiction, Rodopi Press, New York, 2003, p. 5; Victoria De Zwaan,
‘Rethinking the Slipstream: Kathy Acker Reads Neuromancer’, Science Fiction Studies, 24:3,
1997, pp. 459-470, p. 460. For another very interesting analysis of ‘newness’ and Neuromancer,
which contests this position, see John Huntingdon, ‘Newness, Neuromancer and the End of
Narrative’ in George Slusser and Tom Shippey (eds.), Fiction 2000: Cyberpunk and the Future of
Narrative, University of Georgia Press, Athens (Georgia), 1992, pp. 133-141.
129
distinction because one does not imply the other). 4 Lastly and perhaps most
influentially there are those critics who have argued that cyberspace in
theories regarding the hyperreal and simulacra. Whilst these three strands of
either one speaks of cyberspace as Cartesian in the dualist sense, Cartesian in the
simulacral society. This strange lack of intersection between the different modes
conception of the self (and hence the cyberpunk idea of cyberspace), whereas
hyperreality often celebrate that ‘fact’ (both in its literary incarnation and in its
dichotomy.’ 5 This thesis contends that, whilst it is true that the various depictions
4
One can agree, for example, that we reside in a space which can be mapped within a Cartesian
point-grid system, without necessarily agreeing that our mind and bodies are composed of
fundamentally different substances.
5
Kevin McCarron, ‘Corpses, Animals, Machines and Mannequins: The Body and Cyberpunk’, in
Cyberspace/Cyberbodies/Cyberpunk, Mike Featherstone and Roger Burrows (eds), Sage
Publications, London, 1995, pp. 261-273, p. 261.
130
of cyberspace in cyberpunk often act to place the mind at a distance from the
human body, this is not the same as a simple Cartesian postulation of the radical
would be best to attend to the various ways in which cyberspace has been read as
after all, argue that the mind is separable from the body. Descartes repeatedly
accords with the disparaging tone regarding the physical body adopted in much
cyberpunk. Indeed, cyberpunk may in fact take this derogation of the physical
further than does Descartes. For whilst Descartes does insist on a radical
separation of body and mind, he does not condemn the physical as mere ‘meat’.
of physical parts whose utility may have already been superseded’, 7 inherent in
work, and also Gibson’s later work, are more tempered in their views on their
physical existence), which has most likely led to the conclusion, drawn by many
dominant Cartesian dualism’ and that ‘“escape from the meat” into the realm of
the mind was exposed for its abandonment of the discourses of the body-as-
6
See for example René Descartes, Discourse on Method and the Meditations (trans. John
Veitch), Prometheus Books, New York, 1989, pp. 113-114.
7
Louis J. Kern, ‘Terminal Notions of What We May Become: Synthflesh, Cyberreality and the
Post-Human Body’, in Simulacrum America: The USA and the Popular Media, Elisabeth Kraus
and Carolin Auer (eds.), Camden House, Rochester, 2000, pp. 95-106, p. 98.
131
binary has been created between what we could term the ‘embodiment’ paradigm
of human nature and strict Cartesian dualism. That the two are conflicting views
cyberpunk have begun to assume that these are the only possible accounts of
consciousness and the body. Whilst this thesis has clearly expressed sympathies
with the embodiment paradigm, this does not mean that any and all other
consciousness being transferable from its original medium (the human body and
brain) into another medium (the processors of a computer) simply is not the same
to body (or matter). It is rather the case that, as Russell Blackford has pointed out
‘that all of the cyberpunks… radically reject that Cartesian account of the self.
of matter – rather than as separable from it. Descartes would not have been
8
Ross Farnell, ‘Posthuman Topologies: William Gibson’s “Architexture” in Virtual Light and
Idoru’, Science Fiction Studies, 25:3, 1998, pp. 459-480, p. 460.
132
and Gassendi, might have been.’ 9 Thus the difference between an ‘embodiment’
which insists that human consciousness is dependent in very real ways on being
embodied as a human, and another which does not discount the fact that the
nature of that matter is not of such critical importance. 10 The argument that
observes that Gibson may be ‘the victim of a contemporary penchant for literary
consciousnesses which are translated completely from their human bodies into
other forms (such as 3Jane, Bobby Newmark, Angie and The Finn in Gibson’s
Mona Lisa Overdrive and Visual Mark in Cadigan’s Synners) remain dependent
9
Russell Blackford, ‘Review: Reading the Ruined Cities’, Science Fiction Studies, 31:2, 2004,
pp. 264-270, p. 269. Emphasis in original text.
10
For a fuller explanation of similar arguments, see Chapter 3, ‘But it Ain’t No Way Human:
Theories of the Posthuman and Cyberpunk.’
11
Russell Blackford, ‘Review: Reading the Ruined Cities’, p. 270.
133
this near the conclusion of Mona Lisa Overdrive, when Slick Henry converses
with Molly. The conversation is about the continued existence of Bobby, Angie
and 3Jane in the cyberspace of the aleph biosoft. The point is made, however,
Visual Mark are contingent upon the continued functioning of their material
nature and consciousness, it is plain that those critics who insist that the model of
evidence.
from the work of N. Katherine Hayles. Hayles’ theses on the shift from a
12
William Gibson, Mona Lisa Overdrive, Grafton Books, 1989, pp. 309-310.
134
informational pattern which describes it. There are many examples of this in
various cyberpunk works (one could argue that any time a character enters
cyberspace/the Metaverse/the matrix is just such an example), but the single best
examples are from William Gibson’s ‘Sprawl’ trilogy. These are the various
completely into cyberspace – thus completely altering the material in which they
immaterial, over the matter in which it is conveyed, Hayles does not specifically
critique the cyberpunk discarding of the body. Without wishing to prefigure the
Marvin, that ‘information cannot be said to exist at all unless it has meaning, and
informs someone, and that, as the body may well provide critical context for who
that person is, we may want to very carefully consider the consequences of
Cartesian dualist themes, these spaces remain Cartesian in another way. The
Neuromancer. Cyberspace (in this case the cyberspace of the Sense/Net library
14
Carolyn Marvin, ‘Information and History’, in The Ideology of the Information Age, Jennifer
Daryl Slack and Fred Fejes (eds.), Ablex Publishing Corporation, Norwood, pp. 49-62, p. 51.
15
Further examination of the embodiment paradigm and cyberpunk will take place in a later
chapter on feminism and cyberpunk.
16
William Gibson, Mona Lisa Overdrive, Grafton Books, 1989, p. 63. My emphasis.
136
cyberspace offers considerably less space for railing against the evils of humanist
cyberpunk does bear more examination. Scott Bukatman has, albeit briefly,
examined the Cartesian spatial nature of cyberpunk cyberspaces, and has made a
couple of very important points regarding them. Firstly, Bukatman has observed
that cyberspace is ‘an abstraction of the data in all the computers in the human
observed that while the foundation of cyberspace is the infinite space of the
It is the contention of this thesis that Bukatman has insightfully recognised the
17
Scott Bukatman, Terminal Identity: The Virtual Subject in Postmodern Science Fiction, Duke
University Press, Durham, 1993, p. 152.
18
Scott Bukatman, Terminal Identity, p. 152.
137
statements). However, Bukatman also observes that this does not invalidate the
Whilst Ryan is right in arguing that these points do to some degree differentiate
cyberspace from physical space (although one could argue that real space is
infinite too – it is simply the case that we cannot get access to most of it) they do
not, as Ryan inaccurately puts it, distinguish cyberspace from Cartesian space.
Cartesian space and cyberspace have much in common – not least their infinitely
19
Marie-Laure Ryan, ‘Cyberspace, Virtuality and the Text’, in Cyberspace Textuality: Computer
Technology and Literary Theory, Marie-Laure Ryan (ed.), Indiana University Press,
Bloomington, 1999, pp. 78-107, p. 86.
138
very least, our perceptions of cyberspace (the Internet-as-it-is) do not have the
Firstly, as most critics who have written about cyberpunk have written from a
this chapter, Baudrillard’s theories relating to the hyperreal and simulation seem
remarkably apt for adoption by critics wishing to examine the use of cyberspace
simulacrum and the hyperreal are at best a little unclear. However, once one has
20
Scott Bukatman, Terminal Identity, p. 156.
21
Graham Murphy, ‘Post/Humanity and the Interstitial: A Glorification of Possibility in Gibson’s
Bridge Sequence’, Science Fiction Studies, 30:1, pp. 72-90, p. 74.
139
sorted through the apocalyptic debris which clutters much of Baudrillard’s work,
one thing at least becomes apparent. The ‘real’ is dead; in fact, according to
Baudrillard, it ‘is not just dead (as God is), it has purely and simply
order to establish this point, Baudrillard examines various phases of the image.
perhaps states; there seems to be relatively little actual argument) that the image
goes through several phases until it reaches the point of simulation, namely:
process of simulation, the foundation of his argument that society has already
philosophy. In other words, he traces a path which initially deals with art, that
his point, taking it to places where it frankly makes very little sense. Even if
Baudrillard’s system makes some sense when one considers it with relation to,
questioned even at this level), when one considers a more mundane, and yet
22
Jean Baudrillard, The Vital Illusion, ed. Julia Witwer, Columbia University Press, New York,
2000, pp. 61-62. See also Jean Baudrillard, The Intelligence of Evil: Or the Lucidity Pact, Berg,
Oxford, 2005, trans. Chris Turner, pp. 26-27 for a pithy summary of Baudrillard’s views on the
Real and the Virtual.
23
Jean Baudrillard, Simulations, Semiotext(e), New York, 1983, p. 11.
140
For at all levels of Baudrillard’s chain of simulation a brick remains exactly that.
It is intended, for the most part, to be piled on top of other bricks, with
to a code (‘simulation’). 24 This is, largely, because bricks, unlike works of art
anything. This is not to deny that they both do represent things and are
represented, but rather to argue that their primary function is other than
representation (in the case of bricks, they are for building things!). Despite
unstated part of his argument, namely that all the things created by humans in
our world are an attempt to represent something. Either Baudrillard must argue
making it (one might say that in this case he must argue that taking a photo of a
brick has the same purpose as the brick itself) or he must argue that
representation is always the primary function of any activity or creation (that the
worrying hole in his argument, one which must cast a negative light on those
who depend on his theories for their own interpretive efforts with regard to
cyberpunk. However, since few if any cyberpunk critics writing about simulation
24
For Baudrillard’s usages of these terms, see Jean Baudrillard, Simulations, p. 83.
141
The links drawn between the work of Jean Baudrillard and cyberpunk
two by any critic writing on the subject. Victor Margolin agrees, although he
Jean Baudrillard’s world of the simulacrum.’ 27 The links between the philosophy
reality (or, as Baudrillard would have it, a lack of reality) is an overt theme in
many cyberpunk novels. Indeed, one could say that the questioning of reality
was an obsession in cyberpunk fiction from the start; that the cyberpunk
However, it is not only this which raises the idea of the hyperreal in relation to
cyberpunk. As Lance Olsen puts it, in the fictional worlds of cyberpunk, ‘the
artificial and the real are fused and confused’. 28 It is precisely this confusion, the
inability to clearly distinguish between the ‘real’ and the simulated, the authentic
25
Scott Bukatman, Terminal Identity, p. 7.
26
Scott Bukatman, ‘There’s Always Tomorrowland: Disney and the Hypercinematic
Experience’, October, 57, pp. 55-78, p. 72.
27
Victor Margolin, ‘The Politics of the Artificial’, Leonardo, 28:5, pp. 349-356, p. 353.
28
Lance Olsen, William Gibson, Starmont House, Mercer Island, 1992, p. 108.
142
unreality blur, [and] the “artificial” becomes “realer” than the “real” itself.’29
depth than in Pat Cadigan’s Tea from an Empty Cup. In short, in Tea from an
committed in AR, which also leave the victims dead in the real world. This
would seem to be the archetypal situation of the confusion of the real and the
Murphy, for example, has said regarding the character Rez in Gibson’s second,
Whilst it is important to point out that, in Idoru, not only does Rez still exist as a
Laney’s inability to work his magic on the data stream surrounding Rez at this
point stems from only knowing the Rez/corporation/simulacrum and not Rez the
person, Murphy still makes an interesting point. To the majority of the people in
Indeed, it might be appropriate to say that this simulacrum-Rez is more real than
the real Rez, since it seems that there is in fact more evidence of it! Finally, at
the most extreme end of simulation sympathisers, there are those, like David
Porush, who seem to think that Baudrillard does not go far enough, that he is
afraid to plunge into the abyss which he had identified. Thus Porush writes of
Stop rattling the bars of your cage, Jean. You’re weeping in the
ruins. 31
30
Graham Murphy, ‘Post/Humanity and the Interstitial’, pp. 75-76.
31
David Porush, ‘The Architextuality of Transcendence: In Response to Jean Baudrillard’,
Science Fiction Studies, 18:3, 1991, pp. 323-325, p. 325.
144
It is not so certain, however, that at the end of Neuromancer the possibilities for
transcendence have, in fact, been ‘fertilised’. After all, the full quote which
‘“So what’s the score? How are things different? You running the show now?
You God?”
If anything, the conclusion of Neuromancer defuses any option for change, and it
generally the idea of virtuality in general offers support for Baudrillard’s ideas on
hyperreality, this thesis will contend that a fundamental error has been made. The
mistake stems from considering the virtual not to be ‘real’. This confusion stems
from a dual usage of the word real. On the one hand, real is used to denote the
opposite of unreal – for example, ‘Dinosaurs were real. They actually existed.’
On the other hand, ‘real’ and ‘virtual’ are opposed – for example ‘Have you
really met? No, but we have chatted on the web.’ In the first case, to reverse the
claim, to state that dinosaurs were not real, is a total negation of the stated fact.
One would have to make the opposite claim, namely that dinosaurs did not exist,
that they were not real. However, in the second case, denying that we have
‘really’ met a person because we have not met physically does not actually
negate the statement that we have met online, or spoken on the telephone. We
would, in making such a statement, neither intend to imply that the experience of
32
William Gibson, Neuromancer, Ace Books, 1984, p. 270.
145
chatting to someone online never happened, nor to imply that it was some kind of
fake experience (whilst people may be more able to lie online, this is no
indication that they will not do so in a face-to-face meeting), but rather implies
that a different category of real-world experience has taken place. The critical
fakes of real things, rather than as actually beings things in their own right.33
They may, of course, be both: a flight simulator used for pilot training, for
correct to say that one had the ‘faked’ experience of flying a plane, or to say
simply that one had had the experience of operating a flight simulator. It would
not, however, be correct to say that the flight simulator, or the experience derived
from it, were in some way not real. Indeed, whenever we board a plane, we rely
on the real experiences gained by the pilot in such simulations. The point being
made is that it makes no more sense to treat that flight simulator as a fake plane
than it does to treat the Mona Lisa as a fake woman. To draw a contrast between
virtual experience and ‘real’ experience is, similarly, to create a false dichotomy.
This is even more so in the worlds of cyberpunk, where cyberspace can be just as
dangerous as the physical world. One might well pose the question, ‘If you can
die there, how hyperreal is it?’ As Marie-Laure Ryan puts it, in response to
Michael Heim:
33
Marie-Laure Ryan distinguishes at least two potential explanatory models for the virtual in
‘Cyberspace, Virtuality and the Text’, in Cyberspace Textuality: Computer Technology and
Literary Theory, Marie-Laure Ryan (ed.), pp. 78-107, esp. pp. 88-100.
146
The recognition that cyberspace, both in our world and the imagined worlds of
cyberpunk, is in fact a part of reality, not separate from it, has been made by
Baudrillard who has said that ‘We have moved, then, from objective reality to a
later stage, a kind of ultra-reality which puts an end to both reality and
illusion.’ 37 It is the contention of this thesis that the ‘virtual’ has since its creation
been a part of the real – however, that does not mean that its importance has not
shifted. What critics have seen as an indicator of the dominance of the hyperreal
the death of the real – it is rather an indication that a new part of reality is
34
Marie-Laure Ryan, ‘Cyberspace, Virtuality and the Text’, in Cyberspace Textuality: Computer
Technology and Literary Theory, Marie-Laure Ryan (ed.), Indiana University Press,
Bloomington, 1999, p. 91. See also Dani Cavallero, ‘The Brain in a Vat in Cyberpunk: The
Persistence of the Flesh’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical
Sciences, 35:2, 2004, pp. 287-305, p. 302.
35
See, for example, Amy Novak, ‘Virtual Poltergeists and Memory: The Question of
Ahistoricism in William Gibson’s Neuromancer’, Hungarian Journal of English and American
Studies, 6:1, 2000, pp. 55-78.
36
See, for example, Andrew Leonard, ‘William Gibson, The Rolling Stone 40th Anniversary
Interview’,
http://www.rollingstone.com/politics/story/17227831/william_gibson_the_rolling_stone_40th_an
niversry_interview, viewed 23/02/09.
37
Jean Baudrillard, The Intelligence of Evil: Or, the Lucidity Pact, trans. Chris Turner, Berg,
Oxford, 2005, p. 27.
147
asserting itself. In doing so, it will change the ways in which people respond to
the rest of the world (Case’s disgust for the ‘meat’ world being an extreme
example of this), but it neither denies nor supplants the existence of the rest of
reality. Some critics have recognised this, and warned of the dangers of a
example, advises that, ‘As we suit up for the exciting future in cyberspace, we
must not lose touch with the Zionites, the body people who remain rooted in the
energies of the earth. They will nudge us out of our heady reverie in this new
In arguing that the ‘hyperreal’ is a part of the real, albeit a new and rapidly
hyperreality, to the point of the occlusion of the rest of the real (that bit where
we do things like eat, sleep, and reproduce!) is not only dangerous, but also
simulation can completely replace the rest of the real. It is the contention of this
thesis that, even in the simulacral worlds of cyberpunk, this is patently not the
38
Michael Heim, ‘The Erotic Ontology of Cyberspace’, in Michael Benedikt (ed), Cyberspace:
First Steps, MIT Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts), 1992, pp. 59-80, p. 80.
39
N. Katherine Hayles, ‘In Response to Jean Baudrillard: The Borders of Madness’, Science-
Fiction Studies, 18, 1991, pp. 321-323, p. 322.
148
case. In case anyone was going to make the mistake that Porush does, and see
terms of the mythform to say that the matrix has a God, since this being’s
omniscience and omnipotence are assumed to be limited to the matrix’, and that
agency.’ 40 In this passage Gibson too seems to imply that that virtual world is
not a substitute for the physical world, but rather an addendum – and one which
right about simulations and simulacra may not matter. This is because, they
argue, simulation and virtual reality are two different things, with different
Poster, at least, believes that the fundamental difference between virtual reality
40
William Gibson, Mona Lisa Overdrive, Grafton Books, London, 1989 (first published 1988), p.
138.
149
called into question, Poster does make an important point. Specifically, his
Nam (not the actual place, which has been destroyed, but rather an online version
cyberpunk critiques as ‘interstitial spaces’. The idea of the interstitial space has
moved through time, and across disciplines. The term is first used in Frederic M.
41
Mark Poster, ‘Theorizing Virtual Reality: Baudrillard and Derrida’, in Cyberspace Textuality:
Computer Technology and Literary Theory, Marie-Laure Ryan (ed.), Indiana University Press,
Bloomington, 1999, pp. 42-60, p. 50.
42
Graham Murphy, ‘Post/Humanity and the Interstitial’, p. 85.
150
Thrasher’s study, amongst other things, concludes that gang behaviour (which is
society, through employment, marriage or whatever else. The point here is not so
the areas they dealt with as ‘interstitial’ (recalling that this is Thrasher’s largely
derogatory term) books such as William Foote Whyte’s Street Corner Society,
Herbert J. Gans’ The Urban Villagers and Maurice R. Stein’s The Eclipse of
people to which and to whom Thrasher had given the term ‘interstitial.’ As
William Foote Whyte put it in the conclusion of Street Corner Society, ‘The
trouble with the slum district, some say, is that it is a disorganised community. In
problem is not lack of organisation but failure of its own social organisation to
43
Frederic M. Thrasher, The Gang: A Study of 1, 313 Gangs in Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, Chicago, 1937, p. 3. Emphasis in original text.
151
mesh with the structure of the society around it.’ 44 Herbert J. Gans also
emphasised that there were positive aspects of society inside interstitial zones –
that ‘life in the area resembled that found in the village or small town’ 45 in its
sociability and overall neighborliness. Interestingly, Gans also states that, within
the area of his study, ‘Deviant behaviour… was, of course, highly visible. As
long as the West Enders were not affected personally, however, they were highly
that this tolerance for difference is a part of why interstitial places are valued,
interview with Cory Doctorow, ‘The absence of the interstitial I find unbearable.
But not as unbearable as the idea that [the] interstitial is necessarily as banal as
interstitial which take place within cyberpunk critique, the concept had to
44
William Foote Whyte, Street Corner Society: The Social Structure of an Italian Slum,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1955 (Enlarged Second Edition: First published 1943),
pp. 272-273.
45
Herbert J. Gans, The Urban Villagers: Group and Class in the Life of Italian-Americans,
Macmillan, New York, 1962, p. 15.
46
Herbert J. Gans, The Urban Villagers, p. 14.
47
Cory Doctorow, ‘William Gibson Interview Transcript’,
http://craphound.com/nonfic/transcript.html, viewed 23/02/09.
152
undergo a further revision. This re-evaluation took place, unsurprisingly, with the
placed emphasis on the margins of things – they have often valorised these
margins, at the expense of the centre. The notion of the interstitial space has
undergone a similar transformation – from being the place (at the margins of the
dominant culture) where, baldly put, bad people went and bad things happened,
to being the place (still located at the margins of the dominant culture) which had
both positive and negative aspects, yet was internally relatively cohesive, to a
final stage in which both the isolation of the interstitial space from general
and culture came to be viewed as positive. One does not intend to disparage the
groups within the context of Western society; Terry Eagleton has astutely argued
that one of the most important achievements of the postmodern epoch has been
the gradual recognition of the histories and rights of such groups. 48 It is,
revalorisation of the idea of the interstitial space takes place. In particular, in the
work of Edward Said and Homi K. Bhabha on the place of the diasporic
intellectual, that place which is between cultures and between nations, the notion
multiculturalism and the role of the diasporic intellectual. Specifically of the idea
48
See Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, 1996, p.
121.
153
Bhabha’s reading of the interstitial not only draws the concept in a more positive
light; it also serves to expand the idea so that conceptual as well as physical
It is in this new, positive light which the idea of the interstitial is raised
texts as interstitial when they fulfil certain characteristics – specifically, that they
stand apart from the mainstream world physically and socially, and that they
spaces from William Gibson’s second, ‘Bridge’ trilogy. The first of these is the
ruin of the San Francisco Bay Bridge itself. It plays an important part throughout
the trilogy as a haven for the sympathetic characters within the scripts. The other,
the Walled City in Idoru, is also a haven of sorts, although, being ‘of the net, but
not on it’,50 the Walled City does not qualify as a physical space. However, since
49
Homi K. Bhabha, The Location of Culture, Routledge, London, 1994, pp. 2-3.
50
William Gibson, Idoru, Berkley Books, New York, 2003 (first printing 1996), p. 225.
154
the interstitial would make reference to the Walled City. It is of interest that both
the Walled City and the Bridge are ‘places’ where there are, effectively, no laws
– the constraints of normative society simply do not apply. In the case of the
Bridge, the police will not go there; in the case of the Walled City, as it exists
outside the bounds of ordinary cyberspace, they cannot get in. These outlaw
spaces are of critical importance for cyberpunk as a genre; not only because its
plots tend towards those of the heist/detective story, or that its protagonists are
frequently criminals, but also because these spaces help to lend cyberpunk its
both within cyberpunk writing and within the critical literature. They at once
serve as spaces within the system of late capitalism and without it; they provide
raising the spectre of Marxist theory). It will also be argued that the largely
Interstitial spaces also allow postmodern aesthetic theory to reclaim some of the
art. Terry Eagleton has argued that ‘Modernism is amongst other things a
155
strategy by which the dialectical and critical tension between creation and
postmodern attitude, ‘If the work of art is really a commodity then it might as
well admit it, with all the sang-froid it can muster.’ 52 The result of this collapsing
for sustained cultural critique within art. 53 Thus postmodern theory can no longer
depend upon the elitist, high cultural critical capacities of modernism; it must
turn to other sources, and other places for its alternatives. It is perhaps
which modernism utilised. Thus the interstitial space (otherwise known, it should
be pointed out, as a ghetto or slum 54), which could be described as the place
where the lowest of low culture takes place, supplants the role which high
cultural art and critique played within the modernist aesthetic paradigm.
However, within cyberpunk, as well as in the real world, interstitial places do not
seem to fulfil quite the resistant, critical role ascribed to them by critics. In the
real world, it is important to remember that a slum (or interstitial space) is largely
where one resides if one is too poor to live elsewhere – even if poverty increases
51
Terry Eagleton, ‘Capitalism, Modernism and Postmodernism’, New Left Review, 152, pp. 60-
73, p. 67.
52
Terry Eagleton, ‘Capitalism, Modernism and Postmodernism’, p. 68.
53
For an excellent discussion of the role of the work of art in cyberpunk see Sherryl Vint, ‘“The
Mainstream Finds its Own uses for Things”: Cyberpunk and Commodification’, in Sherryl Vint
and Graham J. Murphy (eds.), Beyond Cyberpunk: New Critical Perspectives, Routledge, New
York, 2010, pp. 95-115.
54
See, for example, Francesco Cordasco and Rocco G. Galatioto, ‘Ethnic Displacement in the
Interstitial Community: The East Harlem Experience’, Phylon, 31:3, pp. 302-312, esp. p. 302.
156
seems to recognise that these zones also serve another purpose within the
Terry Eagleton notes that ‘there are now a whole range of competing cultures,
where such novelties evolve, at least in the universe of Gibson’s ‘Bridge’ cycle. 56
of such outlaw zones: ‘He [Case] also saw a certain sense in the notion that
burgeoning technologies require outlaw zones, that Night City wasn’t there for
itself.’ 57 Capitalism requires the new in order to continue the dynamic drive to
profit; interstitial, hybrid spaces provide the new without too much risk of
broader social contamination. 58 Note that the recognition that such resistant
spaces are essential to the continuation of a dominant capitalism does not leave
one with only the lapse into silence and apathy a la Baudrillard 59 as a method of
resistance to systemic hegemony. Rather, the recognition that such spaces still
55
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, p. 39.
56
See William Gibson, All Tomorrow’s Parties, Berkley Books, 2003 (first published 1999), pp.
209-210. Scott Bukatman mentions that a similar sector appears in Bruce Sterling’s The Artificial
Kid. See Scott Bukatman, Terminal Identity, p. 169.
57
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 11.
58
See Tom Moylan, ‘Global Economy, Local Texts: Utopian/Dystopian Tension in William
Gibson’s Cyberpunk Trilogy’, in Sherryl Vint and Graham J. Murphy (eds.) Beyond Cyberpunk:
New Critical Perspectives, Routledge, New York, 2010, pp. 81-94, p. 91, where Moylan states
that ‘in terms of economic structures and practices the heroes and enclaves [of Gibson’s fiction]
become little more than useful cogs in those larger machines [of corporate capitalism].’
59
See Douglas Kellner, Jean Baudrillard: From Marxism to Postmodernism and Beyond, Polity
Press, Cambridge, 1989, p. 89.
157
exist within the broader system should provide critics with the will to examine
systemic issues, rather than give up on the majority for the sake of the
rather than, offering an alternative to it, is one which critics have been loath to
acknowledge. Ross Farnell, for example, argues that ‘Gibson develops the
consumption and privatisation,’ 60 and that the society of the Bridge is ‘a place of
imagines “radical alternatives to late capitalism.”’ 61 With respect, this not only
ignores the express role that the ‘villain’ capitalist of the Bridge sequence assigns
to the Bridge (noticeably one which fulfils a requirement of late capitalism) but
also wilfully ignores the fact that social fragmentation does not necessarily
conflict with the needs of the capitalist order. Whilst this chapter does not seek to
deny that interstitial spaces in cyberpunk do to some degree play the role which
critics desire them to (providing protective safe havens for those who differ from
It is with this in mind, as well as with the history of the idea of the
interstitial in consideration, that this thesis suggests that interstitial spaces have
been a part of cyberpunk from the start. Night City in Neuromancer could be
could call it an interstitial space as it fulfils several of the criteria for becoming
60
Ross Farnell, ‘Posthuman Topologies’, p. 464.
61
Ross Farnell, ‘Posthuman Topologies’, p. 466.
158
such a space. Firstly, it exists physically outside the ordinary spaces of society.
Secondly, it exists legally outside the normal spaces of society; this makes it very
similar to other interstitial spaces, which are de facto outside normal law,
whereas Freeside is de jure outside normal law. Lastly, within its society,
normative rules which differ greatly from those of general society prevail. It is
debatable, however, whether the interstitial zone which is Freeside has any
abuse and insanity; without wishing to appear judgmental, these can hardly be
good outcomes for the participants in this interstitial society. The problem with
good; this has the effect of casting normative behaviours as bad. These are both
no means all bad (there are often good reasons for normative rules – try
imagining a city where which side of the road people drove on was left to
individual choice), and that difference from normative rules can be either or both
good or bad. As Terry Eagleton has put it, regarding the postmodern tendency to
celebrate marginality, ‘One could envisage much celebration of the marginal and
and those who believe in lashing delinquent adolescents until the blood runs
down their thighs.’ 62 Neither normativity nor difference are unalloyed goods, and
62
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, p. 3.
159
contemporary society. The same can be said of interstitial spaces; spaces where
the disciplinary gaze of normative society is blocked are not necessarily either
always valorised, and the potential for systemic change of mass society
going along alright. However, one must ask whether such tiny islands in the vast
sea of oppression are, in fact, enough. For some critics, at least, they are not.
treat this as a positive move, the alternative interpretation is more likely correct:
regionalism only looks good when we have abandoned the world at large to
capitalist domination. This thesis argues that we can do better than hunt the
fringes of the capitalist world for places to hide – and that the message we should
63
Once again, this idea has its genesis in Terry Eagleton’s The Illusions of Postmodernism.
64
John Huntingdon, ‘Newness, Neuromancer, and the End of Narrative’, in Tom Shippey (ed.)
Fictional Space: Essays on Contemporary Science Fiction, Oxford, Humanities Press, 1991, pp.
59-75, pp. 72-73.
65
Ross Farnell, ‘Posthuman Topologies’, p. 466.
160
likely take from cyberpunk is one which is critical of the dominance of capital in
contemporary society.
161
has often been lively debate within feminist criticism about the nature and role of
from active feminist writing to the worst kind of misogynist literature. As will be
observed in this chapter, there are good reasons for this diversity of feminist
all have the same or similar responses to cyberpunk writing is foolish. Indeed,
this thesis has elsewhere observed that an unproductive critical unity has all too
often eventuated in critical literature about cyberpunk, and has argued that room
cyberpunk.
There are, however, other, less prosaic factors which lead to the wildly
are, of course, other critics who take issue with this particular form of
raising the monstrous figure of the cyborg – or at least Donna Haraway’s vastly
influential examination of it. 4 This, it would seem, is one of the places where
surprise, then, that the idea of the cyborg as expressed in cyberpunk fiction has
1
Since I have already devoted a chapter of this thesis to discussion of post/antihumanist
interpretations of cyberpunk, I feel it is unnecessary to reproduce the bulk of my arguments from
that chapter here. It will suffice to say that I believe that the problems with more general
antihumanist accounts of cyberpunk hold true for antihumanist feminist accounts of cyberpunk.
2
See, for example, Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg
Writers’, Science Fiction Studies, 22:3, 1995, pp. 399-421; Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’,
Science Fiction Studies, 22:3, 1995, pp. 357-371. Arguably both these authors conflate
antihumanism and feminism, leading to the conclusion that (for them) anything which
undermines humanism must also undermine patriarchy.
3
See, for example, Vivian Sobchack, ‘Beating the Meat/Surviving the Text, or How to Get Out
of this Century Alive’, in Cyberspace/Cyberbodies/Cyberpunk, Mike Featherstone and Roger
Burrows (eds.), Sage Publications, London, 1995, pp. 205-214. Sobchack emphasises the
importance of the body as a counter to disembodying rhetorics.
4
It would be impractical to attempt to list all of the authors who reference Haraway here. Suffice
to say that ‘The Cyborg Manifesto’ is a continual presence in feminist cyberpunk criticism, from
Sharon Stockton, ‘‘The Self Regained’: Cyberpunk’s Retreat to the Imperium’, Contemporary
Literature, 36:4, 1995, pp. 588-612, through to the most recent feminist writing on cyberpunk,
for example, Helen Merrick, The Secret Feminist Cabal: A Cultural History of Science Fiction
Feminisms, Aqueduct Press, Seattle, 2009.
163
cyberpunk, and as a result of its rich history, feminist criticism about cyberpunk
fiction, and, critically, feminist cyberpunk criticism has been a very important
part of the overall critical community for cyberpunk. Many of the programmatic
about cyberpunk.
Feminist cyberpunk criticism was not, however, born whole and complete
critique which dates back almost as far as the genre itself. In order to gain a
will briefly illuminate some key phases and ideas in the history of feminist
as to claim that one could represent the full richness of feminist contributions to
arguably, dates back almost a far as generic science fiction. Helen Merrick, in
The Secret Feminist Cabal, discusses in some depth the ‘sex scandal’ of science
fiction in the 1920s and ‘30s. Merrick makes a number of important points in her
century. The first, is, most obviously, that opposition from women readers of
science fiction to the hackneyed and misogynistic gender portrayals in the genre
literature (and, for that matter, in the critical literature) was extant from the ‘20s
onwards. 5 The second point that can be inferred from Merrick’s work is an
understanding that will not be novel to anyone familiar to the field of science
1960s, we must look outside the academic circuit. Prior to the ‘60s, science
debates as existed largely took place in the pages of science fiction magazines
feminism and science fiction, these early, fannish contributions to the history are
not lost.
observing that feminist criticism within science fiction went through a period of
growth in the 1960s and ‘70s. Merrick associates this with the ‘sociopolitical
debates [of the time] … the impact of the women’s liberation movement, as well
as a result of trends within the field itself.’ 6 This last could be taken to either
mean the emergence of more radical feminist science fictions (such as Joanna
5
See Helen Merrick, The Secret Feminist Cabal, pp. 34-39.
6
Helen Merrick, The Secret Feminist Cabal, p. 34.
165
science fiction criticism creating a new conceptual space within which feminist
science fiction criticism could be written. Either would be true. The boundaries
between fans, authors and academic writers at this point in time seem to be
blurred (as indeed they may still be), with many people seeming to occupy more
than one of these positions. Joanna Russ’ critical contributions seem to move
and Russ was actively writing science fiction at the time as well.
The critical work of Joanna Russ is a better place than most to start any
and writing) which took place in the 1970s. In a piece entitled ‘What Can a
Heroine Do or, Why Women Can’t Write’, Russ herself provides some
explanation for why generic science fiction (along with a list of other
speculation. Having heavily criticised the literary myths which realist fiction has
inherited as innately sexist, Russ, late in the paper, argues that ‘science fiction,
political fiction and the modes (if not the content) of much medieval fiction all
provide myths for the kinds of experiences we are actually having now, instead
of the literary myths we have inherited, which only tell us about the kinds of
Our traditions, our books, our morals, our manners, our films,
our speech, our economic organisation, everything we have
inherited, tell us that to be a Man one must bend Nature to one’s
7
Joanna Russ, ‘What Can a Heroine Do, or, Why Women Can’t Write’, in Joanna Russ, To Write
Like a Woman: Essays in Feminism and Science Fiction, Indiana University Press, Bloomington,
1995, pp. 79-93, p. 92.
166
This line of argument bears a striking resemblance to those which conclude that
innate (though not always realised) capacity to explore new ideas, and create
new myths, that both feminism and general philosophy find attractive. Sarah
Lefanu also argued that the mode of science fiction lends itself to feminist
[I]t lets writers defamilarise the familiar, and make familiar the
new and strange. These twin possibilities, apparently
contradictory (but SF is full of contradictions), offer enormous
scope to women writers who are thus released from the
constraints of realism. The social and sexual hierarchies of the
contemporary world can be examined through the process of
‘estrangement’, thus challenging normative ideas of gender roles;
and visions of different worlds can be created, made familiar to
the reader through the process of narrative. 9
Science fiction is uniquely useful to feminist authors because it has the power of
feminist science fiction criticism, Lefanu’s book belongs in what might rightly
8
Joanna Russ, ‘What Can a Heroine Do, or, Why Women Can’t Write’, p. 93.
9
Sarah Lefanu, In the Chinks of the World Machine: Feminism and Science Fiction, The
Women’s Press, London, 1988, pp. 21-22.
167
until the 1980s, when it became more common in the sf journals, the first edited
Lefanu’s book as one of these two early monographs on feminism and science
Fiction and Feminist Theory. Whilst neither of these texts discuss cyberpunk,
their dates of publication (Lefanu, 1987 and Barr, 1988) are not far removed
from the first frenetic period of academic discussion of cyberpunk fiction, which
largely took place in the late ‘80s and early ‘90s. This may go some way to
science fiction criticism emerged from the academic wilderness, a place to which
establishment, cyberpunk was the newest, hippest form of science fiction around.
cyberpunk fictions is the ways in which feminist science fiction and, more
Russ once again has a formative opinion on the subject of technology. In her
politics and economics are the specific examples Russ gives. 11 Drawing on
10
Helen Merrick, The Secret Feminist Cabal, pp. 14-15.
11
Joanna Russ, ‘SF and Technology as Mystification’, in Joanna Russ, To Write Like a Woman:
Essays in Feminism and Science Fiction, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1995, pp. 26-
40, particularly pp. 34-39.
168
Russ does not associate technology and masculinity tout court – she is too
skilled a critic to do such a thing – but the association between the reification of
much of the feminist science fiction work of the time, with a contrast being
the observation that, ‘Without exception the stories are ecology-minded. Such
go beyond the problems of living in the world without disturbing its ecological
to the natural world.’ 13 Marleen S. Barr observes something similar about Marge
Piercy’s Woman on the Edge of Time. Barr notes that ‘The exaggerated
around “feminine” and “masculine” in her analysis indicates that she must have
some suspicions regarding the association of the masculine with technology and
12
Joanna Russ, ‘SF and Technology as Mystification’, p. 34.
13
Joanna Russ, ‘Recent Feminist Utopias’, in Joanna Russ, To Write Like a Woman: Essays in
Feminism and Science Fiction, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1995, pp. 133-148, p.
137.
14
Marleen S. Barr, Alien to Femininity: Speculative Fiction and Feminist Theory, Greenwood
Press, New York, 1987, p. 55.
169
the feminine with the natural world, the association is still undeniably there in
this piece of analysis (and in the novel itself). This reciprocal relationship
intersecting interests – or, to put it another way, they often seem to be discussing
often consist of the working through of these apparent intersections, and the
working through feminist concerns in cyberpunk has raised issues relevant to the
critical process more broadly. Indeed, it is apparent when reading much of the
discussions.
article ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, which was originally published in Science
Fiction Eye in 1991, in which Gordon proposed not so much that cyberpunk was
actively feminist, but that cyberpunk had something to offer feminist science
fiction. Gordon’s criticism of the extant canon of feminist science fiction was
15
An interesting article on the negative association of women with the natural world prevailing in
masculinist science fiction is Scott Sanders, ‘Woman as Nature in Science Fiction’, in Future
Females: A Critical Anthology, Marleen S. Barr (ed.), Bowling Green State University Popular
Press, Bowling Green, 1981, pp. 42-59.
170
archetypal Great Mother.’ 16 Gordon’s problem with such fictions is not so much
that they do not have value, but that the far future worlds imagined in such
feminist science fiction typically struggle to extrapolate their meanings back into
salvation.’ 17 This, Gordon argues, is largely due to the gritty, near-future settings
of cyberpunk; as she puts it, ‘It isn’t likely that the earth will pull back from its
movement towards high technology and the Sprawl for a long time, if ever.
Cyberpunk, with all its cynicism, shows a future we might reasonably expect,
and shows people successfully coping, surviving and manipulating it.’ Further,
Gordon observes that, ‘I for one am not convinced that I am an earth mother.
What else might I be? If science fiction can show what it means to be female in
fiction, stating that, ‘Overt feminist science fiction always grapples with the
its values often ignore specifically feminist issues, making its morality more of a
generally applied one.’ 19 In the part of her argument which has induced the most
intense analysis and debate, Gordon goes on to argue that cyberpunk writing
constitutes covert feminist science fiction, that ‘On that night foray into the
16
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming the Reality
Studio, Duke University Press, 1991, pp. 196-202, p. 199.
17
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 197.
18
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 200.
19
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 196.
171
cyberpunk, men and women travel as equals.’ 20 Citing Molly from Gibson’s
Gordon argues that they ‘[perform] the covert feminist act of entering the human
that cyberpunk ‘seems to be overt masculinist science fiction – men are men,
waving guns and knives, competing like all getout and plugged up to the gills
critics, most prominently Sharon Stockton and Nicola Nixon, disagree. 23 They
both argue, in different ways, that the appearance of cyberpunk texts is not
deceiving – that if it walks like a sexist text, and quacks like a sexist text, then it
probably is a sexist text. Of course, their arguments are vastly more involved
than this, and their interpretations have each left a lasting impact on cyberpunk
Keeping the Boys Satisfied?’ is another early and important piece of feminist
criticism of cyberpunk. In it, Nixon takes issue with the ‘revolutionary’ tone of
20
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 196.
21
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 197.
22
Joan Gordon, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, p. 196.
23
See Sharon Stockton, ‘‘The Self Regained’: Cyberpunk’s Retreat to the Imperium’,
Contemporary Literature, 36:4, 1995, pp. 588-612; Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the
Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys Satisfied?’, Science Fiction Studies, 19:2, 1992, pp.
219-235.
172
or the adoption of a similar tone by critics. Nixon stresses that ‘If we are to take
wake of, and contemporaneous with, particular forms of political, feminist SF,
but also as a response to (or perhaps a reflection of) the Reaganite America of the
‘80s.’ 24 Nixon here emphasises that cyberpunk did not emerge in a cultural
vacuum – and also that its cultural context must be of importance when assessing
the nature of cyberpunk texts. Nixon proceeds with a commentary on the much
Whilst Nixon’s argument undeniably has a core of truth (the physical parallels
between Jael and Molly only reinforce their jarringly different circumstances)
she has overstated the point. To claim, on the basis of this, that Neuromancer is a
covert reworking of The Female Man is to do both texts a grave disservice. The
24
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, p. 221.
25
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, p. 222.
173
Female Man can hardly be reduced to the single character of Jael; nor can
Female Man.
continued along these separate lines of development for some time, but this
This was not the case. Almost as if in response to Gordon’s call for feminists to
engage with the cyberpunk imaginary, new feminist cyberpunk authors began to
cyberpunk writing (Pat Cadigan came on to the cyberpunk scene earlier than this,
feminist critics). 26 Authors such as Laura Mixon, Mary Rosenblum and Melissa
Scott began to construct fictions which were both cyberpunk in setting and
overtly feminist in intent. In Trouble and Her Friends, for example, Scott
contested by a central character who is both female and queer – precisely the
cyberpunk.
the critical literature. As these new, overtly feminist fictions came into being,
feminist critics began to discuss the politics of these new contributions at least as
26
Jenny Wolmark, for example, distinguishes Cadigan from the other, male, early cyberpunk
authors. See Jenny Wolmark, Aliens and Others: Science Fiction, Feminism and Postmodernism,
University of Iowa Press, Iowa City, 1994, pp. 121-127. Sherryl Vint does likewise in Bodies of
Tomorrow: Technology, Subjectivity, Science Fiction, University of Toronto Press, Toronto,
2007, pp. 111-118.
174
much as those of earlier cyberpunk. It is the goal of the remainder of this chapter
symbiosis. Themes which are explored in one strand are often adopted or
critical literature – each form of criticism tends to bring its own interpretive
matrices to the project of reading literature. Despite this, some of the interpretive
previous chapters of this thesis. Donna Haraway’s idea of the cyborg, for
has escaped the circle of feminist criticism and become a fixture of cyberpunk
criticism in general. The same is true of other feminist interpretive models. The
been deployed in cyberpunk criticism more generally. Whilst both of these, and
have been discussed elsewhere in this thesis, it will be observed through the
course of this chapter that the feminist uses of these paradigmatic concepts,
usage from the ways in which these concepts are used in cyberpunk criticism
more generally.
175
the cyborg would become a central feature of feminist writing about cyberpunk.
variety of descriptions gave at least a prima facie case for the application of
have been a surprise if feminist critics had not deployed Haraway’s model in
cyborg.
terms of subject unities and binary oppositions. For example, one (allegedly)
united category might be that of women (or perhaps worse, ‘Woman’) – the
given the topic at hand, might be that problematic opposition between male and
female. While it has been the case that feminist theory has often turned its
attention towards the analysis of this binary distinction, and the undeniable
privilege which Western cultures have attached to the male half of this binary,
176
Haraway’s cyborg theory seeks not only to contest the privileges attaching to the
imaginings has centred not so much on whether they are cyborgs (this seems
beyond dispute) but rather on whether these cyberpunk cyborgs have all that
much in common with Haraway’s model of the cyborg. Haraway’s idea(l) of the
there are other meanings to the cyborg metaphor, interpretations which have far
more sinister overtones. Haraway herself acknowledges this, when she states that
‘The main trouble with cyborgs, of course, is that they are the illegitimate
27
Bruce Sterling, Schismatrix Plus, Berkley, New York, 1996, p. 225. (Schismatrix first
published 1985)
28
Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, New York,
Routledge, 1991, p. 151.
177
arises as much from which cyberpunk texts critics choose to analyse as from an
However, there are still significant differences of opinion regarding the liberatory
power of the image of the cyborg as it is deployed in cyberpunk texts, and these
fiction, cyberpunk and posthumanism – but does not consider whether or not
raising Haraway’s Cyborg Manifesto as ‘one of the most brilliant visions of the
the ‘humanist’ binary distinction between human and technology and the claim
29
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions: Cyberpunk and Postmodernism’, Mosaic,
23:2, 1990, pp. 29-44, p. 42. Cybernetic deconstructions is the term which Hollinger uses to
describe the interactions between humans and technology in cyberpunk.
30
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’, p. 41.
178
any measure, almost all the characters in cyberpunk novels are cyborgs – to
(by whatever name individual authors give it), to body modifications and
implanted technologies. Given the key nature of the idea of the cyborg to
this figure as support for their own interpretations of the sub-genre. A common
figure of boundary disruption. Take, for example, Mary Catherine Harper, who,
and the fictional cyborgs of William Gibson, states that ‘This is not to say that
Haraway’s cyborg and the figures in Gibson’s cyberpunk novels are necessarily
between humanity and its technology.’ 31 While this is not different from much of
links the figure of the cyborg, and its attack on humanism, to feminism. Later in
the same article, Harper posits that: ‘Even in its simplest form, the ontological
embracing the post-apocalyptic body… share close kinship with the Feminine
31
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg Writers’, Science
Fiction Studies, 22:3, 1995, pp. 399-421, pp. 403-404. My italics.
179
Other, that gendered, slippery discursive body given the power to effect, and
perhaps unbind, humanist dreams of escape from the body and entry into the vast
world of the mind.’ 32 It is obvious that Harper considers the cyborg’s status as
Cyborgs are, in fact, complex creatures – and it could be argued that ‘by
their nature’ they are nothing in particular. They are rather what they are made to
be. This seems to be the position taken by the bulk of feminists examining
cyberpunk and its cyborg characters. Karen Cadora, for example, argues that
that the cyborgs they portray embody, so to speak, this difference. As Cadora
puts it,
Having drawn this distinction between masculinist and feminist cyberpunk, and
the cyborgs which they respectively portray, Cadora goes on to argue that
feminist cyberpunk authors such as Mary Rosenblum and Laura Mixon ‘depict
32
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 406.
33
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, pp. 359-360.
180
female characters who find ways to work around or within the system.’ 34 What
matters most, according to Cadora, is not so much that cyborgs are present within
a work, but what kind of cyborgs these beings are – what they do, and,
Other feminists have also recognised the problem with adopting the
cyberpunk is obvious. With this question in mind, it cannot be taken for granted
that the cyberpunk cyborgs act to disrupt the boundaries of gender in positive
ways. Cyberpunk texts cannot be read as feminist texts simply because they
contain cyborgs – a point which occasionally seems to have been lost from
Haraway’s ‘Manifesto’. Haraway herself warns that ‘the cyborg is also the awful
space.’ 36 It is with warnings such as these in mind that one imagines Lauraine
Leblanc commenting that ‘Writers such as Gibson and Cadigan present female-
Later in the same piece, Leblanc states that ‘Molly’s character can best be
character, but one who uses her cyborg identity not to rethink what it is to be a
woman, but rather one who does little but take on a masculine role.’ 38 With
respect, Leblanc may in fact give Gibson more credit that he deserves here –
Neuromancer, not the least as Case’s lover. Molly exists as an objectified and
fascinated viewers. Riviera states, appropriately enough, that ‘The title of the
36
Donna Haraway, ‘A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-Feminism in the
Late Twentieth Century’, in Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, New
York; Routledge, 1991, pp.149-181, pp. 150-151.
37
Lauraine Leblanc, ‘Razor Girls: Genre and Gender in Cyberpunk Fiction’, Women and
Language, 20:1, 1997, pp. 71-76, p. 72.
38
Lauraine Leblanc, ‘Razor Girls’, p. 73.
39
William Gibson, Neuromancer, Ace Books, 1984, p. 138.
182
rationality and feminised meat.’ 40 Whilst this may or may not be true of other
of Molly and Case this way requires a very liberal interpretation indeed. Case,
with his hacker skills and casual contempt for the ‘meat,’ is very much a
himself in the abstractly rational world of cyberspace. Molly, on the other hand,
is all body – her skills pertain purely to the physical world. Harper is too subtle
to fall into such a trap, arguing for a distinction between Haraway’s vision and
many authors other than Gibson. This is most appropriate, as cyberpunk, and
William Gibson. For Harper, novels such as Pat Cadigan’s Synners, Misha’s Red
Spider White Web and Laura Mixon’s Glass Houses typify feminist cyberpunk.
the cyberpunk imaginary, but infuse their narratives with feminist values. In
40
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, pp. 399-400.
41
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 405.
183
example, Harper discusses Gina from Cadigan’s Synners, stating that, ‘Gina is a
hybrid, existing as both Subject and Object, perhaps as both in each of her two
worlds, the virtual and the biologic. Thus she exhibits both similarity to and
Enlightenment model of the rational subject, where being a Subject and rational
singular and unchanging unity, feminist cyberpunk transmits ‘the knowledge that
strategies.’ 43 The cyborg is an excellent vehicle for such a message, since among
its strategies of subjectivity is the power to alter its physical self, the physical self
feminist criticism of the sub-genre. Karen Cadora also distinguishes between the
become the metaphor of choice for such a movement is both strange and
42
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 413.
43
Mary Catherine Harper, ‘Incurably Alien Other’, p. 417.
184
uncontested, and that Haraway’s model of the cyborg is simply one of the
interpretations contesting the figure of the cyborg, Cadora’s comment still stands.
The cyborgs of early, masculinist cyberpunk do sit very much at odds with the
Pat Cadigan and later, overtly feminist cyberpunk authors are, however, another
feminist cyberpunk inherits from its sexist predecessor the potential for the
texts such as Glass Houses and Mary Rosenblum’s Chimera, argues Cadora,
boundary – that between the real and the unreal. 46 Cadora’s interest in this
blurring of the line between reality and unreality is not so much in the blurring
itself, but rather in its result, leading her to claim that ‘The blurring between real
and unreal has profound implications for notions of identity. Stable, coherent
which to ground them.’ 47 While it could be said that the key feature of the ‘real’
world, as opposed to the virtual world, is that it remains real without our consent,
and consequently that virtual reality actually constitutes the first-ever form of
44
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, pp. 359-360.
45
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 366.
46
This thesis has examined the inherent terminological problems facing those trying to describe
cyberspatial experience and/or cyberspatial forms of being, particularly in the context of the
cyberpunk imaginary, in Chapter Four, ‘Cyberpunk Spatiality: The ‘Other’ Spaces of
Cyberpunk.’
47
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 368.
185
are ‘just the kind of identities with which feminism must come to terms…
multiply-positioned subject, might look like. More than that, they show how
cyborg subjects are at the core of feminist cyberpunk – and their ability to
function within the imagined worlds of cyberpunk, argues Cadora, presents new
Its main purpose is to remind purveyors of both radical transcendence and radical
48
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 368.
49
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 370.
186
examination of embodiment are obvious. Indeed, Balsamo has argued that ‘By
reasserting a material body, the cyborg rebukes the disappearance of the body
historically material body by taking account of the ways in which the body is
cyborg challenges feminism to search for ways to study the body as it is at once
both a cultural construction and a material fact of human life.’ 51 While this could
that the cyborgs of cyberpunk are not immune to disembodying rhetoric. In fact,
according to some critics at least, some cyberpunk fictions actually affirm ideas
of disembodiment.
50
Anne Balsamo, Technologies of the Gendered Body, Duke University Press, Durham, 1996, p.
31. For a similar argument, see N. Katherine Hayles, ‘The Posthuman Body: Inscription and
Incorporation in Galatea 2.2 and Snow Crash’, Configurations, 5:2, 1997, pp. 241-266, p. 245.
51
Anne Balsamo, Technologies of the Gendered Body, p. 33.
187
a holistic view of the embodied mind, or a view which proposes that mind and
body can be (or should be) separated digitally, by the translation of a person into
a cyberspatial consciousness. This thesis has elsewhere defended even the most
Cartesian dualism, 52 but that, one suspects, is not crucial to the feminist case
which many cyberpunk characters reside. However, there are also those critics
cyberpunk. As was the case with the figure of the cyborg, cyberpunk uses of
interpretation of a given critic depends not just on his or her own critical
52
See Chapter Four – Cyberpunk Spatiality: The ‘Other’ Spaces of Cyberpunk.
188
reinstated sexism.
William Gibson’s first, ‘Sprawl,’ trilogy and particularly Neuromancer which are
selected as the primary target. Karen Cadora, for example, states that ‘For
women, the realities of the flesh are all too present in the imperfect world of
deconstructionism which Balsamo touched on, Cathy Peppers has stated that:
53
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 364.
54
Cathy Peppers, ‘‘I’ve Got You Under My Skin’’, p. 169.
55
Roger Luckhurst observes that, ‘Although there are signs of more ambivalence about the body
in Neuromancer than is generally credited, Gibson works unquestioningly with a Cartesian
dualism of mind and body.’ Roger Luckhurst, Science Fiction, Polity Press, Cambridge, 2005, p.
208. This thesis finds reason to question the generally held view that Gibson specifically, and
189
Inside this paradigm, Vint explains, ‘The transcendence of the pure mind is
available to the male subject, while the female subject must remain immanent,
absorbing all the limits of materiality that man has cast off in his construction of
seem to be the very image of this paradigm – Case, the male hacker who had
‘lived for the bodiless exaltation of cyberspace,’ 57 and Molly, the warrior and
assassin who, as far as we know from the novel, does not even have access to
that realm.
that the scene in the novel where Case is offered a cyberspatial existence with his
dead girlfriend, Linda Lee, and refuses it, means that Case ‘still insists on a
reality based in bodily existence. His love for and connection with Linda cannot
which sees from nowhere, it would also seem that this passage refutes that claim.
Not only does Case have a cyberspatial body, a location from which he views
cyberspace (at least sometimes) but he is capable of being trapped in it. It is also
apparent that he has at least as much distaste for this condition as for the state of
cyberpunk more generally, hold to a Cartesian model of consciousness. See Chapter Four
‘Cyberpunk Spatiality: The ‘Other’ Spaces of Cyberpunk.’
56
Sherryl Vint, Bodies of Tomorrow, p. 104.
57
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 6.
58
Sherryl Vint, Bodies of Tomorrow, p. 108.
190
being trapped in the ‘prison of his own flesh.’ 59 There are also other passages in
location which denies the ‘disembodied view from nowhere,’ not least the final
hack of the novel, where, engaging the Kuang program, Case ‘had the strange
impression of being in the pilot’s seat in a small plane.’ 60 Gibson is too subtle a
writer to produce a text which simply advocates doing away with the body. His
attitude towards disembodiment in Neuromancer and his other, later, works is far
One might also add that Case’s desire for escape from embodiment in
Neuromancer might have at least one other source: namely, a desire to escape
from the actual oppression in which that physical body finds itself. Heather J.
Hicks has made a similar observation with regards to James Tiptree Jr’s The Girl
Who Was Plugged In, commenting that, ‘In Tiptree’s vision, human subjectivity
is sufficiently contingent upon the social status of the subject’s body that those
who have suffered the ordeal of the “worthless” body willingly flee to a more
validated one. Disembodiment, then, is not about the body ceasing to “matter” –
59
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 6.
60
William Gibson, Neuromancer, p. 256.
61
Sherryl Vint, Bodies of Tomorrow, p. 109.
191
many of the heroes and heroines of cyberpunk fiction, and even some of its
villains (Virek in Gibson’s Count Zero for example), this is definitely the case.
Returning to a point which was raised but not discussed in depth earlier,
neither stable nor unitary, but rather fluid, fractured and determined. The
opposite view – that human subjects are unitary, stable, and autonomous – has
been attributed to humanist arrogance, often using the rather ugly fused term
arguing that it does portray such characters, and more negative criticism arguing
of the subject within its texts. Veronica Hollinger alludes to, but does not
62
Heather J. Hicks, ‘“Whatever it is That She’s Since Become”: Writing Bodies of Text and
Bodies of Women in James Tiptree, Jr.’s The Girl Who Was Plugged In and William Gibson’s
“The Winter Market”’, Contemporary Literature, 37:1, 1996, pp. 62-93, p. 71.
63
This thesis has elsewhere argued, in Chapter Two: “Posthumanism With a Vengeance”:
Cyberpunk and Posthumanist Literary Criticism, that the resources available to a humanist
thinker are not reducible to a liberal or libertarian paradigm, and as such those who reduce
humanism in this way are making critical argumentative mistakes.
192
directly discuss, such fragmentation, when she refers to the ‘radical decent[ring]
cyberpunk with the postmodern deconstruction of the unitary self, claiming that
‘For the most part, fragmentation and dispersal of the self occurs in
material medium (the printed book), or between these levels, rather than at the
In other words, for McHale, cyberpunk realises at the fictional level of character
and narrative the disintegration of the unitary self which postmodernist writing
this claim, and posit the reverse. Nicola Nixon, for example, in ‘Cyberpunk:
Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys Satisfied?’, points out
that cyberpunk novels depict the ‘exceptionally talented, very masculine hero…
64
Veronica Hollinger, ‘Cybernetic Deconstructions’, p. 29.
65
Brian McHale, Constructing Postmodernism, Routledge, New York, 1992, p. 254.
66
Brian McHale, Constructing Postmodernism, p. 255.
193
feminised… Japanese “family” corporations.’ 67 Nixon also points out that ‘It
seems telling that the icon of the cowboy, realised so strongly in Reaganite
contest the idea that cyberpunk depicts or supports the idea of fractured
subjectivities, it is fairly clear from her argument that she considers that it in fact
Unlike Nixon, however, Stockton examines both Kathy Acker and Pat Cadigan
as feminist reworkings of cyberpunk generic writing, noting that ‘As is not the
into question the status of the matrix apparently available for inscription in the
67
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, p. 225.
68
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, pp. 224-225.
69
Sharon Stockton, ‘“The Self Regained”’, p. 588.
70
Sharon Stockton, ‘“The Self Regained”’, p. 603.
194
fiction of authors like Gibson and Stephenson, and… she makes explicit the
Later feminist critics writing about cyberpunk have begun to associate the
Karen Cadora, for example, in identifying the fiction of Mary Rosenblum and Pat
point out that ‘this novel [Chimera] gives that construction of identity a moral
imperative. All the ‘good guys’ – David, Jewel, Flander, Susana, Serafina – are
patchwork people… The ‘bad guy’ in this novel, Harmon Alcourt, is the one who
the novel, the heroine, Allie, ‘comes to realise that she must “Choose: a whole
self, or just an accumulation of elements that soon wouldn’t be more than the
sum of their parts. Madness. Fragmentation.” Allie chooses the state of existence
71
Sharon Stockton, ‘“The Self Regained”’, p. 605.
72
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 368.
73
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 368.
74
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 369.
195
differ from the completely unitary subject which is (apparently) the focus of
humanist thought. However, particularly in the case of Cadigan, one cannot help
but wonder whether the point was rather that each individual subject is a union
cyberpunk that:
seems to be making the point that not only can such deconstructionist activities
that,
75
Cathy Peppers, ‘‘I’ve Got You Under My Skin’’, p. 169.
196
and feminist cyberpunk, Peppers concludes that ‘what is at stake for women in
the deconstruction of the subject is more than a mere philosophical play with
boundaries; what is at stake are the very terms under which we know our bodies.
The women writers of cyberpunk show why we should not be in a hurry to leave
those bodies behind.’ 77 The points made by Cadora, Peppers and others are valid
which people’s physical being determines them. This blindness in turn allows a
points out, in response to the wilful ignorance of the body common to much
originates in, and must return to, the physical. No refigured virtual body, no
matter how beautiful, will slow the death of a cyberpunk with AIDS. Even in the
cyberpunk authors perhaps have the same task within the genre as do feminist
76
Cathy Peppers, ‘‘I’ve Got You Under My Skin’’, p. 175.
77
Cathy Peppers, ‘‘I’ve Got You Under My Skin’’, p. 182.
78
Alluquere Rosanne Stone, ‘Will the Real Body Please Stand Up? Boundary Stories About
Virtual Cultures’, in Jenny Wolmark (ed.), Cybersexualities: A Reader on Feminist Theory,
Cyborgs and Cyberspace, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, 1999, pp. 69-98, p. 94.
197
that it may neither be an easy nor a good thing to attempt to do away with, or
even to ignore, the body. This has, in fact, already occurred. One could argue that
Visual Mark, from Pat Cadigan’s Synners, in many ways parallel the various
console cowboys of Gibson’s Sprawl trilogy. He has the same fervent contempt
for his own physical being, and is similarly obsessed with spending as much time
from that of Bobby Newmark, whom he most closely resembles. Where Bobby
seems to be offered the free ride, his consciousness and character remaining
data self, and finally a merger with the AI Art Fish. Leaving the meat, for Mark,
is an apocalyptic experience which endangers both himself and the rest of the
world, and does not result in something which is merely a digital copy of the old,
physical Mark. One suspects that Cadigan deliberately emphasised the danger
inherent in the process to highlight that bodies matter. Kaye Mitchell makes
‘The hotsuit suggests the irreducibility of the body, which becomes here a
Rather than being left behind, the body is the point of transfer and contact
through the body, and the senses, that AR is experienced by the user.’ 79
79
Kaye Mitchell, ‘Bodies that Matter: Science Fiction, Technoculture and the Gendered Body’,
Science Fiction Studies, 33:1, 2006, pp. 109-128, p. 121.
198
early article, Nicola Nixon, amongst her many other valid criticisms of genre
cyberpunk, made the point that ‘The computer matrix, a construct culturally
associated with the masculine world of logic and scientific wizardry, could easily
constitute the space of the homoerotic. But it doesn’t… the matrix itself is
that ‘their very masculinity is constituted by their success both within and against
hero succeeding in a difficult quest, and proving his mastery over both world and
and, ultimately, conquerable. Sharon Stockton both agrees with and expands
with any accuracy, but she does argue that simply to examine the gendered
examining the other theme is to miss a critical point. This point is that the
cyberpunk fiction. The protagonist hackers “project” into a feminised field; the
80
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, p. 222.
81
Nicola Nixon, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the Boys
Satisfied?’, p. 228.
199
plot complication consists in the revolt of this terrain which should be passive.’82
welcome and apposite; and the analysis which results from it is complex and
rewarding.
There are, however, feminist critics who disagree with the stance taken
by Nixon and Stockton. Karen Cadora, for example, agrees that cyberspace as it
argues that this does not complete the story of cyberpunk’s cyberspaces. In
keeping with the division she draws between masculinist and feminist
an androgynous space or is in fact associated with the male body. Cadora argues
that masculinist cyberpunk is a ‘genre which lacks female characters’ and that in
such a genre ‘it is necessary to construct a feminine space in which male heroes
observes that, in Cadigan’s Synners, both gender identity and sexuality are more
fluid than in, for example, Gibson’s work. Referring to Visual Mark’s fluid
gender identity following his digital translation, his relationship with the AI Art
Fish, and the androgynous nature of the AI itself, Cadora comments that in
82
Sharon Stockton, ‘‘The Self Regained’’, p. 591.
83
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 361.
84
Karen Cadora, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, p. 362.
200
When this chapter is read as a part of the whole of this dissertation, the
There are almost no paths which cyberpunk criticism has taken where feminist
critics have not brought significant new and important ideas to the field.
Foremost amongst these, of course, has been the feminist idea of the cyborg,
inevitably raises; and feminist criticism, due to its ongoing concern with the
body, and its varying fates in postmodern theory, capitalism and, of course, in
cyberpunk literature, has provided both the base from which many of these
discussions have built and the structure of these discourses as they have
progressed. It is also apparent that feminist critics have very rarely absorbed
criticism has often projected useful questions into the field of cyberpunk
criticism - a field which at times seems absorbed with the positive potentials of
a whole is difficult to assess - however, it would not be stretching the point too
201
far to say that there is no avenue of inquiry into cyberpunk which has not been in
historical context, and examine the issue of historicity in both the fiction
historians when they use the word historicity. This chapter follows
time passing, the ability of a society to place its events in historical time,
cyberpunk fictions and the generic critical literature will be read in the
temperament. All of these theories, in their own way, express the feeling
Yamazaki muses, ‘We are come not only past the century’s closing… the
that these sentiments situate both the theories referred to above and
Gibson as saying that ‘science fiction is always, really, about the period it
is written in.’ 3 This chapter aims to prove that this is equally true of
about the nature of cyberpunk and its critique. This chapter differs
more direct criticism of the cyberpunk source material, and less meta-
discussion means that this chapter often has to fill in the interpretive
blanks.
The first of these theories is overtly about history, and will be easily
1
Bruce Sterling, ‘Preface’, in William Gibson, Burning Chrome, Voyager, London,
1995 (first published 1986), pp. 9-13, p. 12.
2
Virtual Light, William Gibson, Bantam, 1993, p. 105. Emphasis in original text.
3
Neil Easterbrook, ‘Alternate Presents: The Ambivalent Historicism of Pattern
Recognition’, Science Fiction Studies, 33:3, 2006, pp. 483-504, p. 485.
204
ensured that debates about the ‘End of History’ would continue for some
time. This chapter will make the claim that there are strong affinities
4
Fukuyama’s original thesis can be found in The National Interest Special Reprint,
‘The End of History?’, pp. 1-16, National Affairs, Inc, Washington D.C., 1989. His
considerable expansion of his original thesis takes the form of a book, The End of
History and the Last Man, Hamish Hamilton, London, 1992.
5
For Jameson’s explication of the disappearance of history in postmodern culture, see
Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism: Or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Duke
University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 283-287.
6
Note that interpreting science fiction as a late modernist phenomenon is my own
adaptation of Jameson’s ideas. Jameson generally characterises science fiction as
postmodern; I struggle to understand ‘Golden Age’ science fiction under any
philosophical paradigm but that of the Enlightenment. Hence my decision to
characterise this science fiction as modernist.
205
historicity passes entirely. This may not necessarily be the case. It may be
7
This, to my mind, is one of the key observations of Postmodernism: Or the Cultural
Logic of Late Capitalism. If it is indeed true that, under the sign of postmodernity,
people perceive both time and history in a fundamentally different manner, then this is a
truly great intellectual upheaval – one which must be accounted for and examined.
206
context. Whilst this is not necessarily always the case, and cyberpunk
does display some ambivalence regarding the role of both history and
provides an ideal critical tool for both the analysis of cyberpunk and,
The last theorist from the 1980s whose work will be used to
relevance to history and historical theory, this chapter will contend that
Lyotard taps a strong vein of criticism, and that his arguments are, at
for example, the doing of science can no longer justify itself in terms of
the pursuit of “Truth.” Lyotard extends his theory to include other, and
this argument is not the purpose of the chapter. Instead, as with Jameson
and Fukuyama, Lyotard’s theories will be used to judge the ‘spirit of the
times,’ for want of a better phrase. The chapter will examine cyberpunk
for evidence of the vanishing of grand narratives (in so far as one can
the be-all and end-all; it is the alpha and the omega; it is cause, purpose
another issue.
book The End of History and the Last Man was intense. Criticism flew
from both the academic Left and Right – the Left often accusing
seeing a victory where none had, as yet, been won. 8 There were, of
8
There is a good edited collection of responses to Fukuyama’s thesis, which also
includes his reply to those critiques. See Timothy Burns (ed.), After History: Francis
Fukuyama and His Critics, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, 1994. Saul Friedlander
made an interesting argument that the very nature of modern consciousness may
preclude an ‘end of history’. See Saul Friedlander, ‘The End of Innovation?
Contemporary Historical Consciousness and the “End of History”’, SubStance, 19:2/3,
pp. 29-36. For an example of scholarly cautions about triumphalism, see Jerry W.
Sanders, ‘Retreat from World Order: The Perils of Triumphalism’, World Policy
Journal, 8:2, 1991, pp. 227-250.
9
See, for example, Francis Fukuyama, ‘Reflections on the End of History: Five Years
Later’, History and Theory, 34:3, 1995, pp. 27-43, p. 31.
209
century. His claim is, essentially, that in the battle of ideologies which
and liberal democracy. This is a most serious claim, and one that, in the
at best.
also be said that any thesis which claims that the ‘End of History’ has
happened is never likely to lack for detractors (not least from the ranks of
point must be made that one could devote an entire thesis simply to this
10
Francis Fukuyama, ‘The End of History?’, The National Interest Special Reprint,
National Affairs, Inc, Washington D.C., 1989, pp 48-55, p. 1-2.
210
which is particularly germane to this thesis – their points bear the most
relevance not only to Fukuyama’s ideas but interlock best with the
and other less developed parts of the world. Fukuyama maintains that
such conflicts are not important – that they are a sort of historical
hangover and will not effect the closure of history in any way. Callinicos
makes the point that not only is maintaining that such conflicts are
too close to home to dismiss in such a way. As Callinicos himself puts it:
doesn’t deny that conflict is likely to persist in the “New World Order,”
extraordinary article written after the end of the Gulf War.’ 11 Callinicos’
11
Alex Callinicos, ‘Liberalism, Marxism and Democracy: A Response to David Held’,
Theory and Society, 22:2, 1993, pp. 283-288, p. 283. Fukuyama’s original claim was
that ‘Clearly, much of the Third World remains very much mired in history… But let us
focus on the larger and more developed states of the world, who after all account for the
greater part of world politics.’ Francis Fukuyama, ‘The End of History?’, p. 13.
211
growing pains of the rest of the world. This, in turn, is likely to instigate
changes in the economic and political forms of the West – the supposedly
claim that the systems he identifies as finishing history actually solve all
argues that they have exhausted all systemic competition. This means
that pointing out the problems in the liberal/capitalist system does not
it: ‘Quite expressly his [Fukuyama’s] schema did not require the
the ne plus ultra of political and economic life on earth. The end of
history is not the arrival of a perfect system, but the elimination of any
12
Perry Anderson, ‘The Ends of History’, in Perry Anderson, A Zone of Engagement,
Verso, London, 1992, pp. 279-375, p. 336.
212
misrepresent their structure in the search for a hiding place from the
through the attempt to define capitalism out of existence (by arguing that,
difficult to find forces capable of altering the world, why not change the
contains these analyses, Anderson also deals with a few other major
important.
core, about the failure of socialism in the battle between socialism and
reduced to the end of socialism. As Anderson puts it: ‘If the end of
13
Perry Anderson, ‘The Ends of History’, pp. 240-241.
213
indeed, from the sense that we are witnessing across what was once the
Soviet bloc a gigantic historical upheaval that for the first time in history
seems to bear no new principle within it, but rather to move as in a vast
dream where events are already familiar before they happen.’ 14 For if
history. Anderson points out that the popular view in many circles
finds that there may be life in the Marxist corpse yet. The challenge (and
return when examining the relationship between cyberpunk and the ‘End
of History.’
place the present within historical time, has become blocked. Historicity
10
Perry Anderson, ‘The Ends of History’, pp. 351-352.
214
that History (Fukuyama later uses a deliberate capital ‘H’) 15 has come to
a close; Jameson is not speaking of the historical process itself, but rather
the early nineteenth century. In doing so, he relates the downfall of the
historical novel, claiming that ‘the historical novel… has fallen into
we can no longer tell ourselves our history in that fashion, but because
15
He does this in order to distinguish between history seen as a series of events, and his
Hegelian definition of History as the clash of ideas. See Francis Fukuyama, The End of
History and the Last Man, p. xii.
16
Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism: Or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Duke
University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 283-284.
215
back door.
17
Fredric Jameson Postmodernism: Or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, pp. 285-
286.
18
Anders Stephanson and Fredric Jameson, ‘Regarding Postmodernism – A
Conversation with Fredric Jameson’, Social Text, 21, 1989, pp. 3-30, p. 18.
216
notes that:
19
Anders Stephanson and Fredric Jameson, ‘Regarding Postmodernism’, p. 30.
Emphasis in original text.
217
it, is one to which this chapter’s commentary linking Jameson’s work and
this chapter, Jean-François Lyotard, and his theories, remain a critical part
themselves no longer have the legitimation power they once had. In the
20
Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism: Or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Duke
University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 217-219.
21
Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, Trans.
Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis,
1984, p. xxiv.
218
as an end in itself. This ‘false’ legitimation story has led to the corruption
Lyotard’s work (as with the Fukuyama debates, one could write a tome of
with Lyotard’s thesis should be pointed out. Firstly, whilst decrying the
seem to lead one to a slightly different conclusion than the one which
Lyotard describes: namely, that rather than drawing from the fact that
power the conclusion that all meta-narratives must lack such power, we
previous age will at the very least need to be revised to remain relevant in
this one. Secondly, and Lyotard’s theory has much in common with
22
Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, pp. 45-46.
23
See, for example, Andreas Michel, ‘Differentiation vs. Disenchantment: The
Persistence of Modernity from Max Weber to Jean-François Lyotard’, German Studies
Review, 20:3, 1997, pp. 343-370, p. 343.
219
not often), Fredric Jameson’s name is usually not far behind. This
cyberpunk fictions. There are a few critics who devote whole articles to
this somewhat sparse body of criticism, the following analysis will also
historically. 24
varies, of course, from author to author, but also within the oeuvre of the
24
For observations about post-historical time and Gibson’s later work, Pattern
Recognition, see Veronica Hollinger, ‘Stories about the Future: From Patterns of
Expectation to Pattern Recognition’, Science Fiction Studies, 33:3, 2006, pp. 452-472,
pp. 462-463.
220
than a century old, Deane is in this way himself a kind of historical object.
Screaming Fist commando raid into Russia, he asks Deane for the
information. Deane’s response includes the line ‘Don’t they teach you
from the old to the young since time immemorial, but it could be argued
itself is, like Deane, a semi-comical relic; something which ultimately has
25
William Gibson, Neuromancer, Ace Books, New York, 1984, p. 35.
221
Deane’s seamless pink face regarded Case from a pool of light cast
by an ancient brass lamp with a rectangular shade of dark green
glass. The importer was securely fenced behind a vast desk of
painted steel, flanked on either side by tall, drawered cabinets
made of some sort of pale wood… The desktop was littered with
cassettes, scrolls of some yellowed printout, and various parts of
some sort of clockwork typewriter, a machine Deane never seemed
to get around to reassembling. 26
that they are precisely the sort of postmodern past(iche) which Jameson
identifies in Postmodernism. That is, they are things from the past which
abolished. In short, objects fall into the world and become decoration
26
William Gibson, Neuromancer, pp. 12-13.
27
Anders Stephanson and Fredric Jameson, ‘Regarding Postmodernism’, p. 4. My
emphasis.
222
Claire Sponsler, too, has observed that, ‘Tellingly, many of these objects
section) concludes that the historicity of Gibson’s early texts (or the lack
any real connection to history itself. The question and response are as
follows:
28
John R. R. Christie, ‘Science Fiction and the Postmodern: The Recent Fiction of
William Gibson and John Crowley’, in T. Shippey (ed.) Fictional Space: Essays on
Contemporary Science Fiction, Oxford, Humanities Press, 1991, pp. 34-58, p. 47.
29
Claire Sponsler, ‘Cyberpunk and the Dilemmas of Postmodern Narrative: The
Example of William Gibson’, Contemporary Literature, 33:4, 1992, pp. 625-644, p.
630.
223
FJ: When I talked about the loss of history, I didn’t mean the
disappearance of images of history, for instance, in the case of
nostalgia film. The increasing number of films about the past are
no longer historical; they are images, simulacra and pastiches of
the past. They are effectively a way of satisfying a chemical craving
for historicity, using a product that substitutes for and blocks it.30
Sprawl trilogy. They exist as a sort of cover for the fact that the books
the past and the present?’31 Novak argues that the postmodern pastiche
30
Anders Stephanson and Fredric Jameson, ‘Regarding Postmodernism’, p. 18.
31
Amy Novak, ‘Virtual Poltergeists and Memory: The Question of Ahistoricism in
William Gibson’s Neuromancer’, Hungarian Journal of English and American Studies,
6:1, 2000, pp. 55-78, p. 59.
224
particular, Novak’s analysis supports the idea that, contra Jameson, there
The events and people of history may be remembered, but in a very real
past to us, because we no longer possess the tools with which to interpret
them.
Whilst the remainder of the Sprawl trilogy (Count Zero and Mona
32
Amy Novak, ‘Virtual Poltergeists and Memory’, p. 74.
225
towards history can be seen. This concurs with the impression given by
the critical literature about Gibson’s work that his writing moved away
contexts intact; they still have historical meaning. In the last work of the
kind of historical thinking posits that history not only has a pattern but
that it may be possible for us to discern it; that there is a master story
through which all history can be understood; that there is not just a
undeniable; that Laney is not fully sane is, by this point in the novel, also
a sad truth. The most important part about this, for the purposes of the
such a meta-narrative for history, but that historical thinking enters his
text.
example:
34
William Gibson, All Tomorrow’s Parties, Berkley, New York, 2003 (first published
1999), pp. 198-199.
227
Sometimes she’d thought he’d done that to get the old man
started, and then Skinner’s own stories would come out. He
hadn’t been much for stories, Skinner, but turning some
battered treasure of Fontaine’s in his hands, he’d talk, and
Fontaine would sit and listen, and nod sometimes, as
though Skinner’s stories confirmed some long-held
suspicion.
bearers of context, as the containers for the stories that make up history,
history also differs strongly from Laney’s. Once again, the difference
Parties, however, Gibson has changed enough that not only does
historicity play a central role in his text, but he also uses the pages of his
35
William Gibson, All Tomorrow’s Parties, pp. 190-191.
228
ambivalence, for Laney thinks that he is surpassing the “old history” that
history at all, from the history of ordinary lives to the most abstract
political and diplomatic histories, the common thread must be the ability
to place these events, large and small, into a broader historical context. In
on this change in tone from the Sprawl trilogy to the Bridge sequence. In
36
Neil Easterbrook, ‘Alternate Presents: The Ambivalent Historicism of Pattern
Recognition’, Science Fiction Studies, 33:3, 2006, pp. 483-504, pp. 494-495. Note that
Easterbrook’s usage of the term historicist and the associated concept of historicity are a
little different to the way in which they are used by Jameson and in this chapter.
229
historical artefacts in the Bridge trilogy. As Thrall puts it: ‘What has
seem, wants to suggest that his readers, too, should “like the sound of”
such an interplay between change and the concrete, with some emphasis
characters exist and the historicity in which the Bridge and its
community are encased. Thrall states that, through the figure of the
37
James H. Thrall, ‘Love, Loss and Utopian Community on William Gibson’s Bridge’,
Foundation, 91:3, 2004, pp. 97-115, p. 104.
38
James H. Thrall, ‘Love, Loss and Utopian Community on William Gibson’s Bridge’,
p. 104.
39
James H. Thrall, ‘Love, Loss and Utopian Community on William Gibson’s Bridge’,
pp. 105-106.
230
(which continues into his most recent novels, which only the bravest
‘Why did you decide to set this novel in the present, unlike your previous
futures. Science fiction is always, really, about the period it is written in,
though most people don’t seem to understand that.’ 40 One has to wonder
40
Neil Easterbrook, ‘Alternate Presents’, p. 485.
41
Veronica Hollinger has, in her usual perceptive manner, also observed this, stating
that ‘Gibson’s move from near-future sf in novels from Neuromancer to All
Tomorrow’s Parties to the present-tense “sf realism” of Pattern Recognition seems
inevitable – at least in the hindsight of pattern recognition. The novel freezes in the face
of the sheer impossibility of extrapolation, the sheer opacity of the future.’ Veronica
Hollinger, ‘Stories about the Future: From Patterns of Expectation to Pattern
Recognition’, Science Fiction Studies, 33:3, 2006, pp. 452-472, pp. 462-463.
231
Historicity (or the lack thereof) also plays a part in the work of
follow the pattern of other early cyberpunk when it comes to the sense of
frankly inaccessible, for characters in her novels. They exist in the kind
the past, or to think historically, doesn’t matter. The ability to frame the
and Asherah. While the events of Snow Crash appear to take place in the
are also the setting for Gibson’s cyberpunk world, the difference in
Stephenson’s case is that this does not seem to necessitate them also
ideas that began in the past and continues into the future. Most notably,
this involves his development of the understanding that the snow crash
In this way the past (in the form of Sumerian myth) is brought back into
the present and its relevance restated. This, it could be said, is the heart
of historicity.
the reader acutely aware that the present is always a moment which was
shaped by moments past; even if our ability to sense such a thing fails, it
is, in fact, always true. In particular, the story of Hiro’s father and that of
their sons. The stories told by the two men of their fathers serve to
remind the reader of the links between the past and the present. Raven’s
story, of his own life and his father’s life before him, is used in the plot
the United States of America (even though it can barely be said to exist
anymore). As Raven puts it late in the novel, ‘My father got nuked twice
233
are murky – an unknown, for the text places no value on such things.
These reminders of the flow between the past and the present also
fiction and the role-playing game Cyberpunk. The first is a natural choice,
Schismatrix, hailed as his most posthumanist text, seems to be, when the
42
Neal Stephenson, Snow Crash, Bantam, 2008 (reissue), first published 1992, p. 448.
43
Neal Stephenson, Snow Crash, p. 61.
44
Istvan Csisery-Ronay, Jr., ‘Review: Postmodern Technoculture, or the Gordian Knot
Revisited’, Science Fiction Studies, 19:3, 1992, pp. 403-411, p. 408.
234
sense of history is one of the defining marks of the postmodern (as per
For one thing, the novel displays both internal and external
events both within the logic of its own train of events and it is able to
place them within the history of the human race as a whole. Despite
occasionally viewing the past as dead (and the humans and posthumans of
its worlds as better off for that) Schismatrix never displays the inability to
45
Bruce Sterling, ‘Schismatrix’, in Bruce Sterling, Schismatrix Plus, Berkeley, New
York, 1996, pp. 1-236, p. 20.
235
historicity; however, the fact that Sterling locates the strange desire for
says of Gibson, ‘His work does not accept the values of the black, closed
world he evokes with such skill: he hates the status quo. But his
balancing act accepts the status quo a bit too readily as inevitable and
46
Bruce Sterling, ‘Schismatrix’, p. 103.
236
historicity out with the bathwater of the idea of progress. Returning from
itself necessitates the novel’s historical thinking; for one cannot imagine
Earth (long since a forbidden zone to those who live in the Outer Solar
(And later)
47
Darko Suvin, ‘On Gibson and Cyberpunk SF’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.) Storming the
Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 249-365, p. 357.
237
a failed branch of the tree of (post)humanity. Whilst one can doubt the
mind that we come to the next of the theorists this chapter wishes to
this chapter; the idea that history has come to an end, even if that end is a
argues in both his original article and the book The End of History and
the Last Man that, with the conclusion of the ideological conflict
the collapse of the Soviet Union, liberal democracy and capitalism have
48
Bruce Sterling, ‘Schismatrix’, pp. 222-226.
238
imagines for the future after the end of history. What is really of interest,
any other future economic system. 50 They certainly hold this cognitive
other words, liberal democracy and capitalism not only can coexist but to
hand, abounds with the presence of capital, but very rarely mentions the
the past, done away with by the forces of capital. This thesis contends
49
See, for example, Francis Fukuyama, ‘The End of History?’, p. 12.
50
Richard K. Morgan’s Takeshi Kovacs novels may be an exception, but Morgan is a
relatively recent addition to the cyberpunk spectrum – one might even be tempted to
term him ‘post-cyberpunk’ were the term not so thoroughly ugly.
239
that, in the context of the deregulation politics of the 1980s (Reagan and
Thatcher in the USA and the UK, respectively, whilst here in Australia
for business, the theory went – and in cyberpunk, this seems to have been
extended to its logical extreme: regulators are bad for business. It could
be argued, and it seems Gibson takes this tack, that the only way to have
a truly free market is to get rid of all the institutions which might stand in
one accepts that this is a good thing or not is not necessarily the point.
victor. The same is true of the world of Stephenson’s Snow Crash. Most
global governments are referred to in the past tense, with the possible
under the weight of its own hubris – in fact, the Government of the
240
United States of America has been reduced to the ‘largest, and yet the
presently the USA, Snow Crash portrays a world where the only
democracy.
(the cyberpunk end, rather than the Fukuyaman one) then Cadigan differs
overworked that court appears to be, this is clear evidence of the kind of
51
Neal Stephenson, Snow Crash, p. 437.
241
Despite the clear presence of nation-states and their apparati in her texts,
Cadigan (with the possible exception of Synners) seems to hold out little
more hope than Gibson for the future of the nation state – her
this basis that Pat Cadigan’s worlds can be described as worlds on the
other side of the end of history. In Schismatrix, one feels that the author
had the idea that history was over – but didn’t really want that to be the
case. In order to re-start history, therefore, Sterling takes the huge step of
colonisation, expansion and heroism in the tabula rasa of the outer Solar
between Earth and Space) to cut off the moribund body of Earth history.
The combination of these two effects – the removal of the dead heart of
human history and the opening up of a new space in which history can be
historical process over again, in a new sphere. In keeping with the theme
is far from new in the History of science fiction. Novels of this type can
debate) and it is with narratives that the last theorist whose work will be
theory that all the explanatory and legitimatory grand narratives of the
52
See, for analysis of examples of this literature, Mark Bould and Sherryl Vint, The
Routledge Concise History of Science Fiction, Routledge, Abingdon, 2011, pp. 71-73.
Roger Luckhurst observes that interplanetary travel represents ‘the vehicle of
transcendent possibility’ in the work of Arthur C. Clarke. The corollary of this is that
the Earth itself comes to represent stagnation – precisely the situation in Sterling’s
Schismatrix. See Roger Luckhurst, Science Fiction, Polity Press, Cambridge, 2005, pp.
134-135.
243
knowledge for its own ends) enables the corruption of science in the
53
Andreas Michel, ‘Differentiation vs. Disenchantment’, p. 357.
54
See Andreas Michel, ‘Differentiation vs. Disenchantment’, pp. 358-359, for Michel’s
argument and supplementary quotes from Lyotard. For an argument against the
Lyotardian position, and in favour of continuing the processes of modernity and
rationalisation, see Harry F. Dahms, ‘Democracy and the Post-Enlightenment: Lyotard
244
inserted into the fast-paced, high-tech cut and thrust of most novels in the
laughable. The black clinics of Chiba City are the archetype for research
throughout the novel are usually swept away by the massive potential for
profit the new implants entail. This is the model of science in cyberpunk
itself).
and Habermas Reappraised’, International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society, 5:3,
1992, pp. 473-509.
245
profit, which has stepped in to fill the blanks left in scientific research by
the failure of previous legitimation narratives. The results of this are dire.
In our contemporary world, there are many who make the claim that the
market can and will solve all ills – who attribute the same miraculous
power to the invisible hand that Adam Smith did centuries ago. As far as
are simply too slow to keep pace with the changes engendered by
Epistemology and ethics are closed books, and quite possibly buried
are certainly exciting – but one imagines that they would be quite poor
one of the reasons for this. If Lyotard is correct in stating that the meta-
narratives of the Enlightenment have failed (and this thesis questions that
are bleak, indeed. Still, there are significant ways in which Lyotard’s
fictions.
and Lyotard argue that certain things have actually come to an end
Cyberpunk, when placed in its historical context, acts very much like an
Conclusion.
Throughout its length, this thesis has borne witness to the depth and
diversity of cyberpunk criticism. The critical literature which forms the basis of
this intellectual history is neither monolithic nor unitary; instead it speaks with
many voices, from many different perspectives. This is to be expected, given the
cyberpunk. Despite this diversity, however, certain key intellectual threads may
be identified in the overall progress of cyberpunk criticism, and this thesis has
identified and examined those threads. It has related them back to broader
cyberpunk criticism is the way it is. No critical ‘school’ (for want of a better
different to any other in this respect. This dissertation has contended that
recognisable that cyberpunk burst onto the literary field at a time in which post-
sphere. It was also apparent, at the time, that cyberpunk was different to much
248
certainty of Golden Age science fiction. It also lacked the utopian instincts of the
pastoral science fictions of the ‘70s. Here, proclaimed posthumanist critics, was
the dirty new science fiction for the dirty new age of posthumanism. Gone, the
unitary self, the untainted body, and the unchallenged empire of reason.
Welcome in the new sense of fractured being, body modification, and the assault
delved into the critical literature which identified cyberpunk with posthumanism,
and quickly found that, despite surface similarities, cyberpunk is nowhere near as
posthumanist as many critics would have liked. Instead, this chapter concluded
posthuman and its more ‘philosophical’ counterpart. Having noted that this
posthuman (which abounds in cyberpunk fictions) was largely being taken, in the
posthuman. Again drawing upon Hayles’ work as a critical resource, this thesis
suggested that not only was this not necessarily the case, but that the presence of
the cybernetic posthuman might also preclude the presence of the philosophical
posthuman (which has strong links to posthumanist philosophy) and may instead
entail a model of self which even many humanists find troubling. This chapter
concluded that, despite the great critical potential entailed within theories of the
elaborate precisely what the posthuman actually is often makes the resulting
critiques suspect.
examined two kinds of space in cyberpunk which are discussed in some depth in
the critical literature: cyberspace, the critical novum of cyberpunk; and the idea
of interstitial spaces, which William Gibson in particular holds close to his heart.
chapter concluded that almost all of the analysis which has been done on
they maintain a dualist model of the self; with respect, this is demonstrably
work. This chapter made the case that, in Baudrillard’s work as well as those
who deploy his ideas on their criticisms, fundamental mistakes have been made,
not least the deployment of the idea that the virtual (cyberspatial) environment is
in some way ‘unreal’. If the alternative case is put, that cyberspace be treated as a
vein, this chapter examined the intellectual history of interstitial spaces. Despite
the tendency of both cyberpunk fiction and criticism to valorise the interstitial,
this chapter found significant reasons to doubt that the interstitial can play the
It was the contention of the next chapter, ‘Men, Women and Machines:
proved to be the most fruitful terrain of cyberpunk criticism. This was not mere
happenstance; it was due to the fact that feminist critics displayed less of a
engage in debates regarding the status of cyberpunk. One thing which feminist
critics did, and do, much better than critics of any other persuasion is continually
examine and interrogate the role of the body in cyberpunk fictions. Whether it is
through the lens of Donna Haraway’s cyborg theory, or via a more general notion
the contention of this chapter that, primarily through the analysis of the body
perhaps not even have begun, given the import of some early feminist critical
contributions.
In the final, and most historically minded, chapter this thesis examined
questionable, raising them was never intended to propose such direct links. They
critical literature in the light of these theories was thus intended to elucidate a
doing so it has, perforce, been called upon to examine some of the key
intellectual threads of the last twenty-five years. The rise of postmodernism and
a constant theme throughout this thesis; it could even be said that it was the
constant theme. This thesis has often found cause to celebrate the success of
contributions have been made by many academics, and that the vibrant
opinion which is both fascinating and, often, praiseworthy. However, it has also
found that cyberpunk criticism is a discourse which has become bound within
the majority of critics to engage in any real way with the intellectual resources
our understanding of the genre literature. This thesis has not only sought to
observe these lacunae in the critical literature, but where possible it has also
Bibliography.
Ahrens, John, and Miller, Fred D., ‘Beyond The Green Slime: A Philosophical
Prescription for Science Fiction’, Philosophy in Context, 11, 1981 pp. 1-10.
Barr, Marleen S., Alien to Femininity: Speculative Fiction and Feminist Theory,
Greenwood Press, New York, 1987.
Bartlett, Laura and Byers, Thomas B. ‘Back to the Future: The Humanist
Matrix’, Cultural Critique, 53, 2003, pp. 28-46.
Baudrillard, Jean, The Intelligence of Evil: Or the Lucidity Pact, Berg, Oxford,
2005, trans. Chris Turner.
Baudrillard, Jean, The Vital Illusion, ed. Julia Witwer, Columbia University
Press, New York, 2000.
Bukatman, Scott, ‘Postcards From the Posthuman Solar System’, Science Fiction
Studies, 18:3, 1991, pp. 343-357.
Burns, Timothy (ed.), After History: Francis Fukuyama and His Critics,
Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, 1994.
Cadigan, Pat, Synners, Four Wall Eight Windows, New York, 1991.
Cadora, Karen, ‘Feminist Cyberpunk’, Science Fiction Studies, 22:3, 1995, pp.
357-371.
Calvert, Bronwen and Walsh, Sue, ‘Speaking the Body: The Embodiment of
‘Feminist’ Cyberpunk’, in Andy Sawyer, and David Seed (eds.), Speaking
Science Fiction: Dialogues and Interpretations, Liverpool University Press,
Liverpool, 2000, pp. 96-108.
Christie, John R. R., ‘Science Fiction and the Postmodern: The Recent Fiction of
William Gibson and John Crowley’, in Tom Shippey (ed.) Fictional Space:
Essays on Contemporary Science Fiction, Oxford, Humanities Press, 1991, pp.
34-58.
Christie, John, ‘Of AI’s and Others: William Gibson’s Transit’, in Fiction 2000:
Cyberpunk and the Future of Narrative, in George Slusser and Tom Shippey
(eds.), University of Georgia Press, Athens (Georgia), 1992, pp. 171- 182.
256
Clark, Stephen R.L., How to Live Forever: Science Fiction and Philosophy,
Routledge, London, 1995.
Cordasco, Francesco and Galatioto, Rocco G., ‘Ethnic Displacement in the
Interstitial Community: The East Harlem Experience’, Phylon, 31:3, pp. 302-
312.
Descartes, René, Discourse on Method and the Meditations (trans. John Veitch),
Prometheus Books, New York, 1989.
Farrell, John Aloysius ‘The Cyberpunk Controversy’, The Boston Globe Sunday
Magazine, 19 February 1989, (Interview with William Gibson).
Ferry, Luc, and Renaut, Alain, French Philosophy of the Sixties: An Essay on
Antihumanism, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1990.
Fukuyama, Francis, The End of History and the Last Man, Hamish Hamilton,
London, 1992.
Gans, Herbert J., The Urban Villagers: Group and Class in the Life of Italian-
Americans, Macmillan, New York, 1962
Gibson, William, All Tomorrow’s Parties, Berkley Books, 2003 (first published
1999).
Gibson, William, Idoru, Berkley Books, New York, 2003 (first printing 1996).
Gordon, Joan, ‘Yin and Yang Duke it Out’, in Larry McCaffery (ed.), Storming
the Reality Studio, Duke University Press, 1991, pp. 196-202, p. 199.
Harper, Mary Catherine, ‘Incurably Alien Other: A Case for Feminist Cyborg
Writers’, Science Fiction Studies, 22:3, 1995, pp. 399-421.
Irwin, William (ed.), More Matrix and Philosophy: Revolutions and Reloaded
Decoded, Chicago, Open Court, 2005.
Irwin, William (ed.), The Matrix and Philosophy: Welcome to the Desert of the
Real, Chicago, Open Court, 2002.
James, Edward, Science Fiction in the 20th Century, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1994.
Jameson, Fredric, Archaeologies of the Future: The Desire Called Utopia and
Other Science Fictions, Verso, London, 2005.
Kellner, Douglas, Media Culture: Cultural Studies, Identity and Politics Between
the Modern and the Postmodern, Routledge, London, 1995.
Kronick, Joseph G., ‘Writing American: Between Canon and Literature’, The
New Centennial Review, 1:3, 2001, pp. 37-66.
Kurzweil, Ray, The Age of Spiritual Machines: How We Will Live, Work and
Think in the New Age of Intelligent Machines, Orion, London, 1999.
Landon, Brooks, Science Fiction After 1900: From the Steam Man to the Stars,
Routledge, New York, 2002.
Lee, Chia-Yi, ‘Beyond the Body: Kafka’s The Metamorphosis and Gibson’s
Neuromancer’, Concentric: Literary and Cultural Studies, 30:2, 2004, pp. 201-
222.
Lefanu, Sarah, In the Chinks of the World Machine: Feminism and Science
Fiction, The Women’s Press, London, 1988.
Margolin, Victor, ‘The Politics of the Artificial’, Leonardo, 28:5, pp. 349-356.
Marinoff, Lou, ‘The Matrix and Plato’s Cave: Why the Sequels Failed’ in
William Irwin (ed.), More Matrix and Philosophy: Revolutions and Reloaded
Decoded, Chicago, Open Court, 2005.
Marvin, Carolyn, ‘Information and History’, in Jennifer Daryl Slack and Fred
Fejes (eds.), The Ideology of the Information Age, Ablex Publishing Corporation,
Norwood, pp. 49-62.
261
McCarron, Kevin, ‘Corpses, Animals, Machines and Mannequins: The Body and
Cyberpunk’, in Mike Featherstone and Roger Burrows (eds),
Cyberspace/Cyberbodies/Cyberpunk, Sage Publications, London, 1995, pp. 261-
273.
Mitchell, Kaye, ‘Bodies that Matter: Science Fiction, Technoculture and the
Gendered Body’, Science Fiction Studies, 33:1, 2006, pp. 109-128.
Moravec, Hans, Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Mass.), 1988.
Nixon, Nicola, ‘Cyberpunk: Preparing the Ground for Revolution or Keeping the
Boys Satisfied?’, Science Fiction Studies, 19:2, 1992, pp. 219-235.
Oliver, I., ‘The ‘Old’ and the ‘New’ Hermeneutic in Sociological Theory’,
British Journal of Sociology, 1983, 34:4, pp. 519-553.
Pickering, Michael, ‘History as Horizon’, Rethinking History, 1999, 3:2, pp. 177-
195.
Roberts, Adam, The History of Science Fiction, Palgrave Macmillan, New York,
2006.
Rowlands, Mark, The Philosopher at the End of the Universe, Ebury Press,
London, 2004.
263
Russ, Joanna, ‘What Can a Heroine Do, or, Why Women Can’t Write’, in Joanna
Russ, To Write Like a Woman: Essays in Feminism and Science Fiction, Indiana
University Press, Bloomington, 1995, pp. 79-93.
Said, Edward, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, Palgrave, New York, 2004.
Sanders, Jerry W., ‘Retreat from World Order: The Perils of Triumphalism’,
World Policy Journal, 8:2, 1991, pp. 227-250.
Siivonen, Timo, ‘Cyborgs and Generic Oxymorons: The Body and Technology
in William Gibson’s Cyberspace Trilogy’, Science Fiction Studies, 23, 1996, pp.
227-244.
Skinner, Quentin, ‘Hermeneutics and the Role of History’, New Literary History,
7, 1975, pp. 209-232.
Sobchack, Vivian, ‘Beating the Meat/Surviving the Text, or How to Get Out of
this Century Alive’, in Mike Featherstone and Roger Burrows (eds),
Cyberspace/Cyberbodies/Cyberpunk, Sage Publications, London, 1995, pp. 205-
214.
Spanos, William V., ‘Boundary 2 and the Polity of Interest: Humanism, the
“Center Elsewhere” and Power’, boundary 2, 12:3, 1984, pp. 173-214.
Spanos, William V., ‘The Uses and Abuses of Certainty: A Caviling Overture’,
boundary 2, 12:3, 1984, pp. 1-17.
264
Spinrad, Norman, Science Fiction in the Real World, 1990, Southern Illinois
University Press, Carbondale.
Stephenson, Neal, Snow Crash, Bantam, 2008 (reissue), first published 1992.
Stone, Alluquere Rosanne, ‘Will the Real Body Please Stand Up? Boundary
Stories About Virtual Cultures’, in Jenny Wolmark (ed.), Cybersexualities: A
Reader on Feminist Theory, Cyborgs and Cyberspace, Edinburgh University
Press, Edinburgh, 1999, pp. 69-98.
Suvin, Darko ‘On Gibson and Cyberpunk SF’, in Larry McCaffery, (ed.)
Storming the Reality Studio, Duke University Press, Durham, 1991, pp. 249-365.
Thacker, Eugene, ‘Data Made Flesh: Biotechnology and the Discourse of the
Posthuman’, Cultural Critique, 53, pp. 72-97.
Thrall, James H., ‘Love, Loss and Utopian Community on William Gibson’s
Bridge’, Foundation, 91:3, 2004, pp. 97-115.
Toews, John, ‘Intellectual History after the Linguistic Turn: The Autonomy of
Meaning and the Irreducibility of Experience,’ American Historical Review,
92:4, 1987, pp. 879-907.
Vint, Sherryl, ‘“The Mainstream Finds its Own uses for Things”: Cyberpunk and
Commodification’, in Sherryl Vint and Graham J. Murphy (eds.), Beyond
Cyberpunk: New Critical Perspectives, Routledge, New York, 2010, pp. 95-115.
265
White, Hayden, ‘The Context in the Text: Method and Ideology in Intellectual
History’, in Hayden White, The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and
Historical Representation, 1987.
Whyte, William Foote, Street Corner Society: The Social Structure of an Italian
Slum, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1955 (Enlarged Second Edition:
First published 1943).
Yeffeth, Glenn (ed.), Taking the Red Pill: Science, Philosophy and Religion in
The Matrix, Dallas (Texas), Benbella Books, 2003.