Optimality Theory Course
Optimality Theory Course
ren kager
[g c ]
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress cataloguing in publication data
Kager, Ren.
Optimality theory / Ren Kager.
p. cm. (Cambridge textbooks in linguistics)
Includes bibliographical references and indexes.
ISBN 0 521 58019 6 (hardback). ISBN 0 521 58980 0 (paperback)
1. Optimality theory (Linguistics) I. Title. II. Series.
P158.42.K35 1999
410.1 dc21 98 39103 CIP
ISBN 0 521 58019 6 hardback
ISBN 0 521 58980 0 paperback
CONTENTS
Preface
page xi
1 Conflicts in grammars
1.1 Introduction: goals of linguistic theory
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
1.3 Examples of constraint interaction
1.4 The architecture of an OT grammar
1.5 Interactions of markedness and faithfulness
1.6 Lexicon Optimization
1.7 A factorial typology of markedness and faithfulness
1.8 On defining segment inventories
1.9 Conclusion
1
1
3
14
18
27
32
34
43
47
52
52
59
78
91
91
92
83
86
98
117
124
130
139
vii
Contents
viii
142
142
143
148
161
5 Correspondence in reduplication
5.1 Introduction
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
5.3 From classical templates to generalized templates
5.4 From circumscription to alignment
5.5 Classical versus OT-based prosodic morphology:
conclusions
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
5.7 Summary of Correspondence Theory
194
194
201
216
223
6 Output-to-output correspondence
6.1 Introduction
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
6.3 Identity effects in stem-based affixation
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
6.5 Output-to-output correspondence: conclusions
257
257
259
273
277
293
7 Learning OT grammars
7.1 Introduction
7.2 Learning constraint rankings
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
7.4 The learning algorithm: discussion
7.5 Learning alternations and input representations
296
296
297
300
321
324
8 Extensions to syntax
8.1 Introduction
8.2 OT and syntax
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections
in English
8.4 Typological consequences
8.5 Conclusions
341
341
341
177
189
229
230
248
353
366
369
Contents
9 Residual issues
9.1 Introduction
9.2 Opacity
9.3 Absolute ungrammaticality
9.4 Free variation
9.5 Positional faithfulness
9.6 Underlying Representations versus allomorphy
9.7 Conclusion: future perspectives
References
Index of languages
Index of subjects
Index of constraints
372
372
372
400
404
407
413
420
425
445
447
451
ix
1
Conflicts in grammars
Conflicts in grammars
nor on the notion of possible rule interaction. In the late 1970s and early 1980s,
considerable efforts were put into constraining both rule typology and interactions. The broad idea was to factor out universal properties of rules in the form
of conditions.1 While rules themselves may differ between languages, they must
always respect a fixed set of universal principles. Gradually more and more
properties were factored out of rules and attributed to universal conditions on
rules and representations. Developments came to their logical conclusion in
Principles-and-Parameters Theory (Chomsky 1981b, Hayes 1980), which has as
its central claim that grammars of individual languages are built on a central core
of fixed universal properties ( principles), plus a specification of a limited number of universal binary choices ( parameters). Examples of parameters are the side
of the head (left or right) in syntactic phrases, or the obligatoriness (yes/no)
of an onset in a syllable. At the same time, considerable interest developed in
representations, as a way of constraining rule application, mainly with respect to
locality (examples are trace theory in syntax, and underspecification theory in
phonology). Much attention was also devoted to constraining rule interactions,
resulting in sophisticated theories of the architecture of UG (the T-model) and
its components (e.g. Lexical Phonology, Kiparsky 1982b).
1.1.2 Markedness
What all these efforts to constrain rules and rule interactions share, either implicitly or explicitly, is the assumption that universal principles can only be universal
if they are actually inviolate in every language. This interpretation of universality leads to a sharp increase in the abstractness of both linguistic representations
and rule interactions. When some universal principle is violated in the output of
the grammar, then the characteristic way of explaining this was to set up an
intermediate level of representation at which it is actually satisfied. Each grammatical principle thus holds at a specific level of description, and may be switched
off at other levels.
This absolute interpretation of universality is not the only one possible, however. In structuralist linguistics (Hjelmslev 1935, Trubetzkoy 1939, Jakobson
1941; cf. Anderson 1985), but also in Generative Phonology (Chomsky and Halle
1968, Kean 1975, Kiparsky 1985) and Natural Phonology (Stampe 1972, Hooper
1976), a notion of markedness plays a key role, which embodies universality in
a soft sense. The idea is that all types of linguistic structure have two values,
one of which is marked, the other unmarked. Unmarked values are crosslinguistically preferred and basic in all grammars, while marked values are crosslinguistically avoided and used by grammars only to create contrast. For example,
1
For example, Subjacency was proposed as a universal condition on syntactic movement rules
and the Obligatory Contour Principle as a universal condition on phonological rules.
Markedness may also involve scales. For example, the higher a consonants sonority value, the
more likely its occurrence in the syllable coda.
For the view of markedness as a criterion external to the grammar, evaluating its complexity,
see Chomsky and Halle (1968) and Kean (1975, 1981).
Conflicts in grammars
This conflict-regulating mechanism consists of a ranking of universal constraints. Languages basically differ in their ranking of constraints. Each violation
of a constraint is avoided; yet the violation of higher-ranked constraints is avoided
more forcefully than the violation of lower-ranked constraints. Accordingly, the
notion of grammatical well-formedness becomes a relative one, which is equivalent to the degree of satisfaction of the constraint hierarchy, or harmony.
OTs viewpoint of UG is fundamentally different from that of classical rulebased generative theory, where UG is defined as a set of inviolate principles and
rule schemata (or parameters). OT defines UG as a set of universal constraints
(markedness relations and other types of constraints, as we will see below), and
a basic alphabet of linguistic representational categories. In its interactions, it is
limited to a single device: constraint ranking. OT still shares with its rule-based
generative ancestors the central position taken by UG, as described above. OT is
a theory of the human language capacity.
The remainder of this chapter is organized as follows. Section 1.2 will introduce
basic notions of OT: conflict, constraints, and domination, which will be exemplified in section 1.3. In section 1.4, we will discuss the architecture of an OT
grammar. Section 1.5 will deal with interactions of markedness and faithfulness,
relating these to the lexicon in section 1.6. A factorial typology of constraint
interactions will be developed in section 1.7 and applied to segment inventories
in section 1.8. Finally, section 1.9 presents conclusions.
1.2.1 Language as a system of conflicting universal forces
At the heart of Optimality Theory lies the idea that language, and in fact every
grammar, is a system of conflicting forces. These forces are embodied by constraints, each of which makes a requirement about some aspect of grammatical
output forms. Constraints are typically conflicting, in the sense that to satisfy one
constraint implies the violation of another. Given the fact that no form can satisfy
all constraints simultaneously, there must be some mechanism selecting forms that
incur lesser constraint violations from others that incur more serious ones.
This selectional mechanism involves hierarchical ranking of constraints, such
that higher-ranked constraints have priority over lower-ranked ones. While constraints are universal, the rankings are not: differences in ranking are the source
of cross-linguistic variation.
But before discussing actual constraints and their rankings, let us first find out
in a general way about the two major forces embodied by constraints. Two forces
are engaged in a fundamental conflict in every grammar. The first is markedness,
which we use here as a general denominator for the grammatical factors that exert
pressure toward unmarked types of structure. This force is counterbalanced by
4
Conflicts in grammars
systems (or phonologies), lexical contrasts are carried by oppositions between
sounds, as well as by their combinations. Phonological elements are not the only
carriers of lexical contrast. (Although phonology is what we will focus on in this
book.) Lexical contrasts are also expressible by word structure (morphology) or
phrase structure (syntax).
Closely related to faithfulness (or preservation of lexical contrasts) is the pressure towards the shape invariability of lexically related items in various grammatical contexts. This was known in pre-generative linguistics as paradigm
uniformity. Shape invariance of lexical items is understandable as another priority of linguistic communication: there should be a one-to-one relation between
lexical items, the atoms of meaning, and the shapes which encode them.
1.2.2 Conflicts between markedness and faithfulness
Markedness and faithfulness are inherently conflicting. Whenever some lexical
contrast is being preserved, there will be some cost associated in terms of markedness since in every opposition one member is marked. For example, consider
the fact that English limits the possible contrasts in its vowels with respect to the
dimensions of backness and rounding: no rounded front vowels stand in contrast
to unrounded front vowels. This correlation of rounding and backness in vowels
is not idiosyncratic to English, but it reoccurs in a great majority of the worlds
languages. In fact it is grounded in properties of the articulatory and perceptual
systems. Yet this restriction is certainly not universal in the sense that all of
the worlds languages respect it. Many languages do allow a contrast of rounding
in front vowels, thus increasing the potential amount of lexical contrast at the
expense of an increase in markedness.
Generally we find that the larger the array of means of encoding lexical contrasts, the larger the complexity of the sound system, either in terms of segmental
complexity, or in terms of the combinatory possibilities between segments (phonotactics). A language can be maximally faithful to meaningful sound contrasts
only at the expense of an enormous increase in phonological markedness. Conversely, a language can decrease phonological markedness only at the expense of
giving up valuable means to express lexical contrast.
First consider what a hypothetical language would look like at one extreme of the
spectrum: a language giving maximal priority to the expression of lexical contrasts, while imposing no markedness restrictions. We endow this language with
the combined segment inventories of the worlds languages, roughly 50 consonants and 30 vowels (Ladefoged and Maddieson 1996). We drop combinatory
markedness restrictions, allowing all logically possible segment combinations to
form a lexical item. Permutation of these 80 segments into lexical items of two
6
These limitations are actually grounded in speech production and perception: every consonant
is maximally different from a vowel (hence, all consonants are voiceless stops). Every vowel
is maximally different from other vowels (a 2-vowel set, a). Every consonant is maximally
different from other consonants (place of articulation restricted to labial, alveolar, and velar).
Every vowel is preceded by a consonant (no word-initial vowels, no hiatus). Every consonant
precedes a vowel for optimal release (hence no consonant clusters nor word-final Cs).
Suppose that our hypothetical language would not respect word size restrictions, having at its
disposition all possible CV*-shaped items. Here, with a maximal density of lexical contrast,
all potential items up to seven syllables long would not suffice to build the required size of
lexicon. This would only reach to a moderate total of (46,656 + 7,776 + 1296 + 216 + 36 +
6) = 55,986 lexical items. The average item in this language would be over six syllables long.
Without doubt, speaking would become a rather time-consuming activity.
Conflicts in grammars
In sum, we have seen that every grammar must reconcile the inherently competing forces of faithfulness to lexical contrasts (the inertness which draws output
forms back to their basic lexical shapes) and markedness (minimization of
marked forms). However, as we are about to find out, Optimality Theory recognizes no unitary or monolithic forces of faithfulness or markedness: the picture
is more fragmented. In the grammars of individual languages, the overall conflict
between both forces assumes the form of finer-grained interactions of individual
constraints. At this level, where individual constraints compete, languages are
quite diverse in their resolutions of conflicts between markedness and faithfulness. A language may give priority to faithfulness over markedness with respect
to some opposition, but reverse its priorities for another opposition.
Let us now turn to the implementation of these basic ideas in Optimality
Theory.
1.2.3 The OT grammar as an inputoutput device
The basic assumption of OT is that each linguistic output form is optimal, in the
sense that it incurs the least serious violations of a set of conflicting constraints.
For a given input, the grammar generates and then evaluates an infinite set of
output candidates, from which it selects the optimal candidate, which is the actual
output. Evaluation takes place by a set of hierarchically ranked constraints (C1
C2 . . . Cn), each of which may eliminate some candidate outputs, until a point
is reached at which only one output candidate survives. This elimination process
is represented schematically:6
(1)
Input
Candidate a
Candidate b
Candidate c
Candidate d
Candidate . . .
C2 . . . Cn
Output
The optimal output candidate is the one that is most harmonic with respect to
the set of ranked constraints. Harmony is a kind of relative well-formedness,
taking into account the severity of the violations of individual constraints, as
determined by their hierarchical ranking. That is, violation of a higher-ranked
6
Conflicts in grammars
As we have seen in section 1.1, markedness is an inherently asymmetrical
notion. Hence, the universal constraint inventory lacks the antagonist constraints
of (1ae), which make opposite requirements syllables must have codas, sonorants must be voiceless, etc.7
Faithfulness constraints require that outputs preserve the properties of their basic
(lexical) forms, requiring some kind of similarity between the output and its
input.
(3)
Faithfulness constraints are, strictly speaking, not pure output constraints, since
they take into account elements at two levels: input and output. In contrast,
markedness constraints never take into account elements in the input.8 The
important thing is, however, that both kinds of constraints refer to the output
(exclusively so in markedness, and in relation to the input in faithfulness). OT has
no constraints that exclusively refer to the input. (This is a crucial difference from
classical generative phonology, as we will see in chapter 2.)
From a functional viewpoint, faithfulness constraints protect the lexical items
of a language against the eroding powers of markedness constraints, and thereby
serve two major communicative functions. First, they preserve lexical contrasts,
making it possible for languages to have sets of formally distinct lexical items to
express different meanings. Phrasing it slightly differently, with an emphasis on
contrast, we may say that faithfulness is what keeps the shapes of different lexical
items apart. Second, by limiting the distance between input and output, faithfulness constraints restrict the shape variability of lexical items. Faithfulness thus
keeps the contextual realizations of a single morpheme (called its alternants)
from drifting too far apart. This enhances the one-to-one relations of meaning and
form. In sum, the overall function of faithfulness is to enforce the phonological
shape of lexical forms in the output, as a sort of inertness limiting the distance
between outputs and their basic shapes.
Two more assumptions are to be made about constraints in OT: they are universal and violable requirements on some aspect of linguistic output forms. Let
us now focus on each of these properties of constraints. The first property is
7
8
10
In its strongest interpretation, by which all constraints are part of UG, this implies
that all constraints are part of the grammars of all natural languages. This is not
to say that every constraint will be equally active in all languages. Due to the
language-specific ranking of constraints, a constraint that is never violated in one
language may be violated but still be active in a second language, and be totally
inactive in yet a third language. This strong interpretation, which leaves no room
for language-specific constraints, nor for constraint variability, will be slightly
relativized below.
For phonological markedness constraints, universality may be established by a
variety of factors, ideally in combination. The first sense of universality is typological:
a constraint states a preference for certain structures over other types of structures, which reoccurs in a range of unrelated languages. Segmental markedness
constraints, for example, may be validated by inspecting the relative markedness
of segments in inventories on a cross-linguistic basis. (Such an overview is presented in Maddieson 1984.) However, any exclusively typology-based definition of universality runs the risk of circularity: certain properties are posited as
unmarked simply because they occur in sound systems with greater frequency
than other marked properties.
Hence, a second (non-circular) criterion of universality should ideally accompany typological criteria: phonological markedness constraints should be phonetically grounded in some property of articulation or perception. That is, phonetic
evidence from production or perception should support a cross-linguistic preference for a segment (or feature value) to others in certain contexts. For example,
there is articulatory evidence (to be reviewed in chapter 2) that voiced obstruents
are preferred to voiceless obstruents in a position immediately following a nasal.
Indeed many languages avoid or disallow voiceless post-nasal obstruents, neutralizing voicing contrasts in this position.9 Even though a growing number of
constraints has been phonetically grounded (see the suggested readings at the end
of this chapter), such grounding is still lacking for others.
It should be clear from this discussion that we should be very careful about
positing any constraint lacking both typological motivation and phonetic grounding, even if there is compelling motivation for it from the language data under
analysis. Nevertheless, not all constraints that have been proposed in the OT literature satisfy both criteria, indicating that the major issue of universality of
constraints has not yet been resolved, since analysts do not share the same criteria.
In this book, whenever we employ a constraint that strikes us as parochial or
Post-nasal voicing and its typological consequences will be discussed in detail in chapter 2.
11
Conflicts in grammars
language-specific (since it lacks both phonetic grounding and cross-linguistic
motivation), this will be indicated.
However, the universality of constraints should directly be relativized somewhat. We will find that in special cases, language-specific elements may occur in
constraints of otherwise universal formats. This option is typical for a class of
constraints defining the interface of morphology and phonology, so-called alignment constraints, matching up the edges of specific morphemes and prosodic
categories. (See chapters 3 and 5.) Such interface constraints define schemata in
which individual languages may substitute their specific morphemes.
We now move on to the second major property of OT constraints: their softness,
or violability. Violability of constraints must be understood in a specific way: the
general requirement is that it must be minimal:
(5)
12
So we assume that each output form of the grammar is by definition the best
possible in terms of the hierarchy of constraints, rather than the form which
matches all constraints at the same time. Perfect output forms are principally
non-existent, as every output form will violate at least some constraints. Therefore the selection of the optimal output form involves setting priorities.
This is where a hierarchy comes into play. Conflicts are resolved by domination:
(7)
This tentative definition will be refined below in section 1.4, on the basis of more
complex cases.
The ranking of constraints can be demonstrated by a tableau: this lists two
(or any number of) output candidates vertically in random order, and constraints
horizontally, in a descending ranking from left to right. The cells contain violation
marks * incurred by each candidate for the constraint heading the column.
Schematically:
(8)
candidate b
C2
*
*!
The optimal candidate is marked by the index +. This candidate is (8a), which
has no violations of the higher-ranked constraint C1, a constraint violated by its
competitor (8b). Note that the optimal candidate (8a) is actually not impeccable
itself: it has a violation of C2, but this flaw is insignificant to the outcome.
Although the pattern of violations for C2 is the reverse of that for C1, this does
not help candidate b. Its violation of C1 is already fatal, indicated by the accompanying exclamation mark ! and the shading of cells whose violation content is
no longer relevant. In sum, candidate (a) is optimal as no candidate is available
that fares better, satisfying both constraints at the same time. A violation of C2 is
taken for granted, as long as C1 can be satisfied.
We now turn to exemplification of the ideas that have been introduced thus far.
13
Conflicts in grammars
1.3 Examples of constraint interaction
1.3.1 Neutralization of voicing contrast in Dutch
Among the universal and violable constraints is the following:
(9)
*Voiced-Coda
Obstruents must not be voiced in coda position.
This is a typical markedness constraint, which bans a marked segment type (here:
voiced obstruents) from the syllable coda (which is itself a marked position).10
Coda obstruents are voiceless in Dutch, as illustrated by the following
alternation:
(10)
a. /bd/
bt
bed
b. /bd-n/ bdn beds
If this constraint were the only one relevant for these forms, then things would
be simple. Violators could be dismissed without second thoughts. But in actual
grammars things are not that simple since constraints may make conflicting
requirements about output forms.
A second constraint of the universal inventory is a typical faithfulness constraint, requiring that the input value of the feature [voice] be preserved in the
output.
(12)
10
Ident-IO(voice)
The specification for the feature [voice] of an input segment must be
preserved in its output correspondent.
14
This informal definition is precise enough for our present purposes. (We will
return to the important notion of correspondence, particularly in chapters 2 and
5.)
In a correspondence diagram of the Dutch word [bt] bed the input and output segments that are correspondents of one another are connected by vertical lines.
(14)
Observe the conflict: the evaluation of both output forms is different for each
constraint.
This conflict requires resolution, which is the task of the constraint hierarchy.
The form [bt] emerges as the optimal output of the grammar, given the following
fragment of the phonology of the language:
(16)
Conflicts in grammars
well-formedness with respect to the ranking in (16). Or stated differently, [bt] is
more harmonic than [bd] with respect to the ranking in (16).
(17)
Since we are only considering two candidates here, the harmonic ranking directly
gives us the optimal output: [bt].
The correctness of this constraint ranking can be represented in a tableau-format:
(18)
*Voiced-Coda
a. + [bt]
b.
Ident-IO(voice)
*
[bd]
*!
The optimal candidate in the top row, [bt], incurs a violation of Ident-IO(voice)
while it satisfies *Voiced-Coda. Suboptimal [bd] has exactly the reverse pattern
of violations: it has a violation mark for *Voiced-Coda, but none for IdentIO(voice).
Being presented with these two output candidates, the grammar (whose only
goal is selecting an optimal output) must settle for a candidate that has a violation
of a lower-ranked constraint, simply because no perfect output candidate is available, satisfying both constraints. This point can be made more general: constraints
are intrinsically conflicting, hence perfect output candidates will never occur in
any tableau:
(19)
An output is optimal since there is no such thing as a perfect output: all that
grammars may accomplish is to select the most harmonic output, the one which
incurs the minimal violation of constraints, taking into account their ranking.
Nothing better is available.
Observe that the result of the constraint interaction in Dutch is a neutralization
of the voicing contrast in a specific context: the syllable coda. That neutralization
indeed takes place can be easily shown by the following set of examples:
(20)
16
a.i
a.ii
b.i
b.ii
/bd/
/bd-n/
/bt/
/bt-n/
bt
b.dn
bt
b.tn
bed
beds
(I) dab
(we) dab
That is, assuming an input /bd/, [bd] is more harmonic than [bt] with respect
to the ranking in (21).
Again, we illustrate this ranking with the help of a tableau, evaluating the same
candidates as we used in tableau (18) for Dutch. Observe that Ident-IO(voice)
and *Voiced-Coda have changed places:
(23)
[bt]
b. + [bd]
Ident-IO(voice)
*Voiced-Coda
*!
*
The net result of this ranking is that the index pointing at the optimal output has
shifted downwards (as compared to tableau 18) to the second candidate under
consideration, that is, [bed]. Note that by this ranking, English preserves the
phonological contrast between distinct lexical items, as in bed [bd] versus bet
17
Conflicts in grammars
[bt]. (This contrast is actually reinforced by a subsidiary vowel length difference
between both words: [b]d] versus [bt].)
1.3.3 The relation between universal and language-specific
What we have just witnessed in the examples from Dutch and English is the
universal pan-grammatical conflict of markedness and faithfulness taking place
on a micro-scale. In both languages, the same conflict arises with respect to
preservation of a contrastive property (the feature [voice]), and its neutralization
in a specific context (syllable coda). However, the outcome of this conflict is
different for both languages. Dutch resolves it in the favour of markedness
whereas English favours faithfulness. This shows that universal constraints are
ranked in language-specific ways. OT clearly marks off the universal from the
language-specific. Both constraints and the general principles of their interaction
are universal, while constraint hierarchies are language-specific.
Speaking of forces of faithfulness and markedness is somewhat misleading,
since this suggests that conflicts between these forces are resolved on a superordinate level in the grammar of a single language. This is clearly not the case.
For example, the fact that Dutch ranks markedness above faithfulness with
respect to voice in coda obstruents does not imply that it selects the same ranking
(M F) with respect to voice in other contexts, nor that it selects this ranking
with respect to other features in the syllable coda. In Dutch, voice is contrastive
in obstruents in onsets (even though voiced obstruents are universally marked).
Also, place features are contrastive in obstruents and nasals in codas (in spite of
the markedness of labials and velars). This shows that there are no monolithic
forces of faithfulness and markedness, but that instead finer-grained interactions
occur between the context- and feature-specific versions of these classes of constraints. Still, for expository purposes, the classification of constraints into faithfulness and markedness constraints remains useful, as are shorthand notations
such as M F.
These remarks bring us back to our starting point in this section: the conception of universal grammar in OT. But what exactly do we mean by grammar in
the first place? The OT grammar, and its architecture, will be the topic of the next
section.
1.4 The architecture of an OT grammar
The OT grammar is an inputoutput mechanism that pairs an output form to an
input form (such that each input has precisely one output). To accomplish this
function, the grammar contains a division of labour between a component
which maps the input onto an infinite set of candidate output forms, and another
component that is burdened with evaluating the candidate output forms by a set
18
That is, Gen is a function that, when applied to some input, produces a set of
candidates, all of which are logically possible analyses of this input. Similarly,
Eval is a function that, when applied to a set of output candidates, produces an
output, the optimal analysis of the input. In addition to Gen and Eval, the grammar contains a lexicon storing all lexical forms that are input to Gen. Recapitulating, we find the following model of the grammar:
(25)
Conflicts in grammars
representation, is attributed to interactions at the output level in OT. Whether or
not a feature is contrastive in some language depends on interactions of outputoriented markedness and faithfulness constraints, either preserving or overruling
input specifications (see section 1.5).
OT thus abandons Morpheme Structure Constraints (MSCs), which in classical
generative phonology (Chomsky and Halle 1968) account for prohibitions against
specific types of structure at the level of the morpheme, in specific languages.
MSCs were used, for example, to express prohibitions against front rounded vowels,
or sequences of three or more consonants, or two labial consonants occurring
within a morpheme. In the early 1970s MSCs were argued to be theoretically
problematic in the sense that they duplicate information which is, independently,
expressed by phonological rewrite rules, or that they globally guide the application of rules, a property called structure-preservingness.11 By locating the burden
of explanation of the lack of specific kinds of structure at the level of the output,
OT, in principle at least, circumvents this Duplication Problem.
1.4.2 The GENERATOR , and Freedom of Analysis
The essential property of the Generator is that it is free to generate any conceivable output candidate for some input. This property is called Freedom of Analysis.
(27)
The only true restriction imposed on all output candidates generated by Gen is
that these are made up of licit elements from the universal vocabularies of linguistic representation, such as segmental structure (features and their grouping
below the level of the segment), prosodic structure (mora, syllable, foot, prosodic
word, etc.), morphology (root, stem, word, affix, etc.), and syntax (X-bar structure, heads/complements/specifiers, etc.). Within these limits, anything goes.
Since Gen generates all logically possible candidate analyses of a given input,
the OT grammar needs no rewrite rules to map inputs onto outputs. All structural
changes are applied in one step, in parallel. The evaluation of these candidate
analyses is the function of the Evaluator, the component of ranked constraints,
discussed in section 1.4.3. There we will also discuss the issue of whether or not
Eval is able to deal with an infinite candidate space.
1.4.3 The EVALUATOR: economy, strict domination, and parallelism
The Evaluator (henceforth Eval ) is undoubtedly the central component of
the grammar since it is burdened with the responsibility of accounting for all
11
For example, rewrite rules may be blocked if their output would violate a MSC, or may be
triggered to repair a violation of a MSC.
20