09-23 Slides
09-23 Slides
1
Origin essentialism
Salmon’s reconstruction of Kripke’s argument from footnote 56
Sufficiency For any table t and hunk h: if it is possible for t to be a table originally
formed from h, then it is impossible for a table distinct from t to be
originally formed from h.
Origin Uniqueness Necessarily, no table is originally formed from two distinct hunks.
Weak Compossibility For any two non-overlapping hunks, if each is such that it is
possible for there to be a table originally formed from it, it is possible
that both of them originally form tables.
Necessity of Distinctness For any objects x and y, if x ̸= y, then it is impossible for
it to be the case that x = y.
Overlap Essentialism For any non-overlapping hunks h1 and h2 and table t, if t is
originally formed from h1 , it is impossible for t to be originally formed
from h2 .
2
Why is this argument valid?
3
Why is this argument valid?
3
Why is this argument valid?
3
The other premises: Origin Uniqueness
▶ Of course we could combine two or more hunks of wood to form a table! But the
resulting table is ‘originally formed’ not from any of those small hunks, but from a
bigger hunk that each of them is part of.
4
The other premises: Weak Compossibility
Weak Compossibility seems pretty plausible: what, if not overlap, could explain the
impossibility of making two hunks into tables, if each alone could be made into a table?
5
The other premises: Weak Compossibility
Weak Compossibility seems pretty plausible: what, if not overlap, could explain the
impossibility of making two hunks into tables, if each alone could be made into a table?
But if we wanted to be cautious, we could avoid the need for this premise by replacing
‘non-overlapping’ throughout the argument with ‘such that it is possible that both are
made into distinct tables’. This corresponds to Kripke’s parenthetical remark ‘(We
assume that there is no relation between A and C which makes the possibility of
making a table from one dependent on the possibility of making a table from the
other.)’
5
The other premises: Weak Compossibility
Weak Compossibility seems pretty plausible: what, if not overlap, could explain the
impossibility of making two hunks into tables, if each alone could be made into a table?
But if we wanted to be cautious, we could avoid the need for this premise by replacing
‘non-overlapping’ throughout the argument with ‘such that it is possible that both are
made into distinct tables’. This corresponds to Kripke’s parenthetical remark ‘(We
assume that there is no relation between A and C which makes the possibility of
making a table from one dependent on the possibility of making a table from the
other.)’
The conclusion will then be:
Weaker Origin Essentialism For any hunks h1 and h2 such that it’s possible that h1
and h2 are both made into two distinct tables, and any table t that is
originally formed from h1 , it is impossible for t to be originally formed
5
from h2 .
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
6
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
Immediately after the passage quoted above, Kripke suggests two arguments for ND!
Here is the first:
» However, the same types of considerations that can be used to establish the latter
can be used to establish the former. (Suppose X ̸= Y; if X and Y were both
identical to some object Z in another possible world, then X = Z, Y = Z, hence
X = Y.)
7
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
Immediately after the passage quoted above, Kripke suggests two arguments for ND!
Here is the first:
» However, the same types of considerations that can be used to establish the latter
can be used to establish the former. (Suppose X ̸= Y; if X and Y were both
identical to some object Z in another possible world, then X = Z, Y = Z, hence
X = Y.)
There must be some blunder here. It looks like the only properties of identity being
appealed to are transitivity and symmetry. But there are many transitive and
symmetric relations R for which it can be false that x bears R to y without it being
necessarily false—e.g. being the same height as.
7
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
Immediately after the passage quoted above, Kripke suggests two arguments for ND!
Here is the first:
» However, the same types of considerations that can be used to establish the latter
can be used to establish the former. (Suppose X ̸= Y; if X and Y were both
identical to some object Z in another possible world, then X = Z, Y = Z, hence
X = Y.)
There must be some blunder here. It looks like the only properties of identity being
appealed to are transitivity and symmetry. But there are many transitive and
symmetric relations R for which it can be false that x bears R to y without it being
necessarily false—e.g. being the same height as.
Kripke seems to be simply assuming that if X = Z at some possible world w, then
X = Z. But that’s just equivalent to ND, which he’s supposed to be arguing for!
7
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
» Alternatively, the principle follows from the necessity of identity plus the
’Brouwersche’ axiom, or, equivalently, symmetry of the accessibility relation
between possible worlds.
Here, Kripke is referring to the following principle, named for L.E.J. Brouwer:
8
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
FYI: ‘The accessibility relation between possible worlds’ can be defined as follows:
The symmetry of accessibility entails that the actual world A is a possible world at
every possible world, hence that A is necessarily a possible world, hence that everything
that is the case is necessarily possibly the case.
(We can also use the necessity of B to go the other way, but that’s a bit more
complicated.)
9
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
10
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
But why believe B??? I don’t know any good snappy arguments.
10
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
11
The other premises: Necessity of Distinctness
Weakest Overlap Essentialism For any hunks h1 and h2 that could be made into
two distinct tables and any table t originally formed from h1 , it is
impossible for t to be originally formed from h2 and not from h1 .
11
Problems with Sufficiency: plans
12
Problems with Sufficiency: plans
13
Problems with Sufficiency: plans
A single hunk of wood can be shaped into a table; disassembled; and later made into a
table again, according to the same or a different plan.
Sufficiency implies that whenever this happens, we get the same table both times.
Plan Sufficiency has the same implication in situations where the same plan is used
both times. That may seem dubious!
14
Salmon’s argument against Plan Sufficiency
Maybe it’s not so bad to think that these are cases where we get the same table
again—after all, things do seem to routinely survive disassembly and reassembly.
Salmon (1979) gives an argument against Sufficiency and Plan Sufficiency based on
the following cases.
Table Of Theseus With Reassembly A table is made in 1900 out of hunk h
according to plan P. Over the next fifty years, bits of h are gradually replaced,
until finally at t + 50 none of the original bits of h are part of a table. Then, all
the bits of h are gathered and reassembled into a table, again according to P.
Salmon’s judgment: The original table survives the part-replacements and is in 1950
composed of matter not overlapping h. So, it is not the table made of h in 1950.
15
Salmon’s argument against Plan Sufficiency
Maybe it’s not so bad to think that these are cases where we get the same table
again—after all, things do seem to routinely survive disassembly and reassembly.
Salmon (1979) gives an argument against Sufficiency and Plan Sufficiency based on
the following cases.
Table Of Theseus With Reassembly A table is made in 1900 out of hunk h
according to plan P. Over the next fifty years, bits of h are gradually replaced,
until finally at t + 50 none of the original bits of h are part of a table. Then, all
the bits of h are gathered and reassembled into a table, again according to P.
Salmon’s judgment: The original table survives the part-replacements and is in 1950
composed of matter not overlapping h. So, it is not the table made of h in 1950.
(This is non-obvious! Hobbes 1655 gives essentially the same case with ships, and uses
it to argue that no ship can survive replacement of any of its parts.) 15
Weakening Sufficiency
Only-table Plan Sufficiency For any table t, hunk h, and plan P: if it is possible for
t to be the only table ever originally formed from h, and formed
according to P, then it is impossible for a table distinct from t to be the
only table originally formed from h and formed according to P.
16
Weakening Sufficiency
Only-table Plan Sufficiency For any table t, hunk h, and plan P: if it is possible for
t to be the only table ever originally formed from h, and formed
according to P, then it is impossible for a table distinct from t to be the
only table originally formed from h and formed according to P.
16
Weakening Sufficiency
Not Quite Theseus At possible world w, hunk h is shaped into a table at t; this
table is disassembled, and then much later at t′ , a hunk h′ almost but not entirely
overlapping h is shaped into a table according to the same plan. None of this
wood is ever again used for tables.
At w′ , almost the same story plays out except that h′ is used at t and h is used at
t′ .
Only-table Plan Sufficiency that the table made at t at w is made at t′ at w′ and vice
versa. This seems implausible.
17
Weakening Sufficiency
18
Weakening Sufficiency
18
Weakening Sufficiency
Intuitively: a qualitative property is one that isn’t “about” any specific objects.
Qualitative Presumably not qualitative
Being spherical Being identical to Robert M. Adams
Being either green or spherical Being either green or identical to Kripke or
identical to Adams
Being more than ten miles from all cities Being more than ten miles from NYC
Being a state that contains a big city Being a state that contains NYC
19
The concept of a qualitative property
Intuitively: a qualitative property is one that isn’t “about” any specific objects.
Qualitative Presumably not qualitative
Being spherical Being identical to Robert M. Adams
Being either green or spherical Being either green or identical to Kripke or
identical to Adams
Being more than ten miles from all cities Being more than ten miles from NYC
Being a state that contains a big city Being a state that contains NYC
Adams calls qualitative properties ‘suchnesses’. He calls properties of the form being
identical to x for some x ‘thisnesses’.
These labels didn’t catch on. Amazingly, the label ‘haecceity’ (pron. hax-ee-ity) for
what Adams calls a ‘thisness’ did catch on.
19
Qualitative relations and states of affairs
The contrast between qualitative and non-qualitative isn’t just about properties, but
also applies to relations and states of affairs.
Qualitative Presumably not qualitative
Being bigger than Being closer to NYC than
Being six feet away from Mentioning more Kripke more often than
That at least one park is rectangular That Central Park is rectangular
That it’s possible for every donkey can talk That it’s possible for every donkey to be in
NYC
20
Closure under definability
Any property, relation, or state of affairs that we can define in terms of qualitative
ingredients is itself qualitative.
E.g.: being red and touching are both qualitative; so touching at least one red thing,
not being red, that some red thing touches some non-red thing,…are all qualitative.
21
Caution!
Given the examples, it is tempting to assume that any property, relation, or state of
affairs expressed by a predicate/sentence involving the proper name of an object is not
qualitative.
But this is controversial! Consider the property of being either red or identical to
Kripke, and red. Some hold that this property is identical to being red, and hence
qualitative despite the fact that we just expressed it using a predicate including a
proper name.
22
Caution!
Given the examples, it is tempting to assume that any property, relation, or state of
affairs expressed by a predicate/sentence involving the proper name of an object is not
qualitative.
But this is controversial! Consider the property of being either red or identical to
Kripke, and red. Some hold that this property is identical to being red, and hence
qualitative despite the fact that we just expressed it using a predicate including a
proper name.
Here is one pretty popular view that entails this:
22
Haecceities
Can we at least say for every object x, x’s haecceity—i.e., the property of being
identical to x—is non-qualitative?
Even this is controversial. For example, maybe God exists, and His haecceity is
identical to the qualitative property being omnipotent.
23
Haecceities
Can we at least say for every object x, x’s haecceity—i.e., the property of being
identical to x—is non-qualitative?
Even this is controversial. For example, maybe God exists, and His haecceity is
identical to the qualitative property being omnipotent.
Adams attributes to Leibniz the view that all haecceities—and in fact all properties,
relations, and states of affairs whatsoever—are qualitative. Given this, we can’t give
100% uncontroversial examples of anything non-qualitative.
23
The Identity of Indiscernibles and
Anti-Haecceitism
The Identity of Indiscernibles
In addition to the law named after him, Leibniz also endorsed its converse:
24
The Identity of Indiscernibles
Using the notion of a qualitative property, we can state a more controversial principle
(that probably comes closer to what Leibniz had in mind):
25
The debate about the Identity of Indiscernibles, pre-Adams
Black (1952): it seems possible (maybe even physically possible) for the world to be
symmetric. For example, there could be just two globes of iron, exact duplicates of one
another, revolving around each other forever in otherwise empty space. Such objects
would be distinct while having exactly the same qualitative properties. So the Identity
of Indiscernibles is possibly false.
26
The debate about the Identity of Indiscernibles, pre-Adams
Black (1952): it seems possible (maybe even physically possible) for the world to be
symmetric. For example, there could be just two globes of iron, exact duplicates of one
another, revolving around each other forever in otherwise empty space. Such objects
would be distinct while having exactly the same qualitative properties. So the Identity
of Indiscernibles is possibly false.
Response (cf. Adams’s discussion of Hacking): that’s not possible! If it seems possible,
maybe that’s because you’re confusing it with a genuine possibility that that’s sort of
like it, namely a world with a single sphere in an interestingly non-Euclidean space
where you can follow a straight line and get back where you started.
26
The debate about the Identity of Indiscernibles, pre-Adams
Black (1952): it seems possible (maybe even physically possible) for the world to be
symmetric. For example, there could be just two globes of iron, exact duplicates of one
another, revolving around each other forever in otherwise empty space. Such objects
would be distinct while having exactly the same qualitative properties. So the Identity
of Indiscernibles is possibly false.
Response (cf. Adams’s discussion of Hacking): that’s not possible! If it seems possible,
maybe that’s because you’re confusing it with a genuine possibility that that’s sort of
like it, namely a world with a single sphere in an interestingly non-Euclidean space
where you can follow a straight line and get back where you started.
Adams gives a new argument against II that we’ll discuss next time.
26
Anti-haecceitism
But what is this view that Kripke doesn’t like? If we drop the epistemological remarks
about ‘having a way of telling’, the idea seems to be that the array of qualitative facts
that hold at a world fixes all the facts that hold there:
Anti-Haecceitism (PW version) For any metaphysically possible worlds v and w, if
v ̸= w, then there is some qualitative state of affairs that holds at v but
not w.
For example: there is no possible world just like the actual world except that two
electrons swap roles.
28
Anti-haecceitism
But what is this view that Kripke doesn’t like? If we drop the epistemological remarks
about ‘having a way of telling’, the idea seems to be that the array of qualitative facts
that hold at a world fixes all the facts that hold there:
Anti-Haecceitism (PW version) For any metaphysically possible worlds v and w, if
v ̸= w, then there is some qualitative state of affairs that holds at v but
not w.
For example: there is no possible world just like the actual world except that two
electrons swap roles.
▶ Adams seems to think that Anti-Haecceitism follows from the Identity of
Indiscernibles applied to possible worlds.
This is a mistake: in principle, two worlds at which exactly the same qualitative
states of affairs obtain could differ as regards other qualitative properties, like
28
being actual or being a world such that some red thing is green at it.
Application 3: Anti-haecceitism
This is a case where we don’t really need to bring in possible worlds to get at the idea.
The following seems to do the job:
This is equivalent to the PW version if we assume the Leibniz Biconditionals and the
principle that no two worlds are such that exactly the same propositions are true at
them.
29
Application 2: Anti-haecceitism
30
Application 2: Anti-haecceitism