Drama coursework
The main difference between a comedy and a tragedy lies in their
perspectives and outcomes. Tragedies focus on human suffering,
isolation, and inevitable downfall, often ending in death and
arousing pity and fear. Comedies, on the other hand, emphasize
humor, character idiosyncrasies, and renewal, leading to happy and
positive conclusions. While tragedies highlight human limitations
and fate, comedies celebrate life's absurdities and potential for
improvement.
Tragedies in general take the philosophical view that life is a
misfortune because it is filled with pain and suffering and always
inevitably ends in Wedeath. Comedies in general take the view that
life is ridiculous because most people behave like fools with
unrealistic pretensions and expectations. Both viewpoints are valid.
Most of us see life as a grim and pointless struggle at some times,
while at other times, when we are in a good mood, we see life as a
game to be played and not as something to be taken seriously.
Laughter vs. Tears
While both comedy and tragedy point to human foibles, the manner
in which these foibles are treated as well as the outcome greatly
differ.
TRAGEDY
Emphasis upon human shortcomings which effect suffering
The hero is often isolated
The hero realizes errors too late
The hero and others die in the end/suffer a great...
Classical tragedy – elements include a tragic hero who is of higher
than ordinary moral worth.
Such a man is exhibited as suffering a change in fortune from
happiness to misery because of a
mistaken act, to which he is led by “an error in judgement” or his
tragic flaw. Most often the
mistaken act ultimately leads to the hero’s death. We feel pity for
the tragic hero because he is
not an evil man, so his misfortune is greater than he deserves.
There is also a sense that the hero
could have been more if not for his tragic flaw. Comic elements may
be present in a classical
tragedy.
Let us begin with tragedy.
The first great theC:rist of dramatic art was Aristotle (384-322 B.C.),
whose discussion of tragedy in Poetics has dominated critical
thought
eversince. A very brief summary of Aristotle's view will be helpful.
A tragedy, so Aristotle wrote, is the imitation in dramatic form of
anaction that is serious and complete, with incidents arousing pity
and
fearwith which it effects a catharsis of such emotions. The language
used is pleasurable and appropriate throughout to the situation. The
chief characters are noble personages ("better than ourselves," says
Aristotle), and the actions th~y perform are noble actions. The plot
involves a change in the protagonist's fortune, in which he usually,
but
not always, falls from happiness to misery. The protagonist, though
not
perfect, is hardly a bad person; his misfortunes result not from
character
deficiencies but rather from what Aristotle calls hamartia, a criminal
act committed in ignorance of some material fact or even for the
sake
ofa greater good. A tragic plot has organic unity: the events follow
not
just after one another but because of one another. The best tragic
plots
involve a reversal (a change from one state of things within the play
to its opposite) or a discovery (a change from ignorance to
knowledge)
or both.
In the more extensive account that follows, we will not attempt
to delineate the boundaries of tragedy or necessarily describe it at
its greatest. Instead, i we will describe a common understanding of
tragedy as a point of departure for further discussion. Nor shall we
enter into the endless controversies over what Aristotle meant by
"catharsis" or over which of his statements are meant to apply to
all tragedies and which only to the best ones. The important thing
is that Aristotle had::important insights into the nature of some of
the greatest tragedies and that, rightly or wrongly interpreted, his
conceptions are the basis for a kind of archetypal notion of tragedy
that has dominated critical thought. What are the central features of
that archetype? (The following summary retains Aristotle's reference
to the tragic protagonist in masculine terms; however, the definitions
apply equally to female protagonists such as Sophocles's Antigone
and Shakespeare's Cleopatra.)
1. The tragic hero is a man of noble stature. He has a greatness
about him. He is not an ordinary man but one of outstanding quality.
In Greek and in Shakespearean tragedy, he is usually a prince or a king.
We may, if we wish, set down this predilection of former times for kings
as tragic heroes as an undemocratic prejudice that regarded some men
to be of nobler "blood" than others-preeminent by virtue of their aris-
tocratic birth. But it is only partially that. We may with equal validity
regard the hero's kingship as the symbol rather than as the cause of his
greatness. He is great not primarily by virtue of his kingship but by his
possession of extraordinary powers, by qualities of passion or aspiration
or nobility of mind. The tragic hero's kingship is also a symbol of his
initial good fortune, the mark of his high position. If the hero's fall is
to arouse in us the emotions of pity and fear, it must be a fall from a
height. A clumsy man tripping over his shoelace is comic, not tragic-
even if it could cause him serious physical pain.
2. The tragic hero is good, though not perfect, and his fall results
from his committing what Aristotle calls "an act of injustice" (hamar-'
cia) either through ignorance or from a conviction that some greater
good will be served. This act is, nevertheless, a criminal one, and the
good hero is still responsible for it, even if he is totally unaware of its
criminality and is acting out of the best intentions. Some later critics
ignore Aristotle's insistence on the hero's commission of a guilty act
and choose instead to blame the hero's fall on a flaw in his character
or personality. Such a notion misrepresents Aristotle's view both of
tragedy and of a basically just natural order. It implies a world in which
personality alone, not one's actions, can bring on catastrophe.
Aristotle notwithstanding, there is a critical tradition that
attributes the fall of the hero to a so-called "tragic flaw"-some fault of
character such as inordinate ambition, quickness to anger, a tendency
to jealousy, or overweening pride. Conversely, the protagonist's vul-
nerability has been attributed to some excess of virtue-a nobility of
character that unfits him for life among ordinary mortals. But whatever
it be-a criminal act, a fault of character, or excessive virtue-the
protagonist is personally responsible for his downfall.
3. The •• downfall, therefore, is his own fault, the result
of his own free dhoice-e-not the result of pure accident or someone
else's villainy oj· ,some overriding malignant fate. Accident, vil-
lainy, or fate may contribute to the downfall but only as cooperat-
ing agents: they .are not alone responsible. The combination of the
hero's greatness and his responsibility for his own downfall is what
entitles us to describe his downfall as tragic rather than as merely
pathetic. In common speech these two adjectives are often confused.
If a father of ten children is accidentally killed at a street corner,
the event, strictly speaking, is pathetic, not tragic. When a weak
man succumbs to his weakness and comes to a bad end, the event
should be called] pathetic, not tragic. The tragic event involves a
fall from greatness, brought about, at least partially, by the agent's
free action. ,
4. Nevertheless, the hero's misfortune is not wholly deserved. The
punishment exceeds the crime. We do not come away from tragedy
with the feeling that "he got what he had coming to him" but rather
with the sad sense of a waste of human potential. For what most
impresses us about.the tragic hero is not his weakness but his greatness.
He is, in a sense, "larger than life," or, as Aristotle said, "better than
ourselves." He reveals to us the dimensions of human possibility. He
is a person mainly admirable, and his fall therefore fills us with pity
and fear. i
5. Yet the tragic fall is not pure loss. Though it may result in the
protagonist's death, it involves, before his death, some increase in
awareness, some, gain in self-knowledge-as Aristotle puts it, some
"discovery"-a chknge from ignorance to knowledge. On the level of
plot, the disco~eH may be merely learning the truth about some fact
or situation of wb,i!ch the protagonist was ignorant, but on the level of
character it is accldmpanied or followed by a significant insight, a fuller
self-knowledge, an increase not only in knowledge but in wisdom.
Often this increase in wisdom involves some sort of reconciliation
with the universe or with the protagonist's situation. He exits not
I,
cursing his fate bj1utaccepting it and acknowledging that it is to some
degree just.
6. Though it arouses solemn emotions-pity and fear, says Aristo-
tle, but compassion and awe might be better terms-tragedy, when well
performed, does ddt leave its audience in a state of depression. Though
we cannot be sure.what Aristotle meant by his term "catharsis," some
sort of emotional' release at the end is a common experience of those
who witness gre'id tragedies on the stage. They have r:greatly movea by
pity, fear, and associated emotions, but they are not left
emotionally beaten down or dejected. Instead, there may be a feeling
almost of exhilaration. This feeling is a response to the tragic action.
With the fall of the hero and his gain in wisdom or self-knowledge,
there is, besides the appalling sense of human waste, a fresh recognition
of human greatness, a sense that human life has unrealized potentiali-
ties. Though the hero may be defeated, he at least has dared greatly,
and he gains understanding from his defeat.
The most essential difference between tragedy and comedy, par-
ticularly scornful comedy, is in their depiction of human nature.
Where tragedy emphasizes human greatness, comedy delineates human
weakness. Where tragedy celebrates human freedom, comedy points
up human limitations. Wherever human beings fail to measure up to
their own resolutions or to their own self-conceptions, wherever they
are guilty of hypocrisy, vanity, or folly, wherever they fly in the face
of good sense and rational behavior, comedy exhibits their absurdity
and invites us to laugh at them. Where tragedy' tends to say, with
Shakespeare's Hamlet, "What a piece of work is a man! how noble in
reason! how infinite in faculty! in form and moving how express and
admirable! in action how like an angel! in apprehension how like a
god!" comedy says, with Shakespeare's Puck, "Lord, what fools these
mortals be!"
Because comedy exposes human folly, its function is partly critical
and corrective. Where tragedy challenges us with: a vision of human
possibility, comedy reveals to us a spectacle of human ridiculousness
that it makes us want to avoid. No doubt, we should not exaggerate
this function of comedy. We go to the theater primarily for enjoyment,
not to receive lessons in personality or character development. Nev-
ertheless, laughter may be educative at the same time that it is enjoy-
able. The comedies of Aristophanes and Moliere, of Ben Jonson and
Congreve, are, first of all, good fun, but, secondly, they are antidotes
for human folly
Romantic or so/tiling comedy, as opposed to scornful comedy, and
as exemplified by li-rianyplays of Shakespeare-A Midsummer Night's
Dream, As You Li~ It, Twelfth Night, Much Ado About Nothing, The
Tempest, for instance-puts its emphasis upon sympathetic rather than
ridiculous characters. These characters-likable, not given up to folly
or vanity-are placed in various kinds of difficulties from which, at
the end of the play, they are rescued, attaining their ends or having
their good fortunes restored. Though different from the protagonists
of scornful comedy, however, these characters are not the command-
ing or lofty figures that tragic protagonists are. They are sensible and
good rather than noble, aspiring, and grand. They do not strike us with
awe as the tragic protagonist does. They do not so challengingly test
the limits of human possibility. In short, they move in a smaller world.
Romantic comedies, therefore, do not occupy a different universe from
satiric comedies; they simply lie at opposite sides of the same territory.
The romantic comedy, moreover, though its protagonists are sympa-
thetic, has usually a number of lesser characters whose folly is held
up to ridicule. The satiric comedy, on the other hand, frequently has
minor characters=-often a pair of young lovers-who are sympathetic
and likable. The difference between the two kinds of comedy may be
only a matter of whether we laugh at the primary or at the secondary
characters.
There are oth~r differences between comedy and tragedy. The
norms of comedy are primarily social. Where tragedies tend to isolate
their protagonists ':0 emphasize their uniqueness, comedies put their
protagonists in the] midst of a group to emphasize their common-
ness. Where tragic! protagonists possess overpowering individuality,
so that plays are oHen named after them (for example, Oedipus Rex,
Otheno) , comic pr6f.agonists tend to be types of individuals, and the
plays in which the~'lappear are often named for the type (for example,
Moliere's The Misd.~thrope, Congreve's The Double Dealer). We judge
tragic pro~agonists I~y absolute moral stan~ards, by h.ow far they soar
above society. We [udge comic protagonists by SOCialstandards, by
how well they adjust to society and conform to the expectations of
the g~oup. . Ii. . . .
Finally, comic plots are less likely than tragic plots to exhibit the
high degree of orgapic unity-of logical cause-and-effect progression-
that Aristotle required of tragedy. Plausibility, in fact, is not usually the
central characteristic of a comic plot. Unlikely coincidences, improb-
able disguises, mistaken identities-these are the stuff of which comedy
ismade; and, as lor.g as they make us laugh and, at the same time, help
to illuminate human nature and human folly, we need not greatly care.
Not that plausibility is no longer important-only that other things are
more important, and these other things are often achieved by the most
outrageous violations of probability.
This is particularly true regarding the comic ending. Convention-
ally, comedies have a happy ending. The happy ending is, indeed, a con-
vention of comedy, which is to say that a comedy ends happily because
comedies end happily-that is the nature of the form-not necessarily
because a happy ending is a plausible outcome of the events that have
preceded it. The greatest masters of comedy-Aristophanes, Shake-
speare, Moliere-c-have often been extremely arbitrary in the manner in
which they achieved their endings. The accidental discovery of a lost
will, rescue by an act of divine intervention (deus ex machina), the
sudden reform of a mean-spirited person into a friendly person-such
devices have been used by the greatest comic writers. And, even where
the ending is achieved more plausibly, comedy asks us to forget for
the time being that in actuality life has no endings except for death.
Marriage, which provides the ending for so many comedies, is really a
beginning.