5TAI.
UBRAR
CONTRIBUTIONS TO
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY OF
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
The Open Court
Series
of Classics of Science and
Thilosophy, $(o.
CONTRIBUTIONS TO
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY OF
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
BY
GEORG CANTOR
TRANSLATED, AND PROVIDED WITH AN INTRODUCTION
AND NOTES, BY
PHILIP
E. B.
JOURDAIN
M. A. (CANTAB.)
CHICAGO AND LONDON
THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY
1915
Copyright in Great Britain under the Act of 191
STAT.
PREFACE
" BRAit
THIS volume contains a translation of the two very
important memoirs of Georg Cantor on transfinite
numbers which appeared in the Mathematische
Annalen for 1895 an ^ 1897* under the title:
"Beitrage zur Begriindung der transfmiten MengenIt seems to me that, since these memoirs
lehre."
are chiefly occupied with the investigation of the
various transfinite cardinal and ordinal numbers and
not with investigations belonging to what is usually
described as "the theory of aggregates" or "the
"
theory of sets (Mengenlekre theorie des ensembles},
y
elements of the sets being real or complex
the
numbers which are imaged as geometrical " points "
the title given
in space of one or more dimensions,
to them in this translation is more suitable.
These memoirs are the final and logically purified
statement of many of the most important results of
the long series of memoirs begun by Cantor in 1870.
It is,
to
think, necessary,
earlier researches
It
if
we
are to appreciate the
work on transfinite numbers,
have thought through and to bear in mind Cantor s
import of Cantor
full
was
*
in these
on the theory of point-aggregates.
that the need for the
researches
Vol. xlvi, 1895, pp. 481-512
v
vol. xlix, 1897, pp.
207-246.
PREFACE
vi
transfinite
numbers
showed
first
itself,
and
it is
only
by the study of these researches that the majority
of us can annihilate the feeling of arbitrariness and
insecurity about the introduction of these
even
numbers.
Furthermore,
it is
also necessary to trace
the
through Weierstrass,
course of those researches which led to Cantor s
backwards,
especially
have, then, prefixed an Introduction tracing
the growth of parts of the theory of functions during
work.
the nineteenth century, and dealing, in some detail,
with the fundamental work of Weierstrass and others,
and with the work of Cantor from 1870 to 1895.
Some notes at the end contain a short account of the
developments of the theory of transfinite numbers
^ n these notes and in the Introduction
since 1897.
I have been greatly helped by the information that
Professor Cantor gave me in the course of a long
correspondence on the theory of aggregates which
we carried on many years ago.
The philosophical revolution brought
about by
Cantor s work was even greater, perhaps, than the
With few exceptions, mathe
mathematical one.
maticians joyfully accepted, built upon, scrutinized,
and perfected the foundations of Cantor s undying
but very many philosophers combated it.
theory
This seems to have been because very few under
;
stood
it.
hope that
the subject better
mathematicians.
The
three
mathematics
this
known
men whose
book may help
to
make
to both philosophers
influence on
and indirectly modern
and
modern pure
and the
logic
PREFACE
vii
philosophy which abuts on it is most marked are
Karl Weierstrass, Richard Dedekind, and Georg
A great part of Dedekind s work has de
Cantor.
veloped along a direction parallel to the work of
Cantor, and it is instructive to compare with Cantor s
work Dedekind s Stetigkeit und irrationale Zahlen
and Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen ?, of which
excellent English translations have been issued
the publishers of the present book. *
by
There is a French translation f of these memoirs of
Cantor s, but there is no English translation of them.
For kind permission to make the translation, I
am
indebted to Messrs B.
and
Berlin,
G.
the publishers
Teubner of Leipzig
of the Mathematische
Annalen.
PHILIP
*
Essays on the Theory of Numbers
Numbers
II,
(I,
E. B.
JOURDAIN.
Continuity
and
Irrational
The Nature and Meaning of Numbers], translated by
W. W. Beman,
Chicago,
1901.
shall refer to this as
Essays on
Number.
t
By
F.
Marotte, Sur
trans/mis, Paris, 1899.
les
fondements de
la
theorie des
ensembles
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PAGE
PREFACE
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
ix
CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
ARTICLE
I.
ARTICLE
II.
NOTES
INDEX
(1895)
(1897)
...
85
137
.-
202
209
.V
CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE
FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
INTRODUCTION
I
safe to trace back to any single man the
of
those conceptions with which pure mathe
origin
IF
it
is
matical analysis has been chiefly occupied during
the nineteenth century and up to the present time,
we must,
I think, trace it back to
Jean Baptiste
Fourier was first and
Fourier
Joseph
(1768-1830).
foremost a physicist, and he expressed very defin
itely his
by
view that mathematics only justifies itself
it gives towards the solution of
physical
the help
problems, and yet the light that was thrown on the
general conception of a function and its "con
tinuity," of
and of an
the "convergence"
of
infinite
series,
to shine as a result
first
began
of Fourier s original and bold treatment of the
This it was
problems of the conduction of heat.
that gave the impetus to the formation and develop
ment of the theories of functions.
The broadminded physicist will approve of this refining
integral,
INTRODUCTION
development of the mathematical methods which
arise from physical conceptions when he reflects
that mathematics is a wonderfully powerful and
economically contrived means of dealing logically
and conveniently with an immense complex of data,
and that we cannot be sure of the logical soundness
of our methods and results until we make every
The pure mathe
thing about them quite definite.
matician knows that pure mathematics has an end
in itself which is more allied with philosophy.
But
we have not to justify pure mathematics here we
have only to point out its origin in physical con
But we have also pointed out that
ceptions.
can
justify even the most modern develop
physics
ments of pure mathematics.
:
II
During the nineteenth century, the two great
branches of the theory of functions developed and
The rigorous foundation of
gradually separated.
the
results
of
Fourier on
trigonometrical
series,
which was given by Dirichlet, brought forward as
subjects of investigation the general conception of a
(one-valued) function of a real variable and the (in
particular, trigonometrical)
On
development of functions.
Cauchy was gradually led to
the
importance of what was subsequently
recognize
more special conception of function of
the
be
to
seen
the other hand,
a complex variable and, to a great extent independ
ently of Cauchy, Weierstrass built up his theory of
;
analytic functions of
complex
variables.
INTRODUCTION
These tendencies of both Cauchy and Dirichlet
combined to influence Riemann his work on the
theory of functions of a complex variable carried on
and greatly developed the work of Cauchy, while
" Habilitationsschrift " of
the intention of his
;
1854
was
to generalize as far as possible Dirichlet s partial
solution of the problem of the development of a
function
of
real
variable
in
trigonometrical
series.
Both these
sides of
impression on
Riemann
Hankel.
In
activity left a
deep
memoir of
1870,
Hankel attempted to exhibit the theory of functions
of a real variable as leading, of necessity, to the
restrictions
and extensions from which we
Riemann s theory
and yet Hankel
start in
of functions of a complex variable
researches entitle him to be called
the founder of the independent theory of functions
At about the same time, Heine
of a real variable.
initiated, under the direct influence of Riemann s
"
Habilitationsschrift," a
new
series of investigations
on trigonometrical series.
Finally, soon after this, we
Georg Cantor
memoir and applying to
find
both studying Hankel s
theorems on the uniqueness of trigonometrical de
velopments those conceptions of his on irrational
"
numbers and the
of point-aggregates
derivatives
number-aggregates which developed from the
rigorous treatment of such fundamental questions
or
given by Weierstrass at Berlin in the introduction to
his lectures on analytic functions.
The theory of
point-aggregates soon became an independent theory
INTRODUCTION
of great importance, and finally, in 1882, Cantor s
" transfinite numbers "
were defined independently
of the aggregates in connexion with which they
appeared
in
first
mathematics.
Ill
The investigations * of the eighteenth century on
the problem of vibrating cords led to a controversy
D Alembert
for the following reasons.
maintained
that the arbitrary functions in his general integral
of the
partial
differential
were
equation to which this
to have certain pro
problem
which
assimilate
them
to the analytically
perties
representable functions then known, and which would
led
restricted
prevent their course being completely arbitrary at
Euler, on the other hand, argued for
every point.
"
the admission of certain of these
arbitrary"
functions
into
produced
analysis.
solution
in
Then
the
Daniel
form
Bernoulli
an
of
infinite
and claimed, on certain
this
solution was as general
that
physical grounds,
As Euler pointed out, this was so
as d Alembert s.
trigonometrical
only
if
able in
*
series,
any arbitrary f function
a series of the form
0(ar)
were develop
my papers in the Archiv der Mathematik
Cf. the references given in
Physik^ 3rd series, vol. x,
1906, pp. 255-256, and Isis vol. i,
Much of this Introduction is taken from my
1914, pp. 670-677.
"
" The
account of
Development of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers
vol.
above-mentioned
the
in
x, pp.
Archiv, 3rd series,
254-281
vol. xiv, 1909, pp. 289-311; vol. xvi, 1910, pp. 21-43; vo1 xxn
~ 21
I 9 l $, PP- l
f The arbitrary functions chiefly considered in this connexion by
This word
Euler were what he called "discontinuous" functions.
und
does not
mean what we now mean
in /sis, vol.
i,
1914, pp. 661-703.
(after
Cauchy) by
it.
Cf.
my
paper
INTRODUCTION
That
is
this was, indeed, the case,
not necessarily developable
even when
in a power-series,
was
first shown by Fourier, who was led to study the
same mathematical problem as the above one by
his researches, the first of which were communicated
to the French
To
of heat.
Academy
Fourier
on the conduction
in 1807,
due also the determination
is
of the coefficients in trigonometric series,
0(#)
in the
+ 1
+#
cos ^r+^ 2 cos 2
x+a
sin
sin
form
+
bv
7T
0(a) cos
=-\
IT)
-
av =
vada,
7T
d>(a) sin vada.
TTj
77
7T
This determination was probably independent of
Euler s prior determination and Lagrange s analog
ous determination of the coefficients of a finite
trigonometrical series.
metrical proof of the
Fourier
also
gave a geo
convergence of his
series,
which, though not formally exact, contained
germ of Dirichlet s proof.
the
To
is
Peter Gustav Lejeune-Dirichlet (1805-1859)
due the first exact treatment of Fourier s series.*
He
expressed the sum of the
series
"
by
a definite integral,
first
n terms of the
and proved that the
Sur
la convergence des series trigonometriques qui servent a
representer une function arbitraire entre des limites donnees,"y<?r.
fur
Math.,
pp.
117-132,
vol.
iv,
1829,
pp.
157-169;
Ges.
IVerke,
vol.
i,
INTRODUCTION
6
limit,
is
when n
increases indefinitely, of this integral
is to be represented by the
the function which
trigonometrical
series,
provided that
the function
These conditions were
somewhat lightened by Lipschitz in 1864.
Thus, Fourier s work led to the contemplation
and exact treatment of certain functions which
satisfies certain conditions.
were totally different in behaviour from algebraic
These last functions were, before him,
functions.
be the type of all functions that
Henceforth it was part of
analysis.
tacitly considered to
can occur
in
the business of analysis to investigate such
non-
algebraoid functions.
In the
few decades of the nineteenth century
first
there grew, up a theory of more special functions of
an imaginary or complex variable.
This theory was
part at least, to Carl Friedrich Gauss
(1777-1855), but he did not publish his results, and
in
known,
so the theory
due to Augustin Louis Cauchy
Cauchy was less far-sighted and
is
(1789-1857).*
than
penetrating
Gauss,
the
theory
developed
slowly, and only gradually were
against
"
"
imaginaries
Cauchy s prejudices
overcome.
Through the
1814 to 1846 we can trace, first, the
strong influence on Cauchy s conceptions of Fourier s
ideas, then the quickly increasing unsusceptibility to
years
from
the ideas of others, coupled with the extraordinarily
Cauchy
prolific nature of this narrow-minded genius.
appeared to take pride in the production of memoirs
*
"
The Theory of Functions with
Cf. Jourdain,
Math. (3), vol. vi, 1905, pp. 190-207.
&ibl.
Cauchy and Gauss,"
INTRODUCTION
weekly meeting of the French Academy, and
was partly, perhaps, due to this circumstance that
his works are of very unequal importance.
Besides
that, he did not seem to perceive even approximately
the immense importance of the theory of functions
of a complex variable which he did so much to
create.
This task remained for Puiseux, Briot and
Bouquet, and others, and was advanced in the
most striking manner by Georg Friedrich Bernhard
at each
it
Riemann (1826-1866).
Riemann may have owed
to his teacher Dirichlet
both towards the theory of potential
which was the chief instrument in his classical
his
bent
development (1851) of the theory of functions of a
complex variable and that of trigonometrical series.
By a memoir on the representability of a function
by a trigonometrical series, which was read in 1854
but only published after his death, he not only laid
the foundations for all modern investigations into the
theory of these series, but inspired Hermann Hankel
(1839-1873) to the method of researches from which
we can date
the theory of functions of a real variable
as an independent science.
The motive of HankePs
research
tions of
variable.
was provided by reflexion on the founda
Riemann s theory of functions of a complex
It was HankePs object to show how the
needs of mathematics compel us to go beyond the
most general conception of a function, which was
implicitly formulated by Dirichlet, to introduce the
complex variable, and finally to reach that con
ception from which Riemann started in his inaugural
INTRODUCTION
For
dissertation.
"
Untersuchungen
this
liber
purpose Hankel began his
die unendlich oft oscilli-
renden und unstetigen Functionen ein Beitrag zur
"
Feststellung des Begriffes der Function iiberhaupt
;
of 1870
by a thorough examination of the various
possibilities contained in Dirichlet s conception.
Riemann, in his memoir of 1854, started
from
the general problem of which Dirichlet had only
solved a particular case
If a function is developable
:
in a trigonometrical series,
what
results
variation of the value of the function (that
what
about the
is
to say,
the most general way in which it can become
discontinuous and have maxima and minima) when
is
the argument varies continuously ?
The argument
a real variable, for Fourier s series, as Fourier had
is
already noticed, may converge for real .r s alone.
This question was not completely answered, and,
perhaps
in
consequence of
in
published
that part of
Riemann
this,
lifetime
the work was not
;
but fortunately
which concerns us more particularly,
and which seems to fill, and more than fill, the place
it
of Dirichlet s contemplated revision of the principles
of the infinitesimal calculus, has the finality obtained
by the giving of the necessary and sufficient condi
tions for the integrability of a function f(x)>
which
was a necessary preliminary to Riemann s investiga
tion.
Thus, Riemann was led to give the process
of integration a far wider meaning than that
contemplated by Cauchy or even Dirichlet, and
Riemann constructed an integrable function which
becomes discontinuous an infinity of times between
INTRODUCTION
any two
limits,
as close together as wished, of the
If,
independent variable, in the following manner
where x is a real variable, (x) denotes the (positive or
:
negative) excess of x over the nearest integer, or
zero if x is midway between two integers, (x) is
a one-valued function of
x with
discontinuities at
the points x= + J, where ^ is an integer (positive,
negative, or zero), and with \ and
\ for upper and
lower limits respectively.
Further, (vx), where
is discontinuous at the
points vx=
v is
an integer,
or ;r=-(/z
where the
+ J).
Consequently, the series
added to ensure convergence
may be supposed to be discon
tinuous for all values of x of the form xp\2n,
where/ is an odd integer, relatively prime to n. It
was this method that was, in a certain respect,
factor
i/j/
is
for all values of x,
generalized
by Hankel
in
In
1870.
Riemann
example appeared an analytical expression and
"
therefore a " function
in Euler s sense
which, on
account of its manifold singularities, allowed of no
such general properties as Riemann
" functions of
a complex variable," and Hankel gave a method,
whose principles were suggested by this example, of
forming analytical expressions with singularities at
He was thus led to state, with
every rational point.
some reserve, that every "function" in Dirichlet s
sense is also a " function" in Euler s
sense.
The
greatest influence on
Georg Cantor seems,
INTRODUCTION
io
not
to
have
been
that
exercised by
Riemann, Hankel, and their successors though
the work of these men is closely connected with
some parts of Cantor s work, but by Weierstrass,
however,
a contemporary of Riemann s,
of the same problems in the
functions of complex variables
who attacked many
theory of analytic
by very
different
and
more rigorous methods.
IV
Karl Weierstrass (1815-1897) has explained, in
on the occasion of his entry
his address delivered
into the Berlin
Academy
in
1857, that, from the
time (the winter of 1839-1840) when, under his
teacher Gudermann, he made his first acquaintance
he was power
"
branch
of
Now,
by
analysis.
was accustomed to take the highest
with the theory of
fully attracted
who
Abel,
elliptic functions,
this
standpoint in any part of mathematics, established
a theorem which comprises all those transcendents
which
arise
entials,
Euler
from the integration of algebraic
and has the same
differ
signification for these as
and
integral has for elliptic functions
in demonstrating the existence of
.
Jacobi succeeded
periodic functions of many arguments, whose funda
mental properties are established in Abel s theorem,
and by means of which the true meaning and real
essence of this theorem could be judged.
Actually
to represent, and to investigate the properties of
these magnitudes of a totally new kind, of which
analysis has jas yet no example, I regarded as one
IN TR OD UCTJON
1 1
of the principal problems of mathematics, and, as
soon as I clearly recognized the meaning and sig
nificance of this problem, resolved to devote myself
to
Of
it.
course
it
would have been
to think of the solution of such a
foolish even
problem without
a thorough study of the
having prepared myself by
means and by busying myself with
less
difficult
problems.
With the ends stated here of Weierstrass
we
now concerned only
are
incidentally
it
work
is
the
"
means the
thorough study of which he spoke
which has had a decisive influence on our subject
in
with the theory of functions.
We will,
his
over
work
which
was
then, pass
early
only
published in 1894 on the theory of analytic
common
functions, his later
work on the same
subject,
and
Abelian functions, and examine
his immensely important work on the foundations
of arithmetic, to which he was led by the needs of
his theory of the
a rigorous theory of analytic functions.
have spoken as if the ultimate aim of Weier
We
work was the investigation of Abelian
But another and more philosophical
functions.
view was expressed in his introduction to a course
of lectures delivered in the summer of 1886 and
" In order to
*
preserved by Gosta Mittag-Leffler
strass
penetrate into mathematical science it is indispens
able that we should occupy ourselves with individual
"Sur
d apres
les
fondements arithmetiques de la theorie des fonctions
Congres des Mathtmatiques a Stockholm
Weierstrass,"
1909, p. io.
INTRODUCTION
12
problems which show us its extent and constitution.
But the final object which we must always keep in
sight is the attainment of a sound judgment on the
foundations of science."
In
Weierstrass began his lectures on the
1859,
theory of analytic functions at the University of
The importance of this, from our present
Berlin.
point of view, lies in the fact that he was naturally
obliged to pay special attention to the systematic
treatment
of
the
theory,
and
consequently,
to
scrutinize its foundations.
In
the
first
Weierstrass
the method
place,
one of the characteristics of
theory of functions is the abolition of
of complex integration of Cauchy and
Gauss which was used by Riemann
and, in a
letter to H. A. Schwarz of October 3,
1875,
;
in a systematic
with
better to dispense
integration,
Weierstrass stated his belief that,
foundation,
as follows
it is
<c
.
The more
meditate upon the principles
of the theory of functions,
and I do this incessantly,
the firmer becomes my conviction that this theory
must be built up on the foundation of algebraic
and therefore that it is not the right way to
proceed conversely and make use of the trans
truths,
cendental (to express myself briefly) for the establish
ment of simple and fundamental algebraic theorems
however attractive may be, for example, the con
siderations by which Riemann discovered so many
of the most important properties of algebraic
functions,
That to the discoverer, qua
discoverer,
INTRODUCTION
permissible, is, of course, self-evident
only thinking of the systematic establishment
every route
I
am
13
is
of the theory.
"
In the second
than
portant
systematic
place,
and what
question of
treatment, ab initio,
the
is
far
more im
the
integration,
of the theory of
analytic functions led Weierstrass to profound in
vestigations in the principles of arithmetic, and the
his theory of
great result of these investigations
irrational
matics
numbers
has a significance for
mathe
and our
all
which can hardly be overrated,
subject may truly be said to be almost
wholly due to this theory and its development by
Cantor.
present
In the theory of analytic functions we often have
to use the theorem that, if we are given an infinity
of points
of the
complex plane
in
any bounded
region of this plane, there is at least one point of
the domain such that there is an infinity of the
given points in each and every neighbourhood round
it and
Mathematicians used to express
including it.
There
by some such rather obscure phrase as
a point near which some of the given points are
this
is
infinitely near to
one another."
If
we
apply, for the
method which seems naturally to
and which consists in successively
proof of this, the
suggest itself,
halving the region or one part of the region which
contains an infinity of points,* we arrive at what is
required,
namely,
the conclusion that there
point such that there
*
This method was
first
is
is
another point in any neigh-
used by Bernard Bolzano in 1817.
INTRODUCTION
t4
bourhood of
"
called
it,
that
is
to say, that there
is
a so-
point of condensation," when, and only
we
have proved that every infinite "sum*
when,
such that the sum of any finite number of its terms
does not exceed some given finite number defines a
The geometrical
(rational or irrational) number.
this
of
analogue
proposition may possibly be claimed
to
be evident
functions
but
if
our ideal in
which had, even
in
the theory of
Weierstrass s time,
been regarded for long as a justified, and even as a
is to found this theory on the
partly attained, ideal
conception of number alone,* this proposition leads to
the considerations out of which a theory of irrational
numbers such
as Weierstrass
on the existence of at
least
s is built.
The theorem
one point of condensa
was proved by Weierstsass by the method of
successive subdivisions, and was specially emphasized
tion
by him.
Weierstrass, in the introduction to his lectures on
analytic functions, emphasized that, when we have
admitted the notion of whole number, arithmetic
needs no further postulate, but can be built up in a
purely logical fashion, and also that the notion of a
*
The separation of analysis from geometry, which appeared in the
work of Lagrange, Gauss, Cauchy, and Bolzano, was a consequence of
the increasing tendency of mathematicians towards logical exactitude
in defining their conceptions and in making their deductions, and, con
and
sequently, in discovering the limits of validity of their conceptions
methods.
However, the true connexion between the founding of
"
arithmetization," as it has been
analysis on a purely arithmetical basis
called
shown
and logical rigour, can only be definitely and convincingly
after the comparatively modern thesis is proved that all the con
cepts (including that of number) of pure mathematics are wholly logical.
And this thesis is one of the most important consequences to which the
theory whose growth we are describing has forced us.
INTRODUCTION
one-to-one correspondence
is
fundamental
15
in
count
But it is in his purely arithmetical introduction
ing.
of irrational numbers that his great divergence from
This appears from a consideration
precedent comes.
of the history of incommensurables.
The ancient Greeks discovered the existence of in
commensurable geometrical magnitudes, and there
fore grew to regard arithmetic and geometry as
sciences of which the analogy had not a logical
This view was also probably due, in part at
basis.
to
an attentive consideration of the famous
least,
arguments of Zeno. Analytical geometry practi
cally identified geometry with arithmetic (or rather
with arithmetica universails}, and, before Weierthe introduction of irrational " number"
strass,
The
was, explicitly or implicitly, geometrical.
view that number has a geometrical basis was taken
by Newton and most of
to
the
nineteenth
his successors.
To come
Cauchy
explicitly
century,
At the beginning of his
adopted the same view.
Cours d analyse of 1821, he defined a " limit" as
follows:
"When
the
successive values
attributed
to a variable
approach a fixed value indefinitely
so as to end by differing from it as little as is
limit of all
wished, this fixed value is called the
"
the others"
and remarked that
thus an irrational
;
number
is
furnish
more and more approximate values of it."
consider as, however, Cauchy does not
If
we
the limit of the various fractions which
appear to have done, although many others have
the latter statement as a definition, so that an
INTRODUCTION
number is defined to be the limit of
sums of rational numbers, we presuppose
that these sums have a limit.
In another place
irrational"
certain
Cauchy remarked, after defining a series & u v
... to be convergent if the sum S n = u + u 1 + u 2
,
^2
+# w _i,
for values of n
always increasing,
approaches indefinitely a certain limit j, that, "by
the above principles, in order that the series
.
u^ u l9
and
sum
s
be convergent, it is necessary
sufficient that increasing values of n make the
z/
2,
may
converge indefinitely towards a fixed limit
sn
necessary and sufficient that,
values
of n, the sums s ny s H+l
great
differ from the limit s, and consequently
in other
words,
it is
for infinitely
s n+ z,
from one another, by infinitely small quantities."
Hence it is necessary and sufficient that the different
sums u n + u n+ i +
when n
+#+
for different
;/z s,
end,
by obtaining numerical values con
from one another by less than any
increases,
stantly differing
assigned number.
If we know that the sums s n have a limit
j,
we
can at once prove the necessity of this condition
but its sufficiency (that is to say, if, for any assigned
positive rational
e,
an integer n can always be found
such that
I
where r
is
any
*-**+
integer,
<
I
>
then a limit
s exists) re
of real
quires a previous definition of the system
is
to
be
limit
the
one.
which
of
supposed
numbers,
For
it
is
evidently a vicious circle to define a real
INTRODUCTION
number
17
as the limit of a
"convergent" series, as
the above definition of what we mean by a "con
"
series
a series which has a limit
in
vergent
volves (unless we limit ourselves to rational limits)
" real
a previous definition of what we mean by a
*
number."
It
we
if
seems, perhaps, evident to "intuition" that,
., for which the
lay off lengths s n s n+ly
,
is fulfilled, on a straight line, that
a (commensurable or incommensurable) "limiting"
length s exists and, on these grounds, we seem to
above condition
be justified in designating Cauchy s theory of real
number as geometrical. But such a geometrical
theory is not logically convincing, and Weierstrass
showed that it is unnecessary, by defining real
numbers in a manner which did not depend on a
process of "going to the limit."
To
we have the following
would-be
arithmetical f prelogical
Weierstrassian introductions of irrational numbers
repeat the point briefly,
error
in
all
we
start
with the conception of the system of
we
rational numbers,
define the
"sum"
(a limit of
a sequence of rational numbers) of an infinite series
of rational numbers, and then raise ourselves to the
conception of the system of real numbers which are
The error lies in overlooking
got by such means.
the fact that the
sum " (b) of the infinite series of
*
On
the attempts of Bolzano, Hankel, and Stolz to prove arithmetic
without an arithmetical theory of real numbers, the sufficiency of
the above criterion, see OstwalcCs Klassiker, No. 153, pp. 42, 95, 107.
t It must be remembered that Cauchy s theory was not one of these.
Cauchy did not attempt to define real numbers arithmetically, but
ally,
simply presupposed their existence on geometrical grounds.
INTRODUCTION
rational numbers can only be defined when we have
already defined the real numbers, of which b is one.
" I
believe," said Cantor,* a propos of Weierstrass s
"that
theory,
avoided
by
this logical
Weierstrass,
error,
escaped
which was
notice
first
almost
and was not noticed on
the ground that it is one of the rare cases in which
actual errors can lead to none of the more important
universally in
earlier times,
mistakes in calculation."
Thus, we must bear in mind that an arithmetical
theory of irrationals has to define irrational numbers
not as "limits"
(whose existence
is
not
always
beyond question) of certain infinite processes, but
in a manner prior to any possible discussion of the
question in what cases these processes define limits
at
all.
With Weierstrass, a number was said to be
"determined" if we know of what elements it is
composed and how many times each element
Considering numbers formed with
the principal unit and an infinity of its aliquot parts,
Weierstrass called any aggregate whose elements
occurs
in
it.
and the number
occurs in
it
f are
(finite)
known
of
times
each
a (determined)
element
" numerical
An aggregate consisting
quantity (Zaklengrosse}.
of a finite number of elements was regarded as equal
to the
sum
finite
number
when
of
elements, and two aggregates of a
of elements were regarded as equal
its
the respective sums of their elements are equal.
Math. Ann.,
It is
vol. xxi, 1883, p. 566.
not implied that the given elements are
finite in
number.
INTRODUCTION
A
19
number r was said to be contained in
numerical quantity a when we can separate from
rational
A numerical
a a partial aggregate equal to r.
if we could
"finite"
to
be
said
a
was
quantity
assign a rational
number
number contained
in
such that every rational
Two
is smaller than R.
were said to be " equal,"
when every rational number contained in a is con
When a and b are not
tained in b and vice versa.
numerical quantities
a, b
equal, there is at least one rational number which
is either contained in a without being contained in
by
or vice versa
in
"greater than" b
"
less than
b.
in
was
the second, a was
the
first
case, a
said to be
said to be
the numerical quantity c de
identical with) the aggregate whose
Weierstrass called
fined
by
(i.e.
elements are those which appear in a or b each of
these elements being taken a number of times equal
y
to the
number
of times
in
which
it
occurs
in
by the number of times in which it occurs
sum" of a and b. The "product" of
a and b was defined to be the numerical quantity
defined by the aggregate whose elements are ob
tained by forming in all possible manners the product
of each element of a and each element of b.
In the
was
defined
the product of any finite
same way
number of numerical quantities.
The "sum" of an infinite number of numerical
was then defined to be the
quantities a, by
aggregate (s) whose elements occur in one (at least)
increased
in b y
the
of
a,y
by
.,
each of these elements
being taken
INTR OD UCTION
20
a
number of times
(n) equal to the number of times
occurs in a, increased by the number of times
that it occurs in b, and so on.
In order that s be
that
it
and determined, it is necessary that each of the
elements which occurs in it occurs a finite number of
finite
and
times,
it
necessary and sufficient that we can
N such that the sum of any finite
is
number
assign a
number of the quantities a, 6, ... is less than N.
Such is the principal point of Weierstrass s theory
of real numbers.
It
should be noticed that, with
numbers were aggregates of
Weierstrass, the new
the numbers previously defined and that this view,
which appears from time to time in the better text
;
books, has the important advantage which was
is
that
first
This advantage
the existence of limits can be proved in
sufficiently
emphasized by Russell.
such a theory.
That is to say, it can be proved by
actual construction that there is a number which is
the limit of a certain series fulfilling the condition
"
When real
of
finiteness "or
convergency.
(
numbers are introduced
either without proper defini
tions, or as "creations of our
far worse,
as
minds,"
this existence
"signs,"*
or,
what
is
cannot be
proved.
If
we
consider
an
infinite
aggregate of
real
numbers, or comparing these numbers for the sake
of picturesqueness with the points of a straight
line, an infinite "point-aggregate," we have the
theorem
There
such that there
*
Cf. Jourdain,
in this domain, at least one point
an infinity of points of the aggre-
is,
is
Math. Gazette 9
]a.n.
1908, vol.
iv,
pp. 201-209.
INTRODUCTION
21
gate in any, arbitrarily small, neighbourhood of it.
Weierstrass s proof was, as we have mentioned,
by the process, named
of successively halving
Bolzano and him,
of the intervals
one
any
which contains an infinity of points.
This process
defines a certain numerical magnitude, the " point
"
of condensation (Hdufungsstelle) in question.
An
after
analogous theorem holds for the two-dimensional
region of complex numbers.
Of
real numerical
than some
less
limit,"
which
is
finite
magnitudes x, all of which are
"
number, there is an
upper
defined as
which
is
such that either certain
certain
(G,
numerical magnitude
x and
G or
equal
within the arbitrarily small interval
the end G being excluded.
Ana
(5),
are
;r s
" lower limit
logously for the
It
to
lie
JT S
.
not surpassed in magnitude by any
is
must be noticed
aggregate of
;r s,
that,
"
g.
if
one of these
we have
is
a finite
the upper limit,
and, if the aggregate is infinite, one of them may
be the upper limit.
In this case it need not also,
but of course may, be a point of condensation.
If
none of them
existence
the upper limit, this limit (whose
proved similarly to the existence of a
is
is
point of condensation, but is, in addition, unique]
a point of condensation.
Thus, in the above
is
explanation of the term "upper limit," we can
"
to "being
replace the words "either certain ;r s
"
excluded"
certain ;r s lie in the
arbitrary small
by
interval (G,
The theory
.,
of the
the end
being included*
and
lower
limit of a
upper
<S),
INTRODUCTION
22
" Dirichlet s
(general or
") real one-valued function
of a real variable was also developed and emphasized
by Weierstrass, and
If
is
especially the theorem
the upper limit of those values of y=f(x}* which
belong to the values of x lying inside the interval
from a to
point x
b,
=X
there
in this interval, at least
is,
such that the
which belong
to
neighbourhood of
lower
the
.r s
is
and analogously
and,
for the
limit.
If the j^-value corresponding to
upper
one
of the
ys
upper
in an arbitrarily small
limit
limit
if
called
is
is
;r=X
"maximum"
is G, the
of the y s
a continuous function of x, the
in other words, a con
a maximum
f(x)
upper limit
the
is
upper and lower limits.
That a continuous function also takes at least once
every value between these limits was proved by
Bolzano (1817) and Cauchy (1821), but the Weierstrassian theory of real numbers first made these
tinuous function attains
its
proofs rigorous,
It is of the utmost importance to realize that,
*j"
whereas until Weierstrass s time such subjects as
the theory of points of condensation of an infinite
aggregate and the theory of irrational numbers,
on which the founding of the theory of functions
*
is finite for every single x of the interval a-^x-^b, all
not be, in absolute amount, less than some finite number
= o, in the interval o<; x-^i),
(for example, f(x)=i/x for x>o, /(o)
but if they are (as in the case of the sum of a uniformly convergent
lower limit in the sense defined.
series), these ys have a finite upper and
t There is another conception (due to Cauchy and P. du BoisReymond), allied to that of upper and lower limit. With every infinite
of condensation,
aggregate, there are (attained) upper and lower points
"
Limites,
which we may call by the Latin name
Even
these
if
/ s need
INTRODUCTION
23
depends, were hardly ever investigated, and never
with such important results, Weierstrass carried
research
into
the principles of arithmetic farther
But we must also
had been carried before.
were questions, such as the nature
of whole number itself, to which he made no valuable
These questions, though logically
contributions.
than
it
realize that there
the first in arithmetic, were, of course, historically
the last to be dealt with.
Before this could happen,
arithmetic had to receive a development, by means
of Cantor s discovery of transfinite numbers, into a
theory of cardinal and ordinal numbers, both finite
and transfinite, and logic had to be sharpened, as
it was by Dedekind,
Frege, Peano and Russell to
a great extent
made
owing to the needs which
this
theory
evident.
V
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor was
Petersburg on 3rd March 1845, an d
born at St
lived there until 1856; from 1856 to 1863 he lived
in South Germany (Wiesbaden, Frankfurt a. M.
and Darmstadt); and, from autumn 1863 to Easter
He became Privatdocent at Halle
1869, in Berlin.
a. S. in 1869, extraordinary Professor in 1872, and
,
ordinary
Professor in
1879.*
When
a student at
Berlin, Cantor came under the influence of Weierstrass s teaching, and one of his first papers on
*
Those memoirs of Cantor s that will be considered here more
and which constitute by far the greater part of his writings,
are contained in Journ. fur Math. vols. Ixxvii and Ixxxiv, 1874 and
1878; KTath. Ann., vol. iv, 1871. vol. v, 1872, vol. xv, 1879, vol. xvii,
particularly,
1880, vol. xx, 1882, vol, xxi, 1883.
INTRODUCTION
24
mathematics was partly occupied with a theory of
irrational numbers, in which a sequence of numbers
satisfying Cauchy s condition of convergence was
used instead of Weierstrass s complex of an infinity
of elements
satisfying a condition which, though
equivalent to the above condition, is less convenient
for purposes of calculation.
This theory was exposed in the course of Cantor s
researches on trigonometrical series.
One of the
problems of the modern theory of trigonometrical
was to establish the uniqueness of a trigono
metrical development.
Cantor s investigations re
lated to the proof of this uniqueness for the most
series
general trigonometrical series, that
whose
series
trigonometrical
is
to say, those
are not
coefficients
necessarily supposed to have the (Fourier s) integral
form.
In a paper of 1870, Cantor proved the theorem
that,
if
a l9 # 2
.,
a vy
and
.-..,.;.
d ly
are two infinite series such that the limit of
a v sin
vx-\-
b v cos vx
every value of x which lies in a given interval
(a<x<b) of the domain of real magnitudes, is zero
with increasing y, both a v and b v converge, with
for
increasing
y,
to
criterion for the
series
zero.
This
theorem leads to a
convergence of a trigonometrical
INTRODUCTION
that
25
Riemann proved under the supposition
of the
In a paper im
integral form for the coefficients.
mediately following this one, Cantor used this
theorem
to prove that there is only one representation
of f(x} in the form of a trigonometrical series con
vergent for every value of x, except, possibly, a
finite
number
of
;r s
if
the sums of two trigono
number of ;r s, the
metrical series differ for a finite
forms of the series coincide.
Cantor gave a simpler proof of the
of
the representation, and extended this
uniqueness
If we have, for every value of ;r, a
theorem to
In
1871,
representation of the value o by a
trigonometrical series, the coefficients of this re
In the same year, he also
presentation are zero.
convergent
gave a simpler proof of
his
first
lim (a v sin vx-\-b v cos vx} = o for
lim a v and lim b v are zero.
In
theorem
a<x<b,
that,
if
then both
November
theorem by
1871, Cantor further extended his
proving that the convergence or equality
sums of trigonometrical series may be re
nounced for certain infinite aggregates of ;r s in the
interval O.
2ir without the theorem ceasing to
of the
hold.
To
describe
have
the
structure
such an
Cantor began
that
case,
aggregate may
with "some explanations, or rather some simple
indications, intended to put in a full light the
different manners in which numerical magnitudes,
in
to
in
this
number finite or infinite, can behave,"
make the exposition of the theorem in
as short as possible.
in
order
question
INTRODUCTION
26
The system
serves as basis
of rational
for arriving
numbers (including o)
at a more extended
notion of numerical magnitude.
ization with which we meet is
infinite
The first general
when we have an
sequence
a ly a 2
(i)
...,*...
of rational numbers, given by some law, and such
if we take the
as
positive rational number
small as we wish, there is an integer n l such that
that,
whatever the positive integer m is. * This property
Cantor expressed by the words, ct the series (i)
has a determined limit b" and remarked particularly
that these
enunciate
words, at that point, only
the
above property of the
served
different
series
because of
the
of the
fact
same
that
"limit"
supposed to be previously defined as
av
such that \b
(if such there be) b
small as
finitely
"
it,
of
Cantor
.,
to
be
may
the
number
becomes
in
it appears better to
with Heine, in his ex
increases,
avoid the word and say,
position
we
#,
However,
species.
the
and,
series,
just as we connect (i) with a special sign
must also attach different signs
",
to
theory,
the
series
(#)
is
number-series," or, as Cantor afterwards expressed
(a v )
is
"fundamental
series."
* It
may be proved that this condition (2) is necessary and sufficient
that the sum to infinity of the series corresponding to the sequence (i)
"
in Weierstrass s sense ; and
finite numerical magnitude
should be a
consequently Cantor s theory of irrational numbers has been described
as a happy modification of Weierstrass s,
INTRODUCTION
27
Let a second series
(O
a\,
<*
<* v
-,
2,
have a determined limit $
>
we
that (i) and
find
(i ) have always one of the three relations, which
exclude one another: (a) a n a n becomes infinitely
small as n increases (b) from a certain n on, it
;
remains always greater than e, where e
and rational (c) from a certain n on,
is
positive
it
remains
always
less
than
In
e.
these
cases
we
say,
respectively,
b
=b
b>b
f
,
or
b<b
Similarly, we find that (i) has only one of the
a
three relations with a rational number a (a) a n
:
becomes
infinitely
small as n increases
(b)
from
a certain n on, it remains always greater than
(Y) from a certain n on, it remains less than
We
e.
express this by
fi
respectively.
= a,
b>a,
or
Then we can prove
<#,
that b
a n becomes
infinitely small as n increases, which, consequently,
of the
justifies the name given to b of "limit
series (i).
"
Denoting the totality of the numerical magnitudes
by B, we can extend the elementary operations
with the rational numbers to the systems A and B
b
united.
Thus the formulae
INTRODUCTION
28
express that the relations
lim (a n
- a" n ) = o,
We
respectively.
- a" n ) = o,
=o
n -a"^
\\m(a n la
hold
lim (a n a
have
similar
definitions
when one or two of the numbers belong to A.
The system A has given rise to B by the same
;
process
B and A
Let the
C.
united give rise to a third system
series
(3)
...,,...
numbers from A
#1,
2,
and B (not all
becomes in
small
as
n
m is (this
whatever
finitely
increases,
condition is determined by the preceding definitions),
then (3) is said to have "a determined limit c."
The definitions of equality, inequality, and the
be composed
of
from A), and such that
b n+m
bn
elementary operations with the members of C, or
with them and those of B and A, are analogous to
Now, whilst B and A are such
we can equate each a to a &, but not inversely,
the above definitions.
that
we can equate each b to a c and inversely.
Although
thus B and C can, in a certain measure, be regarded
*
as identical,
essential in the theory here expose.d, according to which the numerical magnitude,
it
is
not having in general any objectivity at
first,*
only
appears as element of theorems which have a certain
objectivity (for example, of the theory that the
numerical magnitude serves as limit for the corre
sponding series), to maintain the abstract distinction
*
This
is
(see below).
connected with Cantor
formalistic view of real
numbers
INTRODUCTION
29
between B and C, and also that the equivalence of
and b does not mean their identity, but only
expresses a determined relation between the series
to which they refer."
b
L
After considering further systems C, D,
.,
of numerical magnitudes which arise successively,
and B, Cantor dealt
and C from
as B did from
.
with the relations of the numerical magnitudes with
If the
the metrical geometry of the straight line.
a
a
on
has
from
fixed
O
line
distance
point
straight
rational
ratio
with
the
of measure,
unit
it
is
expressed by a numerical magnitude of the system
otherwise, if the point is known by a con
we can always imagine a
and having with the distance
struction,
series such as
(i)
in
question a
relation such that the points of the straight line to
which the distances a ly
a^
.,
av
...
refer
approach, ad infinitum, as v increases, the point to
We express this by saying The
be determined.
:
distance from the point to
point
is
equal to
6,
be
determined to the
where b
is
the numerical
We
can
magnitude corresponding to the series (i).
then prove that the conditions of equivalence,
majority, and minority of known distances agree
with those of the numerical magnitudes which
represent these distances.
It now follows without difficulty that the numerical
are also
.,
magnitudes of the systems C, D,
the
known
of
distances.
But,
determining
capable
to complete the connexion we observe between the
.
systems of numerical magnitudes and the geometry
INTRODUCTION
30
of the straight line, an axiom must still be added,
which runs To each numerical magnitude belongs
:
determined point of the straight
is
equal to this numerical
This theorem is called an axiom, for
also, reciprocally, a
line
whose co-ordinate
magnitude.*
nature
cannot be demonstrated generally.
also serves to give to the numerical magnitudes
a certain objectivity, of which, however, they are
in its
it
It
completely independent.
We consider, now, the relations which present them
when we are given a finite or infinite system of
numerical magnitudes, or "points," as we may call
them by what precedes, with greater convenience.
selves
we
are given a system (P) of points in a finite
interval, and understand by the word "limit-point"
(Grenzpunkf) a point of the straight line (not
If
necessarily of P) such that in any interval within
which this point is contained there is an infinity of
points of P,
we can prove Weierstrass
theorem
if P is infinite, it has at least one limit-point.
Every point of P which is not a limit-point of P
was called by Cantor an "isolated" point.
that,
Every
point, then, of the straight line either
is
or
not a limit-point of P and we have thus defined,
at the same time as P, the system of its limit-points,
which may be called the "first derived system "
is
(erste
finite
Ableitung)
number
of points,
If
is
we can
not composed of a
deduce, by the same
*
To each numerical magnitude belongs a determined point, but to
each point are related as co-ordinates numberless equal numerical
magnitudes.
INTRODUCTION
31
process, a second derived
system P" from F
by
we
of
analogous operations,
"
derived
i/th
system P
(
example, P
whose
O and
composed of
is
from
all
abscissae are rational
and,
arrive at the notion
P.
for
If,
the points of a line
and comprised between
(including these limits or not), P is com
of
all the points of the interval (o
i),
posed
and P
P", ... do not
including these limits
i
If
P.
is
from
differ
of the points
composed
whose
abscissae are respectively
I,
is
1/2, 1/3,
composed of the
does not
rise
give
and
happen
that, after
.,
single point o, and derivation
It may
to any other point.
case
this
...,!/..
alone
P^
interests
here
us
of a finite
composed
operations,
of points, and consequently derivation does
In this case
not give rise to any other system.
v
is
number
the primitive
(Art),"
(y
and thus P
2)th,
P",
... are of the (i/-i)th,
theorem
trigonometrical
is
now
equation
^! cos x-\-
is
" vth
species
species respectively.
The extended
If the
said to be of the
is
satisfied for all values of
x except
those which
correspond to the points of a system P of the i/th
is an integer as great as is pleased,
species, where
j/
in the interval (o
271-),
then
INTRODUCTION
32
Further information as to the continuation of
these researches into derivatives of point-aggregates
was given in the series of papers which Cantor
c<
Ueber unendliche,
"
Although these
papers were written subsequently to Cantor s dis
began
1879 under the
in
title
lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten.
covery (1873)
the conceptions of " enumerability
"
"
power" (Mdchtigkeit\ and
(Abzaklbarkeif) and
these conceptions formed the basis of a classification
of aggregates which, together with the classification
by properties of the derivatives to be described
directly,
was dealt with
by Cantor
own
in these papers, yet, since,
indications,* the discovery even of
derivatives of definitely infinite order was made in
1871, we shall now extract from these papers the
parts concerning derivatives.
point-aggregate P is said to be of the "first
kind" (Gattung) and j/th "species" if P
it
of merely a finite aggregate of points
"
"
be of the
second kind if the series
(l/)
p ,ip"
P(")
>
consists
said to
,...
All the points of P",
points of P while a point of P
point of P.
is infinite.
is
P
is
are always
not necessarily a
",
" dialectic
* In
generation of conceptions,
1880, Cantor wrote of the
which always leads farther and yet remains free from all arbitrariness,
necessary and logical," of the transfinite series of indices of derivatives.
"I arrived at this ten years ago [this was written in May 1880] on
;
exposition of the number-conception, I did not
And in a letter to me of 3ist August 1905, Professor
refer to it."
Was die transfiniten Ordnungszahlen betrifft, ist es
Cantor wrote
mir wahrscheinlich, dass ich schon 1871 eine Vorstellung von ihnen
gehabt habe. Den Begriff der Abzahlbarkeit bildete ich mir erst
the occasion of
:
1873."
my
INTRODUCTION
Some
...
(a
33
of the points of a continuous * interval
the extreme points being considered as
or
all
/3),
belonging to the interval, may be points of P
none are, P is said to be quite outside (a
/3).
.
if
If
(wholly or in part) contained in (a ... /3), a
remarkable case may present itself every interval
in it, however small, may contain points
(5)
(y
is
Then P
of P.
said to be
is
"
every where dense"
For example, (i) the
/3).
are all the points
elements
whose
point-aggregate
of (a ... /5), (2) that of all the points whose
and (3) that of all the
abscissae are rational,
points whose abscissae are rational numbers of the
w where m and n are
form
integers, are
(2/2 -f- i)/2
It
results
from this
in
dense
...
(a
everywhere
/3).
the interval (a ...
in
a point-aggregate is not everywhere dense
there must exist an interval (y
S)
/3),
in
(a ... /3) and in which there is no
comprised
that,
if
in (a
...
of P.
point
in
...
(a
/3),
Further,
not only
if
is
everywhere dense
the same
is
true for
7
,
We
but P consists of all the points of (a ... /3).
might take this property of P as the definition
the
of
(a.
expression:
"P
is
everywhere dense
in
,8)."
is necessarily of the second kind, and
a
hence
point-aggregate of the first kind is every
where dense in no interval. As to the question
Such a P
whether
inversely
every
of
point-aggregate
the
At the beginning of the first paper, Cantor stated: "As we shall
show later, it is on this notion [of derived aggregate] that the simplest
and completest explanation respecting the determination of a continuum
"
rests
(see below).
INTR OD UCTION
34
second kind
everywhere dense
Cantor postponed it.
is
some
in
intervals,
Point-aggregates of the first kind can, as we have
seen, be completely characterized by the notion of
derived aggregate, but for those of the second kind
this notion does not suffice, and it is necessary to
give it an extension which presents itself as it
were of
own accord when we go deeper
its
It
question.
may
into the
here be remarked that Paul du
Bois-Reymond was
led by the study of the general
to
a partly similar development
of
functions
theory
of the theory of aggregates, and an appreciation of
In 1874,
importance in the theory of functions.
he classified functions into divisions, according to
its
the variations of the functions required in the theory
of series and integrals which serve for the repre
He then
sentation of " arbitrary" functions.
considered
An
certain
of
distributions
singularities.
aggregate of points which does not form
a continuous line may be either such that in any
line, however small, such points occur (like the points
infinite
corresponding to the rational numbers), or in any
part, a finite line in which are none of those points
exists.
In the latter case, the points are infinitely
dense on nearing certain points
infinite
finite.
number, all
But also not
in
"for
they are
their distances cannot be
all
if
distances
their
in
an
for, if so, the
arbitrarily small line can vanish
So their distances can be
first case would occur.
;
zero only in points, or, speaking
Here
in infinitely small lines."
more
we
correctly,
distinguish:
INTRODUCTION
35
The points k condense on nearing a finite
number of points k2 (2) the points k2 condense at
a finite number of points
Thus, the
3
(i)
o=
sin
condense near ;r=o, those of
near
/sin \\x
of o = sin \\x
roots
the
preceding
roots,
The
functions with such singularities fill the space
between the " common " functions and the functions
with singularities from
du Bois-Reymond
a
In
line.
Finally,
point to point.
discussed integration over such
note
of
remarked that
he
1879,
criterion for the integrability of a function
not sufficient, for we can also distribute intervals
Dirichlet
is
an everywhere dense fashion (pantachisch) that
we can so distribute intervals D on the
in
to say,
is
interval
TT
+ TT)
that
in
TT
portion, however small, of (
intervals
occur.
Let, now,
Ds
and
by
Ds
interval
which
in the points of
then
<[>(x)
inside
is
TT
TT
+ TT)
^>(.r)
.
connected
any
.
connected
be o
+ TT)
these
not integrable, although any
+ TT) contains lines in
.
"To
continuous (namely, zero).
it. is
in
not covered
distribution of intervals
we
are led
this
when we seek
the points of condensation of infinite order whose ex
istence 1 announced to Professor Cantor years ago."
Consider a series of successive intervals on the
those bounded by the points
in the interval (i/i/
i/i/,
line like
.
.,
i,
.
1/2,
1/3,
i/(j/+ i))
point-aggregate of the first kind and j/th
Now, since each term of the series of
species.
derivatives of P is contained in the preceding ones,
take
and consequently each P
(l/)
arises
from the preceding
INTRODUCTION
36
by the falling away (at most) of points, that
no new points arise, then, if P is of the
second kind, P will be composed of two pointaggregates, Q and R Q consisting of those points
of P which disappear by sufficient progression in
the sequence P P",
and R of the
P<*>, \
p(f-i)
is
to say,
points kept
the above example,
Cantor
zero.
in all the
terms of this sequence.
In
consists of the single point
denoted
by P (oo) and called it
"the derived aggregate of P of order oo (infinity)."
The first derivative of P<> was denoted by p(+D,
and so on for
p(o>+2) ,
p(co+3)
j.
P(oo-M
i
,
(oo)
may have a derivative of infinite order
Again, P
which Cantor denoted by p( 2o
and, continuing
)
conceptual constructions, he arrived at de
rivatives which are quite logically denoted by
these
pO+)
where
he went
still
and n are positive
farther, formed the
integers.
But
of
aggregate
.common
points of all these derivatives, and got a
2
derivative which he denoted p( ), and so on without
Thus he got
end.
(*/-!
+ oo
i>i
-1-
derivatives of indices
...
T- IV,
oo
...
oo
...
oo
CO
" Here we see a dialectic
generation of concep
which
leads
tions,*
always
yet farther, and remains
both free from every arbitrariness and necessary
and
*
logical in itself."
*
I was led to this genera
passage Cantor added the note
note was written in May 1880], but when
exposing my theory of the number-conception I did not refer to it."
To
this
tion ten years ago [the
INTRODUCTION
We
37
that point-aggregates of the first kind
characterized by the property that P (co) has no
.re
see
lements, or, in symbols,
and also the above example shows that a pointaggregate of the second kind need not be every
where dense in any part of an interval.
of his papers of 1882, Cantor extended
"
derivative
and
conceptions
everywhere
In the
the
dense
"
first
to
aggregates
situated in
continua of
dimensions, and also gave some reflexions on the
question as to under what circumstances an (infinite)
These reflexions, though
aggregate is well defined.
important
for
the
purpose
of
emphasizing
the
legitimacy of the process used for defining P (oo)
P (2oo)
are more immediately connected with
.,
,
the conception of "power," and will thus be dealt
with later.
The same applies to the proof that it is
to
remove an everywhere dense aggregate
possible
from a continuum of two or more dimensions in
such a way that any two points can be connected
by continuous circular arcs consisting of the re
maining points, so that a continuous motion may
be
possible
in
discontinuous
space.
To
this
Cantor added a note stating that a purely arith
metical theory of magnitudes was now not only
known to be possible, but also already sketched out
in its
leading features.
must now turn our attention to the develop
of
the conceptions of " enumerability " and
ment
We
INTR OD UCTION
power," which were gradually seen to have a
very close connexion with the theory of derivatives
and the theory, arising from this theory, of the
1
numbers.
1873, Cantor
transfinite
In
from
out
set
the
question
whether the linear continuum (of real numbers)
could be put in a one-one correspondence with the
aggregate of whole numbers, and found the rigorous
This proof, together
proof that this is not the case.
with a proof that the totality of real algebraic
numbers can be put in such a correspondence, and
hence that there exist transcendental numbers in
published
the
of
interval
every
number
which
equation of the form
real
a Qy a ly
n,
algebraic
a Q a l9
.
number
.,
The
common
be called the
a
\
"
height
positive integer correspond a
of
a>
numbers whose height
Thus we can arrange the totality
numbers in a simply infinite series
(0
19
o)
finite
algebraic
av,
and
divisor,
positive whole
+a n = o,
a n are integers, is called a real
n and a positive,
.,
a n to have no
N=n- +
we may suppose
to be irreducible.
may
a root of a non-identical
is
co
a wn + al wn
(4)
where
was
number-continuum,
in 1874.
(4)
number
an
and to each
number of real
is
that
integer.
of real algebraic
by arranging the numbers corresponding
to
the
INTRODUCTION
39
height N in order of magnitude, and then the
various heights in their order of magnitude.
Suppose, now, that the totality of the real
numbers
the
in
interval
(a
where a</3,
/3),
could be arranged in the simply infinite series
(5)
i,
*....,*...
Let a /3 be the two first numbers of (5), different
from one another and from a, /3, and such that
a </3
similarly, let a", /3", where a"</3", be the
y
numbers
different
first
The numbers
a, a",
in
indices increase constantly
numbers
Each of
(a"
/3
(3",
the
/3"),
... of
intervals
.
/3 ),
members
and similarly
...
/3),
We
can then only conceive two cases
number
(a
(l/)
(l/)
.
/3
is
for the
magnitude.
(a
{} ),
those which follow.
all
the
of intervals
and so on.
whose
of (5)
decreasing
(a
includes
(a
are
finite
then, since there
is
either (a)
the last be
let
in this interval at
most one number of (5), we can take in it a number
which does not belong to (5)
or (b) there are
r\
infinitely
many
interval s.
Then, since a a
,
a",
<
increase constantly without increasing ad infinitum,
they have a certain limit a (oo) and similarly /3, /3
,
/3",
limit
decrease
(oo)
.
/3
If
when applying
towards
constantly
"
a (o
= f3
(ca)
certain
(which always happens
method to the system (<o)), we
cannot be in (5).*
easily see that the number ^ =
(oo)
in
< /3 (co \ every number
If, on the contrary, a
this
OD )
ct
rj
For
but that
were, we would have rj = u^, p being a determined index
not possible, for up is not in (^) .
.
009), whilst 7;, by
if it
is
definition,
is.
INTR OD UCTION
40
(03)
or equal to one of
the interval (G^ }
/3
)
ends fulfils the condition of not belonging to (5).
.
its
The property
numbers
to-one
is
or
of the totality of real algebraic
that the system (V) can be put in a one(i, i ^correspondence with the system
and hence results a new proof of Liouville s
(V),
theorem that, in every interval of the real numbers,
there is an infinity of transcendental (non-algebraic)
numbers.
This conception of (i, ^-correspondence between
aggregates was the fundamental idea in a memoir
of 1877, published in 1878, in which some import
ant theorems of this kind of relation between various
made
of a
two well-defined aggregates can be put
into
aggregates were given and suggestions
classification of aggregates on this basis.
If
such a
to
is
say, if,
(i,
^correspondence (that
element to element, they can be made to correspond
i
completely and
of
the same
uniquely),
power
they are
said
to
be
or
to
be
"
(Macktigkeit *)
"
When an aggregate
(aequivalenf).
equivalent
is finite, the notion of power corresponds to that of
number (Anzahl), for two such aggregates have the
same power when, and only when, the number
their elements
is
of
the same.
part (Bestandteil any other aggregate whose
elements are also elements of the original one) of a
finite aggregate has always a power less than that
;
*
The word "power" was borrowed from Steiner, who used it in a
quite special, but allied, sense, to express that two figures can be put,
element for element, in protective correspondence,
INTRODUCTION
not always the
for example, the
of the aggregate itself, but this
case with infinite aggregates,*
series of positive integers
41
is
easily seen to have the
is
same power as that part of it consisting of the even
and hence, from the circumstance that
integers,
an
infinite
aggregate
is
part of
(or
is
equiva
we can only conclude that the
than that of N if we know that
lent to a part of N),
power of M is less
these powers are unequal.
The
series of positive integers has, as is easy to
the
smallest infinite power, but the class of
show,
aggregates with this power
extraordinarily rich
is
and extensive, comprising, for example, Dedekind s
finite corpora," Cantor s "systems of points of
the yth species," all ^-ple series, and the totality of
4
real
Further,
(and also complex) algebraic numbers.
is an aggregate of
easily prove that, if
we can
power, each infinite part of
this first infinite
the
same power
as
M, and
if
M", ...
is
has
a finite
or simply infinite series of aggregates of the first
power, the aggregate resulting from the union of
these aggregates has also the first power.
By the preceding memoir, continuous aggregates
f rst power, but a greater one
and
Cantor proceeded to prove that the analogue, with
a continuum of many
continua, of a multiple series
dimensions has the same power as a continuum of
have not the
*
This curious property of infinite aggregates was first noticed by
Bernard Bolzano, obscurely stated ("
two unequal lengths [may
be said to] contain the same number of points") in a paper of 1864 in
which Augustus De Morgan argued for a proper infinite, and was used
as a definition of "infinite" by Dedekind
(independently of Bolzano
and Cantor) in 1887.
.
INTRODUCTION
42
Thus
one dimension.
appeared that the assump
Riemann, Helmholtz, and others that the
essential characteristic of an n-p\y extended con
it
tion of
tinuous manifold
is
that
elements depend on n
its
continuous, independent variables (co-ordin
ates), in such a way that to each element of the
manifold belongs a definite system of values x^ x^
real,
.,
*i>
xn and
*z>
>
reciprocally to each admissible system
a certain element of the
xn belongs
manifold, tacitly supposes that the correspondence
of the elements and systems of values is a continuous
If we let this supposition drop,f we can prove
one. *
that there is a (i, ^-correspondence between the
elements of the linear continuum and those of a
n-ply extended continuum.
This evidently follows from
the
proof of the
theorem: Let x^ x^
.,xn be real, independent
can
take any value o ^^^ I
of
which
each
variables,
.
then to this system of n variables can be made to
correspond a variable t(p<.t<_\) so that to each
t corresponds one system of
and vice versa.
determined values of x^ x^
., xn
To prove this, we set out from the known theorem
that every irrational number e between o and i can
be represented in one manner by an infinite con
determined value of
tinued fraction which
(a 1? a 2
*
may
,
.,
be written
a,,,
.)
That is to say, an infinitely small variation in position of the element
and reciprocally.
implies an infinitely small variation of the variables,
t In the French translation only of this memoir of Cantor s is added
here: "and this happens very often in the works of these authors
(Riemann aifd Helmholtz)." Cantor had revised this translation.
INTRODUCTION
43
where the
s are positive
There is thus
integers.
a (i, i ^correspondence between the
s and the
various series of a s.
n
Consider, now,
variables,
each of which can take independently all the ir
rational values (and each only once) in the interval
(o
I)
*i==(ai,
i,
= (a
^2
=
^
(a,
2,
these
ai,
2,
l>
Ot2, 2>
i)
a,
irrational
i)th irrational
>
ft,
the relation between a and
(6)
ft
I/
_i) +/x
!/>)>
numbers uniquely determine
number in (o ... i),
<*=(ft> ft>
if
...),...
a-2, vy
2>
,)>
ai,
>
=a M|I ,*
(/x=
I, 2,
.)>
/3
.
..,
|;=I, 2,
.00)
Inversely, such a rt determines
uniquely the series of /3 s and, by (6), the series of
the a s, and hence, again of the e s.
have only
7
established.
is
We
now, that there can exist a (i, ^-corre
spondence between the irrational numbers o < e < i
to show,
and
(irrational and rational) numbers
For this purpose, we remark that all
the rational numbers of this interval can be written
in the form of a simply infinite series
the
real
o<.^<.i.
01)
* If
is
we
0i
arrange the n series of a
means
this
>
</->2>
that
Wj 1}
a
lt
we
2
s in a double series with
are to enumerate the a s in the order 04
o 2f
>
an d that the
*/th
term of
n rows,
-
[f
a.,
this series
frv.
t This
is
as follows
Let pjg be a rational number
lowest terms, and put/ + ^ = N. *To each p\q
done most simply
of this interval in
its
INTR OD UCTION
44
Then
in (o
qv
= V 2/2"), and
i)
we take any
.1)
numbers
irrational
x=
{//,
<
*=
if
we
write a
{A,
oo
$ for
is
equivalent to that of the
c\j b
{h,
*} v
}*
formula
last
^-i,
and
e=
0J,
rj vy
and we can also write the
Now,
of
..., /,... (for example,
h take any of the values of
s and j/s, so that
q ly q 2
let
except the
series
infinite
mv}-
the aggregate of the a s
s," and notice that a(\>a,
b c\j c imply a c\)
c,
and that two aggre
gates of equivalent aggregates of elements, where the
elements of each latter aggregate have, two by two,
no
common
element, are equivalent,
h 00
t] v
/Z,
00 ^-1, $ v
we remark
that
02v,
and
generalization of the above theorem to the case
xv
of x^ x.i,
being a simply infinite series
.
(and thus that the continuum may be of an infinity
of dimensions while remaining of the same power
as the linear continuum) results from the observa
tion that,
^ = (a Ml i,
between the double
cv,
<V,
,,)
series
for
{c^,
},
M =i,
2,
where
.
.00
belongs a determined positive integral value of N, and to each such
belong a finite number of fractions pjq. Imagine now the numbers//^
precede
arranged so that those which belong to smaller values of
those which belong to larger ones, and those for which N has the same
the
after
the
smaller.
value are arranged
greater
* This notation means
the aggregate of the ^r s is the union of those
s
and analogously for that of the s.
and
of the ^ s, 7/y s,
;
v
<?
INTRODUCTION
45
and the simple series {/3 X }, a (i, ^-correspondence
can be established * by putting
and the function on the right has the remarkable
property of representing all the positive integers,
and v inde
and each of them once only, when
pendently take all positive integer values.
/m.
"And now
we have proved," concluded
that
Cantor, "for a very rich and extensive
field
of
manifolds, the property of being capable of corre
spondence with the points of a continuous straight
line or
with a part of
tained
in
the
it),
many and what
the
same or
it
(a manifold of points
arises
question
classes
different
we say
(if
Into
con
how
that manifolds of
power are grouped in the same
do linear manifolds
or different classes respectively)
a process of induction, into the further
description of which we will not enter here, we are
fall ?
By
led to the
theorem that the number of classes
is
two
the one containing all manifolds susceptible of being
brought to the form functio ipsius y, where v can
and the other
receive all positive integral values
:
manifolds reducible to the form functio
containing
ipsius x, where x can take all the real values in the
all
interval (o
i)."
In the paper of 1879 already referred to, Cantor
*
Enumerate the double
series
{ a/Xi v }
diagonally, that
is
to say,
in the order
a l,
The term
of
this
a l,
series
2, 1
a
l,
3>
whose index
2, Ji
is
a 3,
(/j.,
y)
is
the
\th,
where
INTR OD UCTION
46
of aggregates * both
according to the properties of their derivatives and
After some repetitions,
according to their powers.
considered
the classification
a rather simpler proof of the theorem that the con
tinuum is not of the first power was given.
But,
though no essentially new results on power were
published until late in 1882, we must refer to the
discussion (1882) of what is meant by a " welldefined
"
aggregate.
The conception
of power f which contains, as a
particular case, the notion of whole number may,
said Cantor, be considered as an attribute of every
" well-defined
nature
its
"
aggregate, whatever conceivable
" An
elements may have.
aggregate of
elements belonging to any sphere of thought is said
to be
well defined when, in consequence of its
definition and of the logical principle of the excluded
it must be considered as intrinsically deter
mined whether any object belonging to this sphere
middle,
to
belongs
the
aggregate or not, and, secondly,
whether two objects belonging to the aggregate
are
in
equal or not, in spite of formal differences
In fact,
the manner in which they are given.
we
cannot, in general, effect in a sure and
manner these determinations with the means
disposal
but here
it is
precise
at our
only a question of intrinsic
determination, from which an actual or extrinsic
*
Linear aggregates alone were considered, since all the powers of
the continua of various dimensions are to be found in them.
t "That foundation of the theory of magnitudes which we may
consider to be the most general genuine moment in the case of
manifolds."
INTRODUCTION
determination
47
by perfecting the
can, without any
to be developed
is
Thus, we
be intrinsically determined
whether a number chosen at will is algebraic or
means."
auxiliary
conceive
doubt,
it
to
was only proved in 1874 that e is
transcendental, and the problem with regard to TT
was unsolved when Cantor wrote in 1882.*
In this paper was first used the word "enumer
"
able to describe an aggregate which could be put
not; and yet
in
it
^-correspondence with the aggregate of
(i,
the positive integers and is consequently of the first
and here also was the important
(infinite) power
;
theorem In a /^-dimensional space (A) are defined
an infinity of (arbitrarily small) continua of n
dimensions f (a) separated from one another and
:
most meeting
the a
s is
For
at their boundaries
the aggregate of
enumerable.
refer
by means of reciprocal
radii vectores
an n-p\y extended figure B within a (;z-f-i)dimensional infinite space A and let the points of
to
B have
of
part b
the constant distance
To every
of B with a
from a fixed point
a corresponds
^-dimensional
and the
definite content,
are
enumerable, for the number of b s greater in con
tent than an arbitrarily small number y is finite, for
their
sum
less
is
than 2
VJ
(the content of B).
Lindemann afterwards proved that tr is transcendental. In this
passage, Cantor seemed to agree with Dedekind.
t With every a the points of its boundary are considered as belong
ing to it.
+ In the French translation (1883) of Cantor
was corrected to 2ir(n +
When n
i)/2/r((+
the theorem
is
memoir,
this
number
i)/2).
that every aggregate of intervals on a
INTR OD UCTION
48
if
Finally, Cantor made the interesting remark that,
we remove from an ^-dimensional continuum any
enumerable and everywhere-dense aggregate, the
remainder (21), if n^2, does not cease to be con*
connected, in the sense that any two
of 21 can be connected by a continuous
tinuously
points N,
line
composed of
belong to
circular arcs all of
whose points
21.
VI
An
bility
application of Cantor
conception of enumera-
was given by a simpler method of condensation
of singularities, the construction of functions having
a given singularity, such as a discontinuity, at an
enumerable and everywhere-dense aggregate in a
This was suggested by Weierand published by Cantor, with Weierstrass s
given real interval.
strass,
in
examples,
indicated
single
1882.*
Let
</>(#)
The method may be thus
be a given function with the
and
singularity ;tr=o,
aggregate
where the
(ov)
any enumerable
put
cv s
are so chosen that the series and
those derived from
it
in the particular cases treated
and
converge unconditionally
uniformly.
Then
or infinite) straight line which at most meet at their ends is
The end-points are consequently enumerable, but not
always the derivative of this aggregate of end-points.
* In a letter to me of
29th March 1 905 Professor Cantor said : "At the
at
conception of enumerability, of which he [ Weierstrass] heard from me
Berlin in the Christmas holidays of 1873, ne was at fi rst quite amazed,
(finite
enumerable.
it became his own and
helped him
wonderful theory of functions."
but one or two days passed over, [and]
to
an unexpected development of
his
INTRODUCTION
f(x) has at
larity as
all
<f)(x)
49
points ^=0^ the same kind of singu
at.r = o, and at other points behaves,
The singularity at x ^^ is
regularly.
exclusively to the one term of the series in
in general,
due
which
/m
the aggregate (&))
may
be any enumer
able aggregate and not only, as in Hankel s method,
the aggregate of the rational numbers, and the
superfluous and complicating oscillations produced
by the occurrence of the sine in Hankel s functions
is
avoided.
" LJeber
"
unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten con
tained six theorems on enumerable point-aggregates.
If an aggregate Q (in a continuum of n dimensions)
The
is
fourth (1882) of Cantor
such that none of
its
points
is
papers
a limit-point,*
it is
Then, round every point of
O a sphere can be drawn which contains no other
point of O, and hence, by the above theorem on
said to be "isolated."
the enumerability of the aggregate of these spheres,
is
enumerable.
Secondly,
if
is
3)(P,
then
is
isolated
enumerable, P
and therefore enumerable, and R
R is contained in P so
also enumerable, since
is
three theorems state
Cantor expressed
Number,
If
enumerable.
The next
let
P>R, P-R^Q;t
is
For
is.
this
2)(Q,
Q = o.
)
Cf.
if
Dedekind
P^, or
Essays on
p. 48.
an aggregate B is contained in A, and
is taken from A, we write
when B
that,
is
the aggregate
left
INTRODUCTION
So
p(
a)
j
where a
is
any one of the "definitely defined
symbols of infinity (bestimmt
is
keitssymbole)"
If the aggregates P 1? P 2
common
no
point, for the
Unendlich-
definirte
enumerable, then P
.
is.
have, two by two,
aggregate P formed by
the union of these (the " Vereinigungsmenge") Cantor
now used the notation
Now, we have the following
and
identity
thus, since
_P" p"_p"
p("-i)__ p(0
is
and therefore enumerable, if P
enumerable, then P is also.
Now, suppose that P (oo) exists then, if any par
ticular point of P does not belong to P (co) there is a
first one among the derivatives of finite order, P
to which it does not belong, and consequently P^- 1
are
isolated
all
(l/)
(l/)
contains
it
as an isolated point.
Thus we can write
and consequently, since an enumerable aggregate of
enumerable aggregates is an enumerable aggregate
of the elements of the latter, and P (oo) is enumerable,
This can evidently be extended to
then P is also.
x
P (a)
if it
exists, provided that the aggregate of all
x
the derivatives from P to P (a)
The
considerations
which
is
enumerable.
arise
from
the
last
INTRODUCTION
51
observation appear to me to have constituted the
reason for considering these definitely infinite
final
indices independently *
on account of their con
nexion with the conception of " power," which
Cantor had always regarded as the most funda
mental one in the whole theory of aggregates.
The
series
to
up
that,
of the indices found, namely, is such
any point (infinity or beyond), the
aggregate of them
always enumerable, and yet
a process exactly analogous to that used in the
proof that the continuum is not enumerable leads
is
to the result that the aggregate of all the indices
if a is any index, the aggregate of all the
such that,
indices preceding a
but
is
as
enumerable,
the
is
not
enumer
of the series of
just
power
positive integers is the next higher one to all finite
ones, the next greater infinite power to the first.
able,
And we
first
is,
can again imagine a new index which
is
the
after all those defined, just as after all the finite
ones.
We
Cantor
at the
shall see these
thoughts published by
end of 1882.
It remains to mention the sixth theorem,
in
which Cantor proved that, if P is enumerable, P
has the property, which is essential in the theory
of integration, of being "discrete," as Harnack
"
called it,
integrable," as P. du Bois-Reymond did,
"
unextended,"
" content-less."
*
or,
as
it
is
now
generally called,
When considered independently of P, these indices form a series
beginning with the finite numbers, but extending beyond them ; so
that it suggests itself that those other indices be considered as infinite
(or transimite) numbers.
INTRODUCTION
52
VII
We
have thus seen the importance of Cantor
"
defined
definitely
theorem that
by what precedes, be inverted
is
the
in
infinity"
symbols
P (a) vanishes, P and therefore P, is
This theorem may, as we can easily
if
enumerable.
see
of
enumerable, there
is
as follows
If
an index a such that P (a)
defining these indices in an inde
manner
as real, and in general transfinite,
pendent
was enabled to form a conception
Cantor
integers,
*
of the enumeral
of certain infinite
vanishes.
By
series,
(Anzahl)
and such
series
infinite
ascending
means
of defining a series of
"powers." The conceptions of
gave a
"enumeral" and "power" coincided
in
the case of
aggregates, but diverged in the case of infinite
aggregates but this extension of the conception of
finite
enumeral served, in the way just mentioned, to
develop and make precise the conception of power
used often already.
Thus, from the new point of view gained, we get
new
insight
Cantor put
has
in finito,
splits, in
it
as
into the theory of finite number
"The conception of number which,
;
manner
when we
of speaking,
into the
and enumeral
descend to the
finite,
see
raise our
two conceptions of
selves to the infinite,
power
of enumeral,
only the background
and,
just
when
as
again
clearly
and
beautifully how these two conceptions again unite
to form that of the finite integer."
* I
have invented this woid to translate
with the word " number" (Zahl).
"
Anzahl,"
to avoid confusion
INTRODUCTION
The
of
all
Cantor
53
significance of this distinction for the theory
and
(finite
s
arithmetic
infinite)
own work
and, above
all,
appears in
the later
in
work of Russell.
Without this extension of the conception of
number to the definitely infinite numbers, said
Cantor, "it would hardly be possible for me to
make without constraint the least step forwards in
the theory of aggregates," and, although "I was
them
[these numbers] many years ago,
without arriving at a clear consciousness that 1
possessed in them concrete numbers of real signi
led
to
{<
ficance," yet
my
will,
was
because
logically forced, almost against
in opposition to traditions
had become valued by me in the course of
researches extending over many years,
which
scientific
to
the
of
the
not
considering
infinitely great,
form of the unlimitedly increasing,
and in the form, closely connected with this, of
thought
merely
in the
convergent
infinite series,
matically by numbers
completed
infinite.
but also to
in
I
the
do not
be
it
it
mathe
form of a
then, that
believe,
any reasons can be urged against
"
unable to combat.
The
fix
definite
which
am
indices of the series of the derivatives can
conceived
as
the
series
of
finite
numbers
followed by a series of transfinite
i, 2,
numbers of which the first had been denoted by the
,
symbol "OQ."
Thus, although there
is
no greatest
*
of the translations of Cantor
Cf., for example, pp. 113, 158-159
memoirs of 1895 and 1897 given below.
INTRODUCTION
54
finite
number,
that there
tradiction,
or,
in other
words, the supposition
a greatest finite number leads to con
there is no contradiction involved in
is
postulating a new, non-finite, number which is to be
the first after all the finite numbers.
This is the
method adopted by Cantor
* to define his
numbers
independently of the theory of derivatives we shall
see how Cantor met any possible objections to this
;
system of postulation.
Let us now briefly consider again the meaning of
"
the- \vord
Mannichfaltigkeitslehre" j- which is
In a
usually translated as "theory of aggregates."
note to the Gtundlagen^ Cantor remarked that he
meant by
this
word
much, which hitherto
only
in
the
special
a doctrine embracing very
have attempted to develop
form
of
an
arithmetical
or
of
geometrical theory
aggregates (Mengenlehre),
By a manifold or aggregate I understand generally
any multiplicity which can be thought of
(jedes Viele, welches sick als
Bines denken
as
one
lasst}, that
any totality of definite elements which
can be bound up into a whole by means of a law."
is
to say,
* "
Ueber unendliche, lineare
V."
Punktmannichfaltigkeiten.
[December 1882], Math. Ann., vol. xxi, 1883, pp. 545-591 ; reprinted,
einer
with an added preface, with the title
Grundlagen
allgemeinen
:
Ein mathematisch-philosophischer Versuch in
Mannichfaltigkeitslehre.
der Lfhre des Unendlichen, Leipzig, 1883 (page n of the Grundlagen is
page n + 544 of the article in the Math. Ann.}. This separate publica
tion, with a title corresponding more nearly to its contents, was made
" since it carries the
subject in many respects much farther and thus is,
"
for the most part, independent of the earlier essays
In
(Preface).
Acta Math., ii, pp. 381-408, part of the Grundlagen was translated
into French.
"
f Or
"Mannigfalligkeitslehre"
theorie des ensembles.
French,
has not come into general usage.
more
"
"
in
usually,
Mcngenlchre
The English " theory of manifolds
or,
"
INTRODUCTION
55
This character of unity was repeatedly emphasized
by Cantor, as we shall see later.
The above quotations about the slow and sure
way in which the transfinite numbers forced them
selves on the mind of Cantor and about Cantor s
philosophical and mathematical traditions are taken
Both here and in Cantor s
from the Grundlagen.
later works we constantly come across discussions
of opinions on infinity held by mathematicians and
philosophers of all times, and besides such names as
Aristotle,
Descartes,
Spinoza,
Hobbes, Berkeley,
Locke, Leibniz, Bolzano, and many others, we find
evidence of deep erudition and painstaking search
after
new views on
infinity to analyze.
devoted
many pages
Fathers of the Church.
to
the
Cantor has
Schoolmen and the
The Grundlagen begins by drawing a distinction
between two meanings which the word "infinity"
The mathematical
may have in mathematics.
infinite, says Cantor, appears in two forms
Firstly,
:
as an
improper
infinite (Uneigentlich-Unendliches}^
a magnitude which either increases above all limits
or decreases to an arbitrary smallness, but always
remains finite so that it may be called a variable
;
finite.
Secondly,
as
(Eigentlich-Unendliches),
a proper infinite
represented
by certain
definite,
geometry, and, in the theory of
the
by
point infinity of the complex plane.
In the last case we have a single, definite point,
conceptions
in
functions,
and the behaviour of (analytic) functions about this
point is examined in exactly the same way as it is
INTRODUCTION
56
about any
other point.*
Cantor s infinite real
integers are also properly infinite, and, to emphasize
" oo which was and is used also
this, the old symbol
,"
for the
To
improper
define his
was here replaced by " co. "
new numbers, Cantor employed the
infinite,
The
following considerations.
series of
the real
positive integers,
(I)
i,
2,
3,
.,
,.
.,
from the repeated positing and uniting of
units which are presupposed and regarded as equal
the number v is the expression both for a definite
arises
finite enumeral of such successive positings and for
the uniting of the posited units into a whole.
Thus
the formation of the finite real integers rests on the
principle of the addition of a unit to a number
which has already been formed
Cantor called
this
moment
the first principle of generation (ErzeugungsThe enumeral of the number of the class
princip}.
is infinite, and there is no greatest
so
formed
(I)
among them.
Thus, although
it
would be contra
dictory to speak of a greatest number of the class (I),
there is, on the other hand, nothing objectionable
in imagining a new number, o>, which is to express
that the whole collection (I) is given
its natural order of succession (in the
v is
by its law
same way
in
as
the expression that a certain finite enumeral of
is united to a whole), f
By allowing further
units
*
"The
behaviour of the function in the neighbourhood of the
shows exactly the same occurrences as in that
of any other point lying infinite, so that hence it is completely justified
to think of the infinite, in this case, as situated in a point."
" It is even
t
permissible to think of the newly and created number
infinitely distant point
INTRODUCTION
positings of unity to
number o>, we obtain
the
follow
ft)
positing
of the
with the help of the
principle of generation the further
0)+I,
57
+2,
...,
ft>
numbers
+ y,
first
...
Since again here we
come to no greatest number, we
a
new
which
we may call 2co, and which
one,
imagine
is to be the first which follows all the numbers v and
to
+ v hitherto formed.
2ft)
The
2co
.,
principle re
to the numbers
first
which has given us the
obviously different from the
function
and
o>
we come
2co,
2ft>+2,
I,
logical
numbers
Applying the
number
peatedly to the
is
2co
principle; Cantor called
it the second
principle
of
real
of generation
integers, and defined it more
If there is defined any definite
closely as follows
first
succession of real integers, of which there is no
greatest, on the basis of this second principle a new
number is created, which is defined as the next greater
number to them all.
By the combined application of both principles
we get, successively, the numbers
:
3ft),
o>
3ft)
as the limit to
v,
that
is
i/,
/Zft),
yUft)
V,
which the numbers
understood than that
numbers
3ft)
o> is
to
to say, is
v strive, if by that nothing else is
be the first integer which follows all the
to be called greater than
every /." Cf.
the next section.
If we do not know the reasons in the
theory of derivatives which
prompted the introduction of w, but only the grounds stated in the text
for this introduction, it naturally seems rather
arbitrary (not apparently,
because of the mere fact that it can apparently be
useful) to create
defined in a manner free from contradiction.
Thus, Cantor discussed
(see below) such introductions or creations, found in them the dis
tinguishing mark of pure mathematics, and justified them on historical
grounds (on logical grounds they perhaps seem to need no
justification).
INTRODUCTION
58
number jnuo + v
new next number to all
and, since no
a
denoted by
numbers
o>
To
2
.
this
we
greatest,
these,
follow,
which
in
create
be
may
succession,
Aft)
and
is
we come
further,
to
JULO)
V,
numbers of the form
and the second principle then requires a new number,
which may conveniently be denoted by
And
so on indefinitely.
Now,
the
all
power of the first number-class (I).
numbers preceding co" are contained
where
that
difficulty
the numbers preceding any of the
numbers and hitherto defined is of the
aggregate of
infinite
without
seen
is
it
/m y
VQ)
j/
1?
v^
Thus, all the
formula
in the
have to take
positive, integral values including zero
all
finite,
and exclud
= 0. As is
ing the combination v = v^
=1/^
well known, this aggregate can be brought into the
form of a simply infinite series, and has, therefore,
.
the power of
(itself of the
which has the
Since,
(I).
first
first
further,
every sequence
power) of aggregates, each of
power, gives an aggregate of the
we
obtain, by the con
tinuation of our sequence in the above way, only
first
power,
it
is
clear that
such numbers with which this condition
is fulfilled,
INTRODUCTION
59
Cantor defined the totality of all the numbers a
formed by the help of the two principles
w,
(II)
+i,
.,
i/oft^
+ iy^-H
+iv_i
w+1
>,
the numbers, from i on, preceding a
form an aggregate of the power of the first number-
such that
all
class (I), as the
"second number-class
The
(II)."
power of (II) is different from that of (I), and is,
indeed, the next higher power, so that no other
power
lies
principle
between them.
demands the
which follows
first
all
Accordingly, the second
creation of a
the
numbers of
new number
(II)
and
is
(i~2)
the
of the third number-class (III), and so on.*
in spite of first appearances, a certain
Thus,
completion can be given to the successive formation
of the
numbers of
limitation
the
first
(II)
present with
principle,
and
which
(I).
so
is
similar to
that
There we only used
was impossible to
it
emerge from the series (I) but the second principle
must lead not only over (II), but show itself indeed
;
as
a means, which,
in
combination with the
first
principle, gives the capacity to break through every
The abovelimit in the formation of real integers.
mentioned requirement, that all the numbers to
be next formed should be such that the aggregate
*
It is particularly to be noticed that the second principle will lake
us beyond any class, and is not merely adequate to form numbers which
are the limit-numbers of some enumerable series (so that a "third
The first and second principles
principle" is required to form H).
together form all the numbers considered, while the "principle of
"
limitation
enables us to define the various number-classes, of un-
brokenly ascending powers in the series of these numbers.
INTRODUCTION
60
numbers preceding each one should be of a certain
power, was called by Cantor the third or limitation-
of
(Hemmungs- oder Beschrankungsprincip},*
in such a manner that the class (II)
with its aid can be shown to have a higher
principle
and which acts
defined
power than
(I)
and indeed the next higher power to
two first principles together define
In fact, the
it.
sequence of integers, while the
third principle lays successively certain limits on
an absolutely
infinite
this process,
so that
we
obtain
natural
segments
(Abschnitte), called number-classes, in this sequence.
Cantor
older
(1873,
1878)
conception of the
"
power of an aggregate was, by this, developed
With finite aggregates the
and given precision.
with
the
enumeral of the elements,
coincides
power
for such aggregates have the same enumeral of
elements
in
every order.
on the other hand, the
With
infinite aggregates,
transfinite
numbers
afford a
means of defining the enumeral of an aggregate, if
it be "well ordered," and the enumeral of such an
aggregate of given power varies, in general, with
The smallest
the order given to the elements.
evidently that of (I), and, now for
the successive higher powers also
in fact, the
receive natural and simple definitions
infinite
the
power
first
is
time,
power of the yth number
By
*
"This
class
is
the yth.
"well-ordered" aggregate, f Cantor underprinciple
(or
requirement,
or
condition)
circumscribes
each number-class."
f The origin of this conception can easily be seen to be the denning
of such aggregates as can be "enumerated" (using the word in the
In
wider sense of Cantor, given below) by the transfinite numbers.
of a well-ordered aggregate simply indicates
fact, the above definition
(limits]
INTRODUCTION
61
any well-defined aggregate whose elements
stood
have a given definite succession such that there is
a first element, a definite element follows every one
is
(if it
not the
and to any
last),
finite or
infinite
aggregate a definite element belongs which is the
next following element in the succession to them
(unless there are no following elements in the
all
Two
well-ordered aggregates are, now,
of the same enumeral (with reference to the orders
succession).
of succession of their elements previously given for
them) if a one-to-one correspondence is possible
between them such that, if E and F are any two
elements of the one, and E p.id F the
corresponding elements (caweqccfifly different) of
different
the
other,
if
respectively precedes or
correspondence
possible at
is
is
all,
or
precedes
follows
follows
preceding numbers (from
The
number
a such that
on) in the natural
enumeral of both well-ordered aggregates,
infinite, or a
is
This ordinal
same enumeral, we must put a
succession have the
for the
then
evidently quite determinate, if it
and since there is, in the extended
number-series, one and only one
its
F,
if
if
is finite.
essential difference
between
finite
and
infinite
aggregates is, now, seen to be that a finite aggregate
has the same enumeral whatever the succession of
the construction of any aggregate of the class required when the first
two principles are used, but to generate elements, not numbers.
An important property of a well-ordered aggregate, indeed, a
characteristic property,
is that any series of terms in it, a^
a2
.,
av
must be finite. Even if the well., where a v +i precedes av
,
ordered aggregate in question
can never be infinite.
is infinite,
such a series as that described
INTRODUCTION
62
the elements
may
be, but
in general, different
an
infinite
aggregate has,
enumerals under these circum
However, there is a certain connexion
between enumeral and power an attribute of the
aggregate which is independent of the order of the
elements.
Thus, the enumeral of any well-ordered
stances.
aggregate of the first power is a definite number of
the second class, and every aggregate of the first
power can always be put in such an order that its
enumeral is any prescribed number of the second
Cantor expressed this by extending the
class.
meaning of the word "enumerable" and saying:
Every aggregate of the power of the first class is
enumerable by tru-^-b^rs of the second class and only
by these, and the aggregate can abyvs be so
ordered that it is enumerated by any prescribed
number of the second class and analogously for
;
the higher classes.
From
his
above remarks on the
"absolute"*
* Cantor said
"that, in the successive formation of number-classes,
we can always go farther, and never reach a limit that cannot be sur
so that we never reach an even approximate comprehension
passed,
The Absolute can
I cannot doubt.
(Erfassen) of the Absolute,
only be recognized (anerkannt), but never apprehended (erkannt),
even approximately. For just as inside the first number-class, at any
finite number, however great, we always have the same
power of
greater finite numbers before us, there follows any transfinite number
of any one of the higher number-classes an aggregate of numbers and
classes which has not in the least lost in power in comparison with the
whole absolutely infinite aggregate of numbers, from I on. The state
ich zieh
of things is like that described by Albrecht von Haller
sie ab [die ungeheure Zahl] und Du [die Ewigkeit] liegst ganz vor mir.
The absolutely infinite sequence of numbers thus seems to me to be, in
a certain sense, a suitable symbol of the Absolute ; whereas the infinity
of (I), which has hitherto served for that purpose, appears to me, just
because I hold it to be an idea (not presentation) that can be appre
hended as a vanishing nothing in comparison with the former. It also
seems to me remarkable that every number-class and therefore every
:
INTRODUCTION
63
numbers and that of
be expected that Cantor would
infinity of the series of ordinal
powers,
it
was
to
derive the idea that any aggregate could be arranged
in a well-ordered series, and this he stated with a
promise to return to the subject later.*
The
addition and multiplication of the transfinite
(including the finite) numbers was thus defined by
and M x be well-ordered aggregates
and /3, the aggregate which arises
when first M is posited and then M x following it,
and the two are united is denoted M + M l and its
enumeral is defined to be a + /3.
Evidently, if a
and /3 are not both finite, a + /3 is, in general,
different from /3 + a.
It is easy to extend the con
Cantor.
Let
of enumerals a
sum to
summands in a
cept of
a finite or transfinite aggregate of
definite order, and the associative
law remains valid.
Thus,
in particular,
If we take a succession (of enumeral /3) of equal
and similarly ordered aggregates, of which each is
of enumeral a we get a new well-ordered aggregate,
whose enumeral is defined to be the product /3a,
,
corresponds to a definite number of the absolutely infinite
indeed reciprocally, so that corresponding to
7 there is a (7th) power so that the various
powers also form an absolutely infinite sequence. This is so much the
more remarkable as the number 7 which gives the rank of a power
(provided that 7 has an immediate predecessor) stands, to the numbers
of that number-class which has this power, in a magnitude-relation
whose smallness mocks all description, and this the more 7 is taken to
be greater."
* With this is
connected the promise to prove later that the power of
the continuum is that of (II), as stated, of course in other words, in 1878.
See the Notes at the end of this book.
power
totality of numbers, and
any transfinite number
INTRODUCTION
64
where /3 is the multiplier and a the multiplicand.
Here also ($a is, in general, different from a/3 but
;
we
"
have, in general,
Cantor also promised an investigation of the
"
prime number-property of some of the transfinite
numbers * a proof of the non-existence of infinitely
small numbers, f and a proof that his previous
theorem on a point-aggregate P in an ^-dimensional
domain that, if the derivate P (a) where a is any
integer of (I) or (II), vanishes, P and hence P, is
of the first power, can be thus inverted
If P is
such a point-aggregate that P is of the first power,
there is an integer a of (1) or (II) such that P (a) = o,
This last
and there is a smallest of such a s.
of
the
transfinite
theorem shows the importance
numbers in the theory of point-aggregates.
,
Cantor s proof that the power of (II) is different
from that of (I) is analogous to his proof of the
Suppose that
non-enumerability of the continuum.
we could put (II) in the form of a simple series
:
(7)
we
a ly a 2
>
av
number which has the
shall define a
properties
both of belonging to (II) and of not being a member
of the series (7) and, since these properties are
contradictory of one another if the hypothesis be
;
granted,
*
we must conclude
A
The property in question is:
the resolution a = Py is only possible
t See the next section.
that (II) cannot be put
"prime-number"
when = I or = a.
is
such that
INTRODUCTION
form
in the
and therefore has not the power of
be the first number of (i) which is
(7),
Let a K
(I).
greater than a x
so on
65
so that
a* the first greater
than a
and
we have
and
and
/
aK
Now
it
on,
all
< a*.A
may happen
following
it
if v
that,
< KAfrom a certain number
in the series (7) are smaller
If, on
evidently the greatest.
the other hand, there is no such greatest number,
imagine the series of integers from i on and smaller
than
it
then
it
is
than a l9 add to it the series of integers
>a K then the series of integers ^a* and
,
so on
we
numbers of
thus get a
and
definite
which
part
^ ai
<a K
>
and
and
of successive
evidently of the
first power, and consequently, by the definition of
which is
(II), there is a least number /3 of (II)
Therefore
numbers.
all
of
these
than
greater
/3> a K
(I)
(II)
is
and thus also {3>a v and also every number /3 </3
is surpassed in magnitude by certain numbers a K
,
If there is a greatest a K
=y, then the number y +
is a member of (II) and not of (7)
not a greatest, the number /3 is a
and not of (7).
and
if
there
member
is
of (II)
Further, the power of (II) is the next greater to
that of (I), so that no other powers lie between
5
INTR OD UCTION
66
them, for any aggregate of numbers of
is
of the
Zx
(I)
and
(II)
In fact, this aggregate
power of (I) or (II).
when arranged in order of magnitude, is well-
ordered, and
may
(js)>
(/3
be represented by
= w,
o>
a,
where we always have /3<2, where
number of (III); and consequently
finite
or of the
power of
(I) or
is
the
is
(ap)
of that
first
either
of (II),
From this results the theorem
any well-defined aggregate of the second
power, M is a part of M and M" is a part of M
and we know that M" is of the same power as M,
then M is of the same power as M, and therefore
as M" and Cantor remarked that this theorem is
generally valid, and promised to return to it.*
Though the commutative law does not, in general,
quartum non datur.
If
is
hold with the transfinite numbers, the associative
law does, but the distributive law is only generally
valid in the form
:
where a + /3,
a,
and
/3
mediately recognize by
are multipliers,
"as we im
inner intuition."
The subtraction, division, prime numbers, and
addition and multiplication of numbers which can
be put in the form of a rational and integral function
of
*
w of the
From
transfinite
numbers were then
the occurrence of this theorem
which we now know (see the
been a forestalling of the theorem that any
we may conclude that this latter theorem
xlvi, 1895,
on
p.
dealt with
484 of the Math. Ann.>
note on p. 204 below) to have
aggregate can be well-ordered,
was used in this instance.
INTR OD UCTION
much
in
the
same way
translated below.
as in the
67
memoir
of 1897
In the later memoir the subject
more completely, and was drawn up
more attention to logical form than was the
isjltreated far
with far
Grundlagen.
An
interesting part of the Grundlagen is the
discussion of the conditions under which we are to
regard the introduction into mathematics of a new
The result of
conception, such as eo, as justified.
was already indicated by the way in
<c
which Cantor defined his new numbers
We may
numbers
as
whole
actual
the
in
so
far as
regard
this discussion
they, on the ground of definitions, take a perfectly
determined place in our understanding, are clearly
distinguished from all other constituents of our
thought, stand in definite relations to them, and
thus modify,
our mind."
*
in so far as
in
We
a definite way, the substance of
"
"
may ascribe actuality to them
they must be held to be an expression
or an image (Abbild) of processes and relations in
the outer world, as distinguished from the intellect."
Cantor s position was, now, that while there is no
doubt that the first kind of reality always implies
the
second,*
difficult
matics,
reality,
the
is
most
pure mathe
often
metaphysical problem but, in
we need only consider the first kind
and consequently " mathematics is, in
development, quite
*
proof of this
;
free,
of
its
and only subject to the
This, according to Cantor, is a consequence of "the unity of the
which we ourselves belong," and so, in pure mathematics, we
need only pay attention to the reality of our conceptions in the first
sense, as slated in the text.
All, to
TNTR OD UCTION
68
self-evident condition that
from contradiction
free
fixed
in
particular,
and
formed
in the
by
arranged
relations,
previously
conceptions are both
themselves and stand
its
in
tested
to
definitions,
In
conceptions.
new numbers,
introduction of
it
only obligatory to give such definitions of them
as will afford them such a definiteness, and, under
is
certain circumstances, such a relation to the older
numbers, as permits them to be distinguished from
one another in given cases.
As soon as a number
satisfies all
these
it
conditions,
can and must be
considered as existent and real in mathematics.
this
In
we must regard the
and complex numbers as just as
see the grounds on which
rational, irrational,
existent as the positive integers."
There is no danger to be feared for science from
this
freedom
in the
formation of numbers,
for,
on
the one hand, the conditions referred to under which
this freedom can alone be exercised are such that
they leave only a very small opportunity for arbi
and, on the other hand, every mathe
matical conception has in itself the necessary
trariness
corrective,
if
is
it
unfruitful
shows
this very soon by
then abandoned.
To
support
the
idea
its
that
or
inconvenient,
it
and
is
unusability,
conceptions
not subject
in
pure
and
to any
metaphysical control, Cantor quoted the names
of, and the branches of mathematics founded by,
some of the greatest mathematicians of the nineteenth
century, among which an especially instructive
mathematics
are
free,
INTR OD UCTION
example
numbers
in
physics,
is
69
introduction of his " ideal"
Rummer s
"
"
into the theory of numbers. But
applied
such
as
mechanics
and
mathematics,
analytical
and
in
its
both
metaphysical
"
ends.
If
it
in
its
seeks to free
foundations
itself
of this,
was proposed
lately by a celebrated physicist,*
it degenerates into a
describing of nature, which
must lack both the fresh breeze of free mathematical
as
thought and the power of explanation and grounding
of natural appearances. "
The note of Cantor s on the process followed in
the correct formation of conceptions is interesting.
In his judgment, this process
is
everywhere the same
we
posit a thing without properties, which is at first
nothing else than a name or a sign A, and give it
order different, even infinitely many, predicates,
whose meaning for ideas already present is known,
and which may not contradict one another.
By
in
this
the
to the conception already
particular to the allied ones, are
relations of
present, and
determined
in
when we have completed
this, all the
conditions for the awakening of the conception A,
which slumbers in us, are present, and it enters
completed into "existence"
its
existence
"
in the first
in the
sense; to
is then
second sense
prove
a matter of metaphysics.
This seems to support the process by which Heine,
*
This
is
evidently Kirchhoff.
iiber
As
is
well
known, Kirchhoff pro
mathematische Physik,
vol. i, Mechanik,
Cf. E. Mach in his prefaces to his Mechanics
and
(3rd ed., Chicago
London, 1907 Supplementary Volume, Chicago
and London, 1915), and Popular Scientific Lectures; 3rd ed., Chicago
and London, 1898, pp. 236-258.
posed
Vorlesungtn
Leipzig, 1874) this(
INTRODUCTION
70
in a
paper partly inspired by his discussions with
Cantor, defined the real numbers as signs, to which
But
subsequently various properties were given.
Cantor himself, as we shall see later, afterwards
pointed out
emphatically the
Kronecker and von Helmholtz
mistake into which
fell
when they
started
number-concept with the
and most unessential thing the ordinal words
in their expositions of the
last
theory of number so that
think, regard this note of Cantor s as
indication that, at this time (1882), he was a
or signs
in the scientific
we must,
an
or at
supporter of the formalist theory of number,
least of rational and real non-integral numbers.
as to what is meant
mathematics notions which
are intimately connected with his introduction of
irrational and transfinite numbers
were in substance
"
identical with those of Hankel (1867) on
possible
In
fact,
Cantor
by "existence"
notions
in
or impossible numbers."
Hankel was a formalist,
not
a
consistent
one, and his theory was
though
with great acuteness by Frege in 1884.
But these criticisms mark the beginning of the
logical theory of mathematics, Cantor s earlier work
belonging to \heformal stage, and his later work to
what may be called the psychological stage.
Finally, Cantor gave a discussion and exact de
criticized
termination
of the
"continuum."
meaning of the conception of
After briefly referring to the dis
cussions of this concept due to Leucippus,
Demo-
critus, Aristotle, Epicurus, Lucretius, and Thomas
Aquinas, and emphasizing that we cannot begin, in
INTRODUCTION
71
with the conception of time or
that of space, for these conceptions can only be
this determination,
by means of a continuity-concep
which must, of course, be independent of them,
he started from the ^-dimensional plane arithmetical
clearly explained
tion
space
values
GH
that
is
to say, the totality of
which every x can receive any
in
to
co
by
value from
independently of the others.
Every
called an "arithmetical point" of
co
such system
Gn
real
systems of
is
the "distance" of two such points
is
defined
the expression
and by an "arithmetical point-aggregate" P con
in G n is meant any aggregate of points
tained
;,
selected out of
it
by a
law.
Thus the
investi
gation comes
to the establishment of a sharp and
as general as possible a definition which should
allow us to decide when P is to be called a "con
tinuum."
P is of the power of (I),
number a of (I) or (II) for which
P (a) vanishes but if P is not of the power of (I),
P can be always, and in only one way, divided into
two aggregates R and S, where R is "reducible,"
that is to say, such that there is a first number y
If the first derivative
there
is
first
;
of (I) or (II) such that
INTRODUCTION
72
and S
such that derivation does not alter
is
it.
Then
S^S
and consequently also
and S is said to be " perfect. " No aggregate can
be both reducible and perfect, "but, on the other
hand, irreducible
imperfect
is
exactly
much
not so
the
same
as
as
perfect,
reducible,
as
nor
we
easily see with some attention."
Perfect aggregates are by no means always every
where dense an example of such an aggregate
which is everywhere dense in no interval was given
;
Thus such aggregates
by Cantor.
for the
are not fitted
definition of a continuum, although
complete
we must grant that the continuum must be perfect.
The other predicate is that the aggregate must be
connected (zusammenhdngend), that is to say, if t
and t are any two of its points and e a given arbi
trarily small positive number, a finite number of
r
t v of P exist such that the dis
points /j, t^
are all less than e.
tances #!, // 2
., t v t
"All the geometric point-continua known to us
.
are,
now,
as
and I believe,
two
recognize
predicates
and connected the necessary and sufficient
is
that
5
easy to
see,
connected
in
these
perfect
characteristics of a point-continuum."
Bolzano s (1851) definition of a
certainly not correct,
for
it
property of a continuum, which
continuum
expresses
is
only
also possessed
is
one
by
INTRODUCTION
aggregates which arise from
aggregate is removed from
73
G n when
any isolated
and
also
in those
it,
Also
continua.
consisting of many separated
Dedekind * appeared to Cantor only to emphasize
another property of a continuum, namely, that which
it
common
with
has
in
We
will pass over the
all
other perfect aggregates.
development of the theory
Benof point-aggregates subsequently to 1882
on
the
s
and
s
researches
Cantor
dixson
power of
adherences "
perfect aggregates, Cantor s theory of
"
the
of
and
*
Cantor,
investigations
others
and
on the
Stolz, Harnack, Jordan, Borel,
"content" of aggregates, and the applications of
coherences,"
the
the
of point-aggregates to
theory
made by
functions
theory of
Jordan, Broden, Osgood, Baire,
Arzela, Schoenflies, and
trace the development,
many
others,
and
will
now
in Cantor s hands, of the
of
the
transfinite
cardinal
and ordinal numbers
theory
from 1883 to 1895.
VIII
An
account of the development that the theory
mind
of transfinite numbers underwent in Cantor
from
articles
to
1883
published
in
1890
is
described
in
his
Zeitschrift fur Philosophic und
Kritik for 1887 and 1888, and
the
philosophische
collected and published in 1890 under the title Zur
Lehre vom Transfiniten.
great part of this little
book
is
taken up with detailed discussions about
philosophers
denials of the possibility of infinite
*
Essays on
Number
>
p.
u.
INTR OD UCTION
74
numbers, extracts from
letters to and from philo
and
"All sosophers
theologians, and so on.*
called proofs of the impossibility of actually infinite
numbers," said Cantor, "are, as may be shown in
every particular case and also on general grounds,
false
in
numbers
that
in
they begin by attributing
all
question
numbers, whereas the
to be thinkable in
the
to
of
properties
the
finite
numbers, if they are
must
constitute quite
any form,
infinite
a new kind of number as opposed to the finite
numbers, and the nature of this new kind of number
is dependent on the nature of things and is an object
of investigation, but not of our arbitrariness or our
"
prejudice.
In 1883 Cantor had begun to lecture on his view
of whole numbers and types of order as general
concepts or universals (unum versus alia) which
relate to aggregates
when we
"
and
arise
from these aggregates
abstract from the nature of the elements.
Every aggregate of
as a unitary thing in
distinct things can be regarded
which the things
are constitutive elements.
If
we
first
mentioned
abstract both from
the nature of the elements and from the order in
which they are given, we get the
or
power
which the
cardinal
number
of the aggregate, a general concept in
elements, as so-called units, have so
one another to make a
unitary whole that no one of them ranks above the
grown organically
into
Hence results that two different aggregates
others.
have the same cardinal number when and only when
*
Cf.
VII, near the beginning.
INTRODUCTION
75
they are what I call equivalent to one another,
and there is no contradiction when, as often happens
with infinite aggregates, two aggregates of which
one
is
a part of the other have the same cardinal
I regard the non-recognition of this fact
number.
the
principal
infinite
numbers.
as
to,
obstacle
the
to
introduction
of
If the act of abstraction referred
when we have
to do with an aggregate ordered
one or many relations (dimensions), is
according to
only performed with respect to the nature of the
elements, so that the ordinal rank in which these
elements stand to one another
is kept in the general
whole
the
arising is what I call
organic
concept,
ordinal type, or in the special case of well-ordered
aggregates
an
ordinal
number.
This
ordinal
the same thing that I called, in my
Grundlagen of 1883, the enumeral (Anzahl) of a
Two ordered aggregates
well-ordered aggregate.
number
is
have one and the same ordinal type if they stand
to one another in the relation of
similarity,
be exactly defined.
These are
the roots from which develops with logical necessity
which relation
will
the organism of transfinite theory of types and in
particular of the transfinite ordinal numbers, and
which
hope soon to publish
in a
systematic form."
The contents
of a lecture given in 1883 were also
a
of 1884.
In it was pointed out
in
letter
given
that the cardinal number of an aggregate
is the
general concept
equivalent to
"One
under which
M, and
that
of the most
fall
all
aggregates
important problems of the
INTR OD UCTION
76
theory of aggregates, which
my
as to its principal part in
believe
have solved
Grundlagen, consists
the question of determining the various powers
of the aggregates in the whole of nature, in so far
in
we can know
This end
have reached by
the development of the general concept of enumeral
of well-ordered aggregates, or, what is the same
as
it.
The
of the concept of ordinal number."
concept of ordinal number is a special case of the
thing,
concept of ordinal type, which relates to any simply
or multiply ordered aggregate in the same way as
ordinal number to
The problem here arises
the
ordinal
numbers
When
part
of
powers
a well-ordered
aggregate.
of determining the various
in nature.
Cantor said that he had solved the chief
the
in
problem of determining the various
meant that he had almost
nature, he
proved that the power of the arithmetical continuum
the same as the power of the ordinal numbers of
In spite of the fact that Cantor
the second class.
is
firmly believed this, possibly on account of the fact
that all known aggregates in the continuum had
been found to be either of the
first
power or of the
power of the continuum, the proof or disproof of
this theorem has not even now been carried out,
and there
is
some ground
for
believing
that
it
cannot be carried out.
Cantor, in his Grundlagen, had noted as the
relation of two well-ordered aggregates which have
the same enumeral was here called the relation of
What
"
similarity,"
and
in the
laws of multiplication of
INTRODUCTION
77
two ordinal numbers he departed from the custom
followed in the Grundlagen and wrote the multiplier
The
on the right and the multiplicand on the left.
importance of this alteration
that we can write
a^.a Y = a^ +Y
:
is
seen by the fact
whereas we would
in the notation of the
have to write,
Grundlagen
afi.av-tf+fi,
the end of this letter, Cantor remarked that
may, in a sense, be regarded as the limit to which
At
CD
number tends. Here " o> is
transfinite ordinal number which is greater
finite numbers
exactly in the same way
the variable finite whole
the least
than all
j/
that ^/2 is the limit of certain variable, increasing,
rational numbers, with this difference the difference
:
between *J2 and these approximating fractions be
comes as small as we wish, whereas <o v is always
But this difference in no way alters the
equal to w.
fact that to is to be regarded as as definite and com
pleted as ^2, and in no way alters the fact that
has no more trace of the numbers which tend to
j/
a)
it
has of the approximating fractions.
The
transfinite numbers are in a sense new irrationalities,
than
^2
and indeed
in
my
finite irrational
my
eyes the best method of defining
numbers
is
method of introducing
the same in principle as
transfinite
numbers.
We
can say that the transfinite numbers stand or fall
with finite irrational numbers, in their inmost being
they are
alike,
for
both are definitely marked off
modifications of the actually infinite."
With
this
is
connected
in principle
an extract from
INTR OD UCTION
78
((
a letter written in 1886:
Finally
have
still
to
explain to you in what sense I conceive the minimum
of the transfinite as limit of the increasing finite.
For
this
purpose
we must
consider that the concept
domain of finite numbers has two
essential characteristics.
For example, the number
i is the limit of the numbers #= i
where v is
i/j/,
a variable, finite, whole number, which increases
of
limit
above
in the
difference
zv
finitely small
In
limits.
finite
all
is
the
first
place
the
a magnitude which becomes in
second place i is the least of
in the
numbers which are greater than all magnitudes z v
Each of these two properties characterizes the finite
number i as limit of the variable magnitude z v
all
Now
if
we wish
transfinite limits
characteristics
extend the concept of limit to
as well, the second of the above
used
the first must here be
to
is
allowed to drop because
finite limits.
it
Accordingly
has a meaning only for
call co the limit of the
increasing, finite, whole numbers v because co is the
least of all numbers which are greater than all the
,
finite
numbers.
But
CD
v is
co, and
numbers
increasing
indeed any number
off from co as the least
always equal to
we cannot say that the
come as near as we wish to o>
therefore
however great is quite as far
Here we see especially clearly the
finite number.
very important fact that
my
least transfinite ordinal
and consequently all greater ordinal
o>,
numbers, lie quite outside the endless series i, 2, 3,
and so on. Thus o> is not a maximum of the finite
"
numbers, for there is no such thing.
number
INTRODUCTION
79
In another letter written in 1886, Cantor empha
In all
sized another aspect of irrational numbers.
of the definitions of these numbers there is used,
indeed essential, a special actually infinite
In both this and
aggregate of rational numbers.
as
is
1886, Cantor returned in great
to the distinction between the "potential"
another letter of
detail
and "actual" infinite of which he had made a great
The
point under other names in his Grundlagen.
potential infinite is a variable finite, and in order
may be completely known, we
must be able to determine the domain of variability,
and this domain can only be, in general, an actually
that such a variable
infinite
infinite
Thus every potential
aggregate of values.
an
actually infinite, and these
presupposes
"domains of
variability" which are studied in the
theory of aggregates are the foundations of arith
metic and analysis. Further, besides actually infinite
aggregates, we have to consider in mathematics
natural abstractions from these aggregates, which
form the material of the theory of transfinite
numbers.
In 1885, Cantor had developed to a large extent
his theory of cardinal numbers and ordinal types.
In the fairly long paper which he wrote out, he
on the theory of ordinal types
laid particular stress
and entered
into details
which he had not published
before as to the definition of ordinal type in general,
number is a particular case. In
of which ordinal
this paper also
an aggregate
he denoted the cardinal number of
by M, and the ordinal type of
INTR OD UCTION
8o
by
that
thus indicating by lines over the letter
of abstraction is to
double or single act
be performed.
In the theory of cardinal numbers, he defined the
addition and multiplication of two cardinal numbers
and proved the fundamental laws about them in
much
the
1895 which
same way
as he did in the
translated below.
is
memoir
of
It is characteristic
of Cantor s views that he distinguished very sharply
between an aggregate and a cardinal number that
" Is not an
to it
out
an
belongs
aggregate
side us, whereas
cardinal
its
picture of it in our
In an ordered
mind
number
object
is
an abstract
"
?
aggregate of any number of
dimensions, such as the totality of points in space,
as determined by three rectangular co-ordinates, or
a piece of music whose dimensions are the sequence
of the tones in time, the duration of each tone in
time, the pitch of the tones, and the intensity of the
tones, then "if we make abstraction of the nature
of the elements, while
we
retain their rank in all the
n different directions, an intellectual picture, a general
concept, is generated in us, and I call this the /z-ple
The definition of the " similarity of
ordinal type."
ordered aggregates " is
"Two n-p\y ordered aggregates
and
so
to
make
called
similar
if
is
it
possible
are
their
elements correspond to another uniquely and com
pletely that, if E and E are any two elements of
and F and F the two corresponding elements of
N, then for
I,
2,
n the relation of rank of
INTR OD UCTION
E
to
in
the
direction inside the aggregate
*/th
exactly the same as the relation of rank of F to
in the i/th direction inside the aggregate N.
is
M
F
We
such a correspondence of two aggregates
which are similar to one another an imaging of the
will
call
"
one on the other.
The addition and multiplication of ordinal types,
and the fundamental laws about them, were then
dealt with much as in the memoir of 1895 which is
The
translated below.
to
consideration
rest of the
of problems
paper was devoted
about ^-ple finite
types.
In 1888, Cantor, who had arrived at a very clear
notion that the essential part of the concept of number
lay in the unitary concept that we form, gave some
on the essays of Helmholtz and
Kronecker, which appeared in 1887, on the concept
of number.
Both the authors referred to started
with the last and most unessential feature in our
treatment of ordinal numbers the words or other
interesting criticisms
signs that we use to represent these numbers.
In 1887, Cantor gave a more detailed proof of the
non-existence of actually infinitely small magnitudes.
This proof was referred to in advance in the Grundlagen^
and was
later put into a
more rigorous form
by Feano.
We
have already referred to the researches of
in 1883 and
Cantor on point-aggregates published
only other paper besides those already
dealt with that was published by Cantor on an
later
the
important
question
in
the
theory of
transfinite
INTRODUCTION
82
numbers was one [published
in 1892.
In this paper
see the origins of the conception of
cover
ing" (Belegung) defined in the memoir of 1895 trans
lated below.
In the terminology introduced in this
we can
memoir, we can say that the paper of 1892 contains
a proof that 2, when exponentiated by a transfinite
cardinal number, gives rise to a cardinal number
which
is
greater than
the
cardinal
number
first
mentioned.
introduction of the concept of " covering" is
the most striking advance in the principles of the
The
theory of transfinite numbers from 1885 to 1895,
and we can now study the final and considered form
which Cantor gave to the theory in two important
memoirs of 1895 an ^ 1897. The principal advances
in the
theory since 1897 will De referred to in the
notes at the end of this book.
CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE
FOUNDING OF THE THEORY OF
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE
FOUNDING OF THE THEORY OF
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
[481]
(FIRST ARTICLE)
"
Hypotheses non
"
Neque enim
"
fingo.
leges intellectui aut rebus
damus
ad arbitrium nostrum, sed tanquam scriboe
fideles ab ipsius naturae voce latas et prolatas
excipimus et describimus."
"Veniet tempus, quo ista quae nunc latent, in
lucem dies extrahat et longioris sevi diligentia."
The Conception
of
Power or Cardinal Number
BY an "aggregate" (Menge) we
are to understand
whole {Zusammenfassung zu
of definite and separate objects m
collection into a
any
.einem Ganzeri)
of our intuition or our thought.
"
of M.
called the "elements
In signs
we express
We
.
denote the uniting of many aggregates M, N,
which have no common elements, into a
single aggregate
(2)
M = {**}.
(1)
P,
this thus
These objects are
by
(M, N,
P,
85
.)-
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
86
The elements
elements of
We
of this aggregate are, therefore, the
of N, of P,
., taken together.
M,
the
will call
name "part"
or "partial
by
of
an
aggregate
aggregate
any other aggregate
whose elements are also elements of M.
x
"
If
is
2
is a part of
2
a part of M.
Mj and
is
a part of
M has a definite
M, then
"
power," which
we will also call its " cardinal number."
We will call by the name " power" or "cardinal
Every aggregate
number "
the general concept which, by means
of our active faculty of thought, arises from the
when we make abstraction of the
aggregate
of
nature of
its
various elements
and of the order
which they are given.
in
[482]
We
denote the result of this double act of
abstraction, the cardinal
its
number
or
power of M, by
M.
(3)
Since every single element m, if we abstract from
nature, becomes a "unit," the cardinal number
a definite aggregate composed of units, and
this number has existence in our mind as an intel
is
lectual
We
image or projection of the given aggregate M.
"
say that two aggregates M and N are
equi
valent," in signs
(4)
M oo N
or
<\>
M,
possible to put them, by some law, in such a
relation to one another that to every element of each
if it is
one of them corresponds one and only one element
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
87
there corre
To every part 1 of
of N, and
a
definite
x
equivalent part
sponds, then,
of the other.
inversely.
If
a law of co-ordination of two
we have such
equivalent aggregates, then, apart from the case
of them consists only of one element, we
when each
We can, for
can modify this law. in many ways.
to
take
that
a
care
instance, always
special element
;/z
of
M a special
element n of
N corresponds.
For
according to the original law, the elements m Q
and n do not correspond to one another, but to the
if,
the element n l of N corresponds,
m of
and to the element n Q of N the element m of M
element
which
we
take the modified law according to
corresponds to n Q and ;;z x to n^ and for the
corresponds,
other elements the original law remains unaltered.
By this means the end is attained.
Every aggregate
equivalent to itself
MooM.
(5)
If
is
two aggregates are equivalent
equivalent to one another
(6)
from
M oo P
and
to a third, they are
that is to say
:
oo P
follows
M oo N.
Of fundamental importance is the theorem that
two aggregates M and N have the same cardinal
number if, and only if, they are equivalent thus,
:
(7)
from
M oo N
we
get
from
we
get
M oo N.
N,
and
(8)
= N
Thus the equivalence of aggregates forms the neces-
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
88
sary and sufficient condition for the equality of their
cardinal numbers.
[483] In
according to the above definition of
fact,
remains unaltered if
power, the cardinal number
in the place of each of one or many or even all
elements
of
other things are substituted.
If,
oo N, there is a law of co-ordination by
now,
means of which
and N are uniquely and recipro
and by it to the
cally referred to one another
element
of
corresponds the element n of N.
;
Then we can imagine, in the place of every element
m of M, the corresponding element n of N substi
tuted, and, in this
way,
M transforms
alteration of cardinal number.
into
N without
Consequently
M = N.
The converse of the theorem results from the re
mark that between the elements of M and the
different units of its cardinal number M a recipro
cally univocal (or bi-univocal) relation of correspond
ence subsists.
speak, out of
of
element
we can say
For, as we saw, M grows,
M in such a way that from
M a special unit of M arises.
every
Thus
that
M oo M.
(9)
same way
by (6), M oo N.
In the
We
so to
oo N.
If
then
M = N,
we
have,
mention the following theorem, which
results immediately from the conception of equivalwill
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
ence.
M, N,
If
P,
are aggregates which have
P
are also aggre
M N
no common
elements,
gates with the same property, and
,
M oo M
N oo N
89
if
P oo P
we always have
then
(M, N,
P,
oo (M
.)
P;
.)
" Greater" and
If for
numbers
(a)
(b}
two aggregates
a
There
There
if
in
= M and b = N,
are fulfilled,
hold
"Less" with Powers
is
no part of
is
a part
it
is
them
with the cardinal
:
M which
Nj_
is equivalent to N,
of N, such that N x oo M,
obvious that these conditions
and
and
both the conditions
equivalent aggregates
press a definite relation
a
and
still
by two
and N
Thus they ex
of the cardinal numbers
are replaced
.
to one another.
and N, and
[484] Further, the equivalence of
thus the equality of a and b, is excluded for if we
had
oo N, we would have, because N x oj M, the
;
M
M
oo N,
equivalence N x oo N, and then, because
there would exist a part MJ of
such that
x oj M,
and therefore we should have Mj c\; N
and this
contradicts the condition
Thirdly, the relation
(a).
of a to
makes impossible the same
is
such that
relation of b to a
it
for if
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
90
in
and
(a)
(6)
arise
tradictory to the former ones.
express the relation of a to
We
(a)
"
and
(b)
"
greater
a is
by saying:
than a in signs
characterized
"less" than
or
by
is
a<b
(1)
We
and N are
which are con
the parts played by
interchanged, two conditions
or
b>a.
can easily prove that,
(2) if a
< b and
Similarly,
that,
if
Px
follows a
We
<
from the
is
c,
then
we always have
definition,
from P
<b
<
c.
follows at once
it
part of an aggregate
< P and
P,
follows Pj
from
< Pl
< b.
have seen that, of the three relations
a
= b,
a<b, b<a,
each one excludes the two others.
On
the other
theorem that, with any two cardinal
numbers a and b, one of those three relations must
necessarily be realized, is by no means self-evident
and can hardly be proved at this_stage.
Not until later, when we shall have gained a
hand,
the
survey over the ascending sequence of the transfinite
cardinal numbers and an insight into their connexion,
theorem
two
cardinal numbers, then
any
will result the truth of the
A. If a and
either a
=b
or a
are
<b
or a
> b.
From this theorem the following theorems, of
which, however, we will here make no use, can be
very simply derived
;
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
two aggregates
If
B.
equivalent to a part
M, then
If
C.
and
MJ
is
M
M of
and N are such that
N and N to a part
of
are equivalent
a part of an aggregate
is
M,
is
of the aggregate
and if the aggregates
1?
and
are
then
2
equivalent,
Mj is equivalent to
part
91
both
and
with two aggregates
and N, N
to
nor
to
neither
a
equivalent
part of M, there
D.
If,
a part
E. If
that
equivalent to
and N are not equivalent,
two aggregates
and there is a part N t of N that is equivalent to M,
x
of
is
is
is
then no part of
is
[485]
equivalent to N.
The Addition and Multiplication
of
Powers
two aggregates
and N which
elements was denoted in
i, (2),
" union
by (M, N). We call it the
-aggregate
and N."
(Vereinigungsmenge) of
The union
have no
of
common
two other aggregates without
common elements, and if M ou M and N oj N we
saw that we have
If
and
are
(M, N) ro
Hence the
cardinal
upon the cardinal
(M
number
put
(i)
).
of (M,
N) only depends
and N = b.
of the sum of a and b.
numbers M = a
This leads to the definition
We
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
92
Since in the conception of power, we abstract from
the order of the elements, we conclude at once that
(2)
+ b = b + a;
ci
and, for any three cardinal numbers
a
(3)
We
now come
+ (b + c) = (a + b) +
a,
b,
c,
we have
c.
to multiplication.
Any
element
can be thought to be bound up
with any element n of another aggregate N so as
we denote by (M N)
to form a new element "(m n)
of an aggregate
the aggregate of all these bindings (m, n), and call
it the "aggregate of bindings
(Verbindungsmehge)
of
and N."
Thus
(M.N) = {(,)}.
(4)
We
power of (M N) only depends on
and N = b for, if we replace the
and N by the aggregates
see that the
the powers
aggregates
M=a
M
W = {m}
N ={#
and
respectively equivalent to them, and consider ;;/,
and n ri as corresponding elements, then the
y
aggregate
(M NO = {(*
.
)}
brought into a reciprocal and univocal corre
spondence with (M N) by regarding (m, n) and
Thus
n } as corresponding elements.
(;
is
(5)
We now
(6)
(M N )oo(M.N).
.
define the product a
a
= (M
N).
by the equation
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
An
[486]
a
aggregate with the cardinal number
made up out of two aggregates
also be
may
93
with the cardinal numbers a and b according
to the following rule
We start from the aggregate
N and replace in it every element n by an aggregate
and
w r>o
if,
then, we collect the elements of
these aggregates
M to a whole S, we see that
;
all
Sco(M.N),
(7)
and consequently
=a.b.
For, if, with any given law of correspondence of the
two equivalent aggregates M and M n we denote
by m the element of M which corresponds to the
,
element
mn
of
Mw
we have
S
(8)
= {*};
and thus the aggregates S and (M.N) can be re
ferred reciprocally and univocally to one another by
regarding m n and (m, n) as corresponding elements.
From
our definitions result readily the theorems
a.b = b.a,
(9)
a.(b.c) = (a.b).c,
(10)
(u)
because
a(b
+ c) = ab + ac;
(M.N)ro(N.M),
(M.(N.P))ou((M.N).P),
(M (N, P)) cv ((M N), (M
.
P)).
Addition and multiplication of powers are subject,
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
94
therefore, to the commutative, associative, and dis
tributive laws.
The Exponentiation
By
of
a " covering of the aggregate
Powers
with elements
of the aggregate M," or, more simply, by a "cover
with M," we understand a law by which
ing of
with every element n of N a definite element of
is bound up, where one and the same element of
M
M
can come repeatedly into application.
The element
of
bound up with n is, in a way, a one-valued
and
may be denoted by f(n) it is
function
of n."
The correspond
covering
of
N
will
be
called
ing covering
/(N).
[487] Two coverings /^(N) andy^(N) are said to
function of
n^
((
called a
be equal
if,
and only
if,
for all
elements n of
the
equation
/i()=/2 ()
(i)
so that if this equation does not subsist
even a single element n = n ^fl (N) and^(N) are
For ex
characterized as different coverings of N.
is fulfilled,
for
ample,
if
is
fix that, for all
a particular element of
f(n)
this
M.
are
M, we may
=m
;,
law constitutes a particular covering of N with
Another kind of covering results if m g and m
two
different particular elements of
particular element of N, from fixing that
and n a
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
for all
which are different from n
95
totality of different coverings of N with
forms a definite aggregate with the elements /(N)
The
we
of
call
it
with
M"
and denote
(N
(2)
If
M oo W
and
the cardinal
it
by (N
N we
,
Thus
M).
easily find that
M) oo (N
M)={/(N)}.
c\;
(N
(3)
Thus
the " covering-aggregate (Beltgungsmenge)
number
of
).
(N M) depends only
and N = b it serves
|
on the cardinal
numbers M = a
us for the definition of a
= (NpS).
a*
(4)
For any three aggregates, M, N,
P,
we
easily prove
the theorems:
(5)
(6)
((N
((P
(7)
M)
M)
(P
(P
(P
(N
M))
c\j
((N, P)
N))
ex.
(P
M))
fX>
(M
((P N)
M),
N)),
M),
if we put P = c, we have, by (4) and by
attention
to
3, the theorems for any three
paying
cardinal numbers, a, b, and c
from which,
.a
(8)
(9)
a r .b f
(10)
( a t)t
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
96
[488] We see how pregnant and far-reaching
these simple formulae extended to powers are by the
If we denote the power of the
following example.
continuum X (that is, the totality X of real
numbers x such that x>_ and <^i) by o, we easily
linear
see that
it
may
the formula
be represented by, amongst others,
= 2^,
(n)
where
2^
is
6 gives the meaning of N O
the power of
all
In fact, by (4),
representations
(where f(y) = o or
If we pay
of the numbers x in the binary system.
attention to the fact that every number x is only
represented once, with the exception of the^numbers
x=
-< i,
which are represented twice over, we
have, if we denote the
the latter by \s v },
2* =
enumerable"
totality of
*}. X).
" enumerable "
If we take away from X any
aggre
the
remainder
X
have
denote
we
and
by
1;
gate {/}
x =({*}, x )=({^-i}, {M,
1
so
Jr },
X),
xj,
OF TRANSFIN1TE NUMBERS
and thus
i)
2 No
From
(11) follows
0.0 = 2^
= X=0.
by squaring (by
.
2^
= 2^^"^
6, (6))
= 2^ =
and hence, by continued multiplication by
where
we
o,
0*=0,
(13)
If
y;
v is
we
any
raise
finite
cardinal number.
both sides of
to the
(n)
power* N O
get
Ko
But
since,
by
= (2 N ) Ko =2 Ko
6, (8),
N O .N O =:N O we have
,
o^-o.
(14)
The
Ko
(13) and (14) mean that both the
y-dimensional and the ^-dimensional continuum have
formulae
the power of the one-dimensional continuum.
the whole contents of
my
paper
in Crelle s
Thus
Journal\
Ixxxiv, 1878,1 are derived purely algebraically
with these few strokes of the pen from the fundamental
vol.
formulae of the calculation with cardinal numbers.
[489]
The
We
have
will
laid
Finite Cardinal
Numbers
next show how the principles which we
down, and on which later on the theory
of the actually infinite or transfinite cardinal numbers
*
[In English there is an ambiguity.]
of the Introduction.]
t [See Section
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
98
be built, afford also the most natural, shortest,
and most rigorous foundation for the theory of
finite numbers.
To a single thing
if we subsume it under the
of
an
concept
aggregate E = (V ), corresponds as
will
cardinal
i
number what we
"one" and denote by
call
we have
=E
(1)
Let us now unite with
call
another thing
el
and
the union-aggregate Ej, so that
E = (E
(2)
The
number
cardinal
denoted by
of
*!>
=(
is
*i)-
<>.
"two" and
called
is
(3)
By
= Er
new elements we
addition of
get the series of
aggregates
E 8 = (E
E 2^( E *,
i>
which give us successively,
the
other
noted by
make
3,
4,
5,
of these
We
it
have,
(5)
The
numbers
number
unlimited sequence,
numbers" de
if
by
i/
E = (E
v
is
which we here
use
as suffixes
is
is
understood the number im
v in
.i,
by
a cardinal number.
the above series,
.!>
justified
only used as a suffix
has been defined as
mediately preceding
(4)
*3 ), ...,
so-called "finite cardinal
the fact that a
when
in
2,
*) = (*<>,
e l9
e v ).
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
From
the definition of a
sum
in
follows
99
E^E^-i+i;
(6)
to say, every cardinal number, except
the sum of the immediately preceding one and
that
is
the following three theorems
Now,
foreground
A. The terms
come
I,
is
i.
into the
cardinal
the unlimited series
of
numbers
2, 3,
i,
are
...,?,...
from one another (that
different
all
of finite
is
to say,
the condition of equivalence established in
fulfilled for the corresponding aggregates).
is
not
[490] B. Every one of these numbers v is greater
than the preceding ones and less than the following
ones ( 2).
C.
There are
lie
magnitude,
v
and
i/+
We
no cardinal numbers which, in
between two consecutive numbers
2).
make
the proofs of these theorems rest on
and E.
the two following ones,
shall, then,
We
in
next
the
place, give the latter theorems rigid
proofs.
is an aggregate such that it is of
If
equal
of its parts, then the aggregate
none
with
power
by the addition of a
(M, e), which arises from
D.
new element
has the same property of
with
none of its parts.
of
being
equal power
E. If N is an aggregate with the finite cardinal
single
number
y,
and
Nx
is
ey
any part of N, the cardinal
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
TOO
number
of
numbers
is
2, 3,
i,
.,
one of the preceding
to
equal
i.
Proof of D.
Suppose that the aggregate (M, e)
is equivalent to one of its parts which we will call
Then two cases, both of which lead to a con
N.
tradiction, are to be distinguished
The aggregate N
(a)
N = (Mj_,
e)
then
a part of (M,
contains
a part of
is
1
As we saw
e].
as element
in
because
let
is
the law of
i,
correspondence of the two equivalent aggregates
(M, e) and (M 1 e) can be so modified that the
,
element
element
e
e
this contradicts the supposition that
not equivalent to
is
and univocally to one
reciprocally
But
another.
referred
are
one corresponds to the same
of the other
and Mj
by that, then,
the
of
its
part
Mr
part N of (M, e) does not contain e as
that N is either
or a part of M.
so
In
element,
of
between
and
the law
correspondence
(M, e)
N,
The
(b)
which
lies
element
latter
at the basis of our supposition, to the
of the former let the element
of the
correspond.
N = (M X
Let
/)
then
the
is put in a reciprocally univocal relation
aggregate
is a part of N and hence of M.
But
with
x
r
would be equivalent to one of its
So here too
parts,
and
this
Proof of E.
contrary to the supposition.
is
We
will
suppose the correctness
of the theorem up to a certain v and then conclude
its validity for the number v+i which immediately
follows, in the following
the aggregate
K,,
= <>
e l9
manner
.
.,
e v)
We
start
from
as an aggregate
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
with the cardinal number
true for
this
v+
theorem
If the
i.
for
aggregate,
aggregate with the same cardinal
Let E be any part of
follows at once by
i.
we
is
any other
number j/+i
truth
its
101
distinguish the following cases
(a) E does not contain e v as element, then
E,,
is
either E v _i [491] or a part of
_!, and so has as
cardinal number either v or one of the numbers
2
i)
>
true
3>
>
number
(b)
fore
we supposed
aggregate
consists of the
consists of e v
//
because
>
_!,
our theorem
with the cardinal
v.
E =i.
(c) E
E = (E
l/
the
for
E"
element
single
e v)
then
and an aggregate E", so that
_! and has there
number one of the
a part of
e v ).
supposition as cardinal
is
by
But now E = E"-fi>
i.
numbers i, 2, 3,
., v
and thus the cardinal number of E is one of the
numbers 2, 3,
., v.
.
Every one of the aggregates which
Proof of A.
we have denoted by E, has
being equivalent
to
suppose that this
from the theorem
is
the property of not
For if we
any of its parts.
as
far
as
a
so
certain j/, it follows
D that
following number v+i.
it is
so for the immediately
For
i/=
i,
we
recognize at
once that the aggregate E 1 = (^ e t ) is not equivalent
to any of its parts, which are here (e ) and (^).
,
Consider, now, any two
numbers
series
if p.
1,2,
the later,
3,
E^
is
then,
a part of
;
is
_!.
/x
and
of the
the earlier and
Thus
E^ and
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
102
not
are
,,_!
equivalent,
numbers
cardinal
= EM _
and
accordingly
and
=E
their
not
are
equal.
If of the two finite cardinal numbers
Proof of B.
and v the first is the earlier and the second the
For consider the two aggregates
later, then ^ < v.
M = E M _! and N = _!; for them each of the two
ILJL
conditions in
dition (a)
is
M=E
of
/X
M<N
for
is
fulfilled.
The con
because, by theorem E, a part
only have one of the cardinal
fulfilled
can
numbers i, 2, 3,
and therefore, by
.,
I,
/*
theorem A, cannot be equivalent to the aggregate
.
N=E
J/
itself
is
The
1.
less
condition (b)
is
fulfilled
because
a part of N.
Let
Proof of C.
is
v+
than
I.
be a cardinal number which
Because of the condition
(b)
of
a part of E,, with the cardinal number
| 2,
theorem
a.
E, a part of E^ can only have one
By
of the cardinal numbers i, 2, 3,
Thus a is
v.
there
is
one of the cardinal numbers i, 2, 3,
., v.
than
theorem
none
of
these
is
v.
B,
By
greater
Consequently there is no cardinal number a which
equal to
is
less
than
v+i and
Of importance
theorem
F.
for
greater than v.
what follows is the following
If
is
any aggregate of
different
finite
cardinal numbers, there is one, /q, amongst them
which is smaller than the rest, and therefore the
smallest of
all.
[492] Proof.
The aggregate
either contains
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
the
number
or
it
i,
does not.
aggregate of
i,
2,
in
3,
.,
all
103
the least, K I = I,
In the latter case, let J be the
which case
is
it
those cardinal numbers of our series,
which are smaller than those occurring
number v belongs to J, all numbers less
But J must have one element
belong to J.
that
such
!>!+!, and consequently all greater
j/j
not
do
numbers,
belong to J, because otherwise
in
K.
than
If a
would contain all finite numbers, whereas the
numbers belonging to K are not contained in J.
Thus J is the segment (Abscknitt) (i, 2, 3,
., Vl ).
The number V I +I=K I is necessarily an element of
K and smaller than the rest.
From F we
conclude
Every aggregate K={/c} of different finite
cardinal numbers can be brought into the form of
G.
a series
K=
(/c 1 ,
K2
AC
S,
.)
such that
The Smallest
Number
Transfinite Cardinal
Aleph-Zero
Aggregates with
finite cardinal
"finite aggregates,"
all
finite
and
(<
aggregates"
transfinite cardinal
The
first
others
their
numbers are
we
will call
cardinal
called
"trans-
numbers
numbers."
example of a
given by the totality of
transfinite aggregate
finite cardinal
numbers
is
v
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
104
we
call its
denote
it
cardinal
by N O
number
we
thus
"
(
i)
Aleph-zero
"
and
define
o={^-
(1)
That N O
is
a transfinite number, that is to say, is
finite number /x, follows from the
not equal to any
simple fact that,
new element
if
,
to the aggregate {v}
the
is
union-aggregate
added
is
({/},
For we
equivalent to the original aggregate {y}.
can think of this reciprocally univocal correspond
ence between them to the element e of the first
:
corresponds the element i of the second, and to the
element v of the first corresponds the element v + i of
the other.
By
we
thus have
N O + I= NO-
(2)
But we showed in
5 that /x-f i is always different
from /x, and therefore N O is not equal to any finite
number /x.
The number N O
is
greater than any finite
number /x
N O >M-
(3)
This follows,
[493]
we pay
if
attention
from the three facts that /x = (i, 2, 3,
no part of the aggregate (i, 2, 3,
.,
lent to the aggregate {j/}, and that (i,
.
a part of {i/}.
the other hand,
/x)
2,
to
3,
., /x),
that
is
equiva
3,
.,
/x)
is itself
On
cardinal number.
number
(4)
different
If a
NO
is
is
from N O then
,
the least
any
transfinite
transfinite cardinal
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
105
This rests on the following theorems
A. Every transfinite aggregate T has parts with
:
the cardinal
Proof.
number N O
by any
If,
number
finite
we have taken away
rule,
of elements
tv
there
2
_^
/j,
always remains the possibility of taking away a
further element t v
The aggregate {t v }, where v
denotes any finite cardinal number, is a part of T
.
.,
with the cardinal number N O because {^,}ou{y} ( i).
B. If S is a transfinite aggregate with the cardinal
,
number N O and S x
,
is
any
transfinite part of S, then
Si = NO-
We
have supposed that S cx> {i/}. Choose
Proof.
a definite law of correspondence between these two
aggregates, and, with this law, denote by s v that
element of S which corresponds to the element
of
{y}, so that
S = {*,}.
The part B! of S consists of certain elements S K
of S, and the totality of numbers /c forms a transfinite part
of
of the aggregate
the aggregate
K=U},
where
K V <K V +I
we have
By theorem G
can be brought into the
form of a series
consequently
{j/}.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
io6
Hence
follows that S x
From
no S, and therefore S^NQand B the formula (4) results, if we have
regard to
From
2.
(2)
we
by adding
conclude,
to both sides,
and, by repeating this
(5)
We
have also
NO
(6)
[494] For, by (i) of
({& v }j
{}
+ NO = NO-
3,
MO
+ MO is the cardinal number
because
Now, obviously
M=({2,,-I}, {2,}),
({2,- I}, {2,,}) 00 ({*}, {6 V }),
and therefore
I^})=R = N
(Kl,
The equation
(6) can also
NO
be written
= NO
by adding N O repeatedly
and,
to both sides,
find that
NO
(7)
We
also
(8)
= v.
NO
NO
NO = NO
have
= NO-
we
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
Proof.
number
By
of
(6)
NO NO
3,
is
107
the cardinal
of the aggregate of bindings
where ^ and
any finite cardinal numbers which
are independent of one another.
If also X repre
sents any finite cardinal number, so that {X}, {/*},
and { v \ are only different notations for the same
aggregate of all finite numbers, we have to show
v
are
that
{(^v}}^{\\.
Let us denote
/x
numerical values
I
elements
+ y by
(I,/)--
3, 4,
2,
(/x,
i),
j/)
then p takes
.,
p-2),
the
all
and there are
in
= p namely
im +
which
for
(2,
.,
(p-i,
all
:
i).
first the element (i, i),
which p=2, put, then the two elements for
which p 3, then the three elements for which
= 4, and so on. Thus we get all the elements
p
In this sequence imagine
for
(/UL,
v) in
a simple series
and here, as we easily see, the element
at the Xth place, where
(9)
The
.
(^c,
v)
comes
= M + V"
variable X takes every numerical value
once.
.,
Consequently, by means of
2,
3,
(9),
i,
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
io8
reciprocally univocal relation subsists
aggregates
{v}
and
between the
{(/x, i/)}.
[495] If both sides of the equation (8) are multi
3
2
and, by repeated
plied by N O we get ^ = ^ = ^
we
the
N
multiplications by
get
O
equation, valid
,
for
every
finite cardinal
(10)
KO"
The theorems E and
on
finite
number
aggregates
= NO-
of
lead to this theorem
aggregate E is such that it is
none of its parts.
This theorem stands sharply opposed to the
following one for transfinite aggregates
C.
finite
Every
equivalent to
D. Every transfinite aggregate T
has parts T x which are equivalent to
Proof.
a part S
Let
T=
By theorem
is
such that
it
it.
of this paragraph there
is
{/} of T with the cardinal number N O
is composed of those
(S, U), so that
.
which are different from the elements
= (5!, U) then T x is
fv
Let us put S 1 = {/ J/+ i},
a part of T, and, in fact, that part which arises out
Since
of T if we leave out the single element / r
S oo S ly by theorem B of this paragraph, and
elements of
U r\j U, we
have, by
i,
In these theorems C and
T oo T r
the essential differ
ence between finite and transfinite aggregates, to
which I referred in the year 1877, in volume Ixxxiv
[1878] of Crelle
Journal
p.
242, appears in the
clearest way.
After
we have
introduced the least transfinite
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
cardinal
number N O and derived
its
109
properties that
most readily to hand, the question arises
the higher cardinal numbers and how they
shall show that the transproceed from N O
lie
as
the
to
We
numbers can be arranged according
finite cardinal
to their magnitude,
and, in this order, form, like
the finite numbers, a "well-ordered aggregate" in
an extended sense of the words.
Out of N O pro
ceeds, by a definite law, the next greater cardinal
number & 19 out of this by the same law the next
But even the
greater N 2 and so on.
of
cardinal
numbers
sequence
,
does
not
exhaust
the
We
cardinal number.
a cardinal
which shows
as
conception of transfinite
will prove the existence of
number which we denote by N W and
itself
the numbers & v
way
unlimited
to be the
out of
it
next greater to
proceeds
N X out of N a next greater
in
N^+I,
all
the same
and so on,
without end.
[496] To every transfinite cardinal number a
there is a next greater proceeding out of it accord
ing to a unitary law, and also to every unlimitedly
ascending well-ordered aggregate of transfinite
a next greater pro
ceeding out of that aggregate in a unitary way.
For the rigorous foundation of this matter, dis
covered in 1882 and exposed in the pamphlet
cardinal numbers, {a}, there
Grundlagen
lehre
is
einer allgemeinen
(Leipzig,
1883) and
in
MannicJifaltigkeits-
volume xxi of the
no THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
Mathematische Annalen, we make use of the so"
called "ordinal types
whose theory we have to
set forth in the following paragraphs.
The Ordinal Types
Simply Ordered
Aggregates
We
its
and
elements m, so that, of every two elements
one takes the " lower " and the other the
2
;;/
"
higher
;/z
2,
and
is
;/z
The
l
rank,
3,
mv
and so
say,
that,
is
of three elements
then
3,
;;/
2,
ly
and
of lower
is
s.
relation of
two elements
has the lower rank
cedence and
formulae
if
of lower rank than
of lower rank than
rank than
an aggregate
"simply ordered" if a
order of precedence " (Rangordnung) rules
call
definite
over
of
;;z
the
and
;# 2
in
which
the given order of pre
higher, is expressed by the
in
m^^m^ m
(i)
^m
Thus, for example, every aggregate P of points
defined on a straight line is a simply ordered
aggregate
if,
two points p^ and / 2 belong
whose co-ordinate (an origin and
of every
that one
ing to it,
a positive direction having been fixed upon)
lesser is given the lower rank.
is
the
evident that one and the same aggregate can
"
"
be
simply ordered according to the most different
laws.
Thus, for example, with the aggregate R of
It is
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
numbers //^ (where/ and q are
relatively prime integers) which are greater than o
and less than i, there is, firstly, their "natural"
all
positive rational
order according to magnitude
arranged (and in this order
then they can be
will denote the
we
aggregate by R ) so that, of two numbers f 1 /g 1 and
AA?- f r which the sums p + q and / 2 + ^2 have
that
different values,
sponding sum
Pi
+ 4i = /2 + ^2>
numbers
number
for
which the corre
lower rank, and, if
then the smaller of the two rational
is
less takes the
the lower.
this order of
[497] 1
since
our
to
one and the
aggregate,
precedence,
of rational
of
a
finite
number
same value
p + q only
numbers//^ belongs, evidently has the form
is
R = 0v
o
>*
>
r-
= (!.
*> T> f> ii v, f> T>
)>
where
r,
Always,
ordered
"
< ^+i-
when we speak of a "simply
aggregate M, we imagine laid down a
then,
definite order or precedence of
its elements, in the
sense explained above.
There are doubly, triply, y-ply and a-ply ordered
aggregates, but for the present we will not consider
what follows we will use the shorter
"ordered
aggregate" when we mean
expression
"simply ordered aggregate."
Every ordered aggregate M has a definite "ordinal
type," or more shortly a definite "type," which we
will denote by
them.
(2)
So
in
M.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
H2
By
we understand the general concept which
M if we only abstract from the nature
this
results
from
of the elements m, and retain the order of precedence
Thus the ordinal type M is itself an
ordered aggregate whose elements are units which
have the same order of precedence amongst one
among them.
another as the corresponding elements of M, from
which they are derived by abstraction.
We
and N
aggregates
be
can
into
a bithey
put
(ahnlicK)
univocal correspondence with one another in such
call
similar
manner
two
"
ordered
if
that, if
m^ and m^
are
any two elements
and n and n 2 the corresponding elements of N,
is the
then the relation of rank of m^ to m% in
n
in
a
n
to
Such
N.
of
that
as
same
correspond
2
l
"
ence of similar aggregates we call an
imaging"
on
one
In
these
of
another.
aggregates
(Abbildung)
of
imaging, to every part which obviously
of
also appears as an ordered aggregate
x
corresponds a similar part N x of N.
such an
We
express the similarity of two ordered aggre
and N by the formula
gates
(3)
M oo N.
Every ordered aggregate is similar to itself.
If two ordered aggregates are similar to a third,
they are similar to one another.
shows that two
[498] A simple consideration
same
ordinal type if,
the
.have
ordered aggregates
so
are
similar,
and only if, they
that, of the two
formulae
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
M = N, MooN,
(4)
one
is
If,
113
always a consequence of the other.
with an ordinal type
we also abstract from
the order of precedence of the elements,
is,
types
that
i)
to say, ordered
is
aggregates of equal
always have the same power or cardinal
from the similarity of ordered aggregates
number
On
follows their equivalence.
aggregates
We
at the
the ordinal
M = N,
get
number M of the ordered aggregate M,
same time, the cardinal number of
From M = N always follows
type M.
the cardinal
which
we
may
the other hand, two
be equivalent without being similar.
Greek alphabet
an ordinal type,
will use the small letters of the
denote ordinal types.
we understand by
If a
to
is
(5)
corresponding cardinal number.
The ordinal types of finite ordered aggregates
For we easily convince
offer no special interest.
its
ourselves that, for one and the
number
same
finite
cardinal
y,
simply ordered aggregates are similar
to one another, and thus have one and the same
all
Thus the finite simple ordinal types are
subject to the same laws as the finite cardinal
numbers, and it is allowable to use the same signs
type.
i,
2,
3,
.,
i/,
for
them, although they are
conceptually different from the cardinal numbers.
The case is quite different with the transfinite
ordinal types
for
to
one and the same cardinal
8
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
ii4
number belong innumerably many
different types of
ordered
simply
aggregates, which, in their totality,
constitute a particular "class of types " ( Typenclasse).
Every one of these classes of types is, therefore,
determined by the transfinite cardinal number a
which is common to all the types belonging to the
Thus we call it for short the class of types [a].
That class which naturally presents itself first to us,
and whose complete investigation must, accordingly,
be the next special aim of the theory of transfinite
aggregates, is the class of types [N O ] which embraces
class.
the
all
number
types
NO
with the least transfinite cardinal
From
the
cardinal
determines the class of types
number
tinguish that cardinal
[499]
latter
^
is
has,
[a]
[a]
number
we have
which
which
to
dis
for its part
determined by the class of types [a].
The
the cardinal number which (
the
class
i)
in
so
far
as
it
represents a well-defined
aggregate whose elements are all the types a with
the cardinal number a.
We will see that a is
different from a, and indeed always greater than a.
an ordered aggregate
all the relations of
of
its
elements are inverted, so that
precedence
" lower " becomes
"
"
"higher "and
higher becomes
"lower" everywhere, we again get an ordered
aggregate, which we will denote by
If in
*M
(6)
and
call
the
ordinal type of
(7)
"inverse" of M.
*M,
if
a = M, by
We
denote the
OF TRANSFfNITE NUMBERS
It
may happen
that *a
= a,
as, for
example,
115
in the
case of finite types or in that of the type of the
aggregate of all rational numbers which are greater
than o and
precedence.
the notation
than
less
in
we
This type
their natural order of
will investigate
under
>/.
We
remark further that two similarly ordered
aggregates can be imaged on one another either in
one manner or in many manners in the first case
the type in question is similar to itself in only one
Not only
way, in the second case in many ways.
;
all finite
types, but the types of transfinite
ordered aggregates," which
" well-
occupy us later
" ordinal
numbers,"
are such that they allow only a single imaging on
and which we
themselves.
will
call transfinite
On
other hand,
the
the type
similar to itself in an infinity of ways.
will make this difference clear by
We
r\
is
two simple
By o> we understand the type of a wellexamples.
ordered aggregate
\^l>
in
^2>
>
^vy
)>
which
ev
<
*,+i,
and where v represents all finite cardinal numbers
Another well-ordered aggregate
turn.
L/lJ
-/2>
>
Jv>
in
/>
with the condition
fv -^.A+ii
of the
same type & can obviously only be imaged
ii6
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
on the former
such a
in
way
that
ev
and
are
For e 11 the lowest element
corresponding elements.
in rank of the first, must, in the process of imaging,
be correlated to the lowest element /j of the second,
the next after e in rank (* 2 ) to/2 the next after/x
,
and so
[5]
Every other bi-univocal corre
spondence of the two equivalent aggregates {e v } and
{fv } is not an "imaging" in the sense which we
on.
have fixed above
On
for the
theory of types.
the other hand, let us take an
ordered
aggregate of the form
where
represents
integers, including o,
This
aggregate
element in rank.
a
sum given
in
It is similar to
positive and negative
and where likewise
all
has
Its
no lowest and
type
is,
by the
finite
no highest
definition of
8,
itself in
an infinity of ways.
let us consider an aggregate of the
{/,
For
same type
},
where
fv ^.fv +I
Then the two ordered aggregates can be so imaged
on one another that, if we understand by VQ a
definite
one of the numbers
to the element e v of
<
i/,
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
the
first
Since
the element
is
j/
f^
v
arbitrary,
>
117
of the second corresponds.
here an infinity of
we have
imagings.
The concept of " ordinal type" developed here,
when it is transferred in like manner to " multiply
ordered aggregates," embraces, in conjunction with
the concept of "cardinal number" or "power"
introduced
in
I,
everything capable
numbered (Anzahlmdssige) that
is
of being
thinkable,
and
be further generalized.
It
contains nothing arbitrary, but is the natural ex
It deserves to
tension of the concept of number.
in
this
be
sense
especially
equality (4)
the concept
cannot
emphasized that the criterion of
with absolute necessity from
of ordinal type and consequently
follows
The chief cause of the
permits of no alteration.
s
in
Veronese
errors
G.
grave
Grundziige der
Geometric (German by A. Schepp, Leipzig, 1894)
the non-recognition of this point.
On page 30 the "number (Anzahl oder Za/il)
"
of an ordered group is defined in exactly the same
is
way
a
as
what
simply
\ve
have called the "ordinal type of
"
aggregate
(Zur Lehre vom
ordered
Transfiniten, Halle, 1890, pp.
from the Zeitschr. fur Philos.
for
1887).
must make
68-75
und
reprinted
philos.
Kritik
[SOI] But Veronese thinks that he
an addition to the criterion of equality.
page 31: "Numbers whose units
correspond to one another uniquely and in the
same order and of which the one is neither a part
He
says
on
of the other nor equal to a part of the other are
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
n8
"
equal.
and
circle
the
This definition of equality contains a
thus is meaningless.
For what is
of
meaning
other
"
"not
in this addition
we must
unequal.
of
his
equal to
To answer
of
part
the
this question,
know when two numbers
first
or
are equal
Thus, apart from the arbitrariness
definition
of
it
equality,
presupposes
definition of equality, and this again presupposes
a definition of equality, in which we must know
again what equal and unequal are, and so on ad
After Veronese has, so to speak, given
up of his own free will the indispensable foundation
for the comparison of numbers, we ought not to
infinitunt.
be surprised at the lawlessness with which, later
on, he operates with his pseudo-transfinite numbers,
and ascribes properties to them which they cannot
possess simply because they themselves, in the
form imagined by him, have no existence except
on paper.
Thus, too, the striking similarity of his
"numbers"
in
to the very absurd "infinite
Fontenelle
becomes
numbers"
Geometrie de tlnfini (Paris,
comprehensible.
Recently,
W.
1727)
Killing
has given welcome expression to his doubts con
cerning the foundation of Veronese s book in the
Index lectionutn of the Miinster
Academy
for
1895-
" Numeri
* In the
original Italian edition (p. 27) this passage runs
corrispondono univocamente e nel medesimo ordine,
e di cui 1 uno non e parte o uguale ad una parte dell altro, sono uguali."
t [Veronese replied to this in Math. Ann., vol. xlvii, 1897, pp. 423:
le unita dei quali si
432.
Cf. Killing, ibid., vol. xlviii, 1897, pp.
425-432.]
OF TRANSFIN1TE NUMBERS
119
Addition and Multiplication of Ordinal Types
The union-aggregate (M, N)
M and N can,
and
of
two aggregates
are ordered, be conceived
as an ordered aggregate in which the relations of
precedence of the elements of
among themselves
if
as well as the relations of precedence of the elements
of N among themselves remain the same as in
or
respectively, and
lower rank than
N
N
all
elements of
ordinal type of (M,
M=a
and
If M
M rv> M
and
and
N)
the
so
N) depends only on the ordinal
N=
/3.
Thus, we define:
a+j8=(M,N).
(1)
In the
have a
the elements of N.
all
two other ordered aggregates,
oo N [502] then (M, N) oo (M
are
types
sum
a-f /3
we
call a
the
"augend" and
ft
the
" addend."
For any three types we easily prove the associa
law
tive
(2)
a + (/3 + y)
= (a + /3) + y.
On
the other hand, the commutative law is not
valid, in general, for the addition of types.
We
see this by the following simple example.
If co is the type, already mentioned in
the well-ordered aggregate
7,
of
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
120
then
+co
element,
not equal to co+
is
we have by
(i)
For,
I.
if
/is a new
+<=(/, E),
a>+ i=(E,/>
i
But the aggregate
(/,E)=(/^,^2
is
...,^, ...)
similar to the aggregate E,
and consequently
On the contrary, the aggregates E and (E, f) are
not similar, because the first has no term which is
highest in rank, but the second has the highest
term/
Out
the
of
Thus w+ I is different from w= i +a>.
two ordered aggregates M and N with
types a and
/3
we can
set
up an
ordered
aggregate S by substituting for every element n of
N an ordered aggregate n which has the same
type a as
(3)
M,
so that
M^-a;
and, for the order of precedence in
(4)
we make
S = {M B }
the two rules
two elements of S which belong to
Every
(1)
one and the same aggregate M are to retain in
S the same order of precedence as in M w
of S which belong to two
(2) Every two elements
different aggregates M Wl and M W2 have the same
relation of precedence as n l and n% have in N.
:
OF TRANSFfNITE NUMBERS
121
ordinal type of S depends, as we easily
on
the types a and ft we define
only
The
see,
(5)
./3
= S.
"
multiplicand
[503] In this product a is called the
and ft the "multiplier."
"
In any definite imaging of
on
w let m n be the
element of M w that corresponds to the element m
of
M; we can then
also write
S=
(6)
Consider a
the ordinal type P
a
{;*,}.
third ordered
ft= {m n },
ft
= y,
.
y=
aggregate P
{/} with
then, by (5),
{#/},
(a
ft)
y = {(^),},
But the two ordered aggregates
and
{(#/) }
{^(np \}
are similar, and are imaged on one another if we
regard the elements (m n ) and ^/.\ as correspond
ing.
Consequently, for three types
a, /3,
and y
the associative law
(a./3).y =
(7)
subsists.
From
(i)
and
.(/3.y)
(5) follows easily the dis
tributive law
(8)
in this form, where the factor with two
the multiplier.
On the contrary, in the multiplication of types
as in their addition, the commutative law is not
but only
terms
is
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
122
For example,
by (5),
generally valid.
different types
2.00
and
co.2
are
for,
while
o>
{j, ^ 2
>
-5
^i/>
y i> y2>
>
./
vi
obviously different from w.
If we compare the definitions of the elementary
operations for cardinal numbers, given in
3, with
is
those established here for ordinal types, we easily
see that the cardinal number of the sum of two
types is equal to the sum of the cardinal numbers
of the single types, and that the cardinal number
of the product of two types is equal to the pro
duct of the cardinal numbers of the single types.
Every equation between ordinal types which pro
ceeds from the two elementary operations remains
correct, therefore,
by
their cardinal
if
we
replace in
it
all
the types
numbers.
[504]
The Ordinal Type of the Aggregate R of all
Rational Numbers which are Greater than
o and Smaller than i, in their Natural
r\
Order of Precedence
By R we
understand, as in
7,
the system of
numbers p\q (p and q being relatively
>o and < I, in their natural order
of precedence, where the magnitude of a number
all
rational
prime) which
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
determines
of
by
rj
We
rank.
its
123
denote the ordinal type
*=R.
(1)
But we have put the same aggregate in another
order of precedence in which we call it R
This
order is determined, in the first place, by the
.
magnitude of p + q, and in the second place for
numbers for which p + q has the same value
the
The aggregate
magnitude of p\q itself.
by
R is a well-ordered aggregate of type co
rational
(2)
R = (>
(3)
RO
= ^-
and
Both
!,
r2
.,
R =N
elements,
we
.),
where
rv
<rv+l
have the same cardinal number
since they only differ
of their
rv
order of precedence
in the
since
and,
we
obviously have
also have
R= =N
(4)
7;
Thus the type
r\
belongs to the class of types [N O ].
Secondly, we remark that in R there is neither
an element which is lowest in rank nor one which
Thirdly, R has the property
highest in rank.
that between every two of its elements others lie.
is
This property we express by the words
"
"
everywhere dense (ilberalldichf).
We
will
now show
characterize the type
following theorem
Y\
is
that these three properties
of R, so that we have the
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
124
we have
If
a simply ordered aggregate
such
that
(a)
(b}
M=N
M has
no element which
and no highest
is everywhere dense
lowest in rank,
is
(c)
then the ordinal type of
is
r\
M=iy.
Proof.
Because of the condition (a),
can be
the form [5S]
f a well-ordered
into
brought
aggregate of type u>
form, we denote it by
(5)
We
1,
having fixed upon such a
M
m^
and put
.
.,
.).
have now to show that
MooR
(6)
that
on
= (w
to say,
in such a
is
we must prove that M can be imaged
way that the relation of precedence
any and every two elements in M is the same
two corresponding elements in R.
r in R be correlated to the
the
element
Let
The element r2 has a definite
element m^ in M.
of
as that of the
relation of precedence to r in R.
condition (b), there are infinitely
of
to
Because of the
many elements
which have the same relation of precedence
;% as r2 to 1\ in R of them we choose
let it
that one which has the smallest index in
to
r
it
The
r
correlate
element
has
be m and
2
s
in
in
definite relations of precedence to r
because
of the conditions (b} and
(c)
and r2
there
is
an
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
elements
infinity of
of
relation of precedence to
and r2 to
which have the same
and m in M as r3 to r^
t
them we choose
of
which has the smallest index
it
to r3
According to
of
process
correlation
125
this
in
that
law
let it
be
we imagine
continued.
and correlate
If
the
the
to
elements
of
are correlated, as images, definite elements
which have the same relations of precedence amongst
as the corresponding elements in
one another in
R, then to the element rv+l of R is to be correlated
of M which has the smallest
that element m
lv+l
index
in
same
relations
correlated
definite
of those which have the
of precedence to
in
M
In
as rv+l to rl9 r2
this
elements
lv
the elements
of
iv
.,
rv in R.
we have
manner
to
all
have
in
the elements rv of R, and
the same order of pre
cedence as the corresponding elements r v
we have still to show that the elements
all the
elements
of
M,
or,
what
is
thing, that the series
[506]
is
only a permutation of the series
i,
2, 3,
...
r,
...
in R.
tv
But
include
the
same
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORV
126
We
this
prove
show
the
imaging, that
following element m v+l
in
the elements
if
that,
a complete induction
by
the
also
is
ly
case
we
will
appear
with the
v
Let A be so great that, among the elements
m m^ m^
ly
m, K
the elements
m^
;!,
.,
which, by supposition, appear in the imaging, are
It may be that also m v+l is found
contained.
among them
But
if
then
m v+
m v+
then
not
is
among
has with
ordinal
definite
m v+
appears in the imaging.
the elements
respect
to
in
position
these elements a
;
infinitely
many
have the same ordinal position in R
with respect to rly r2
., rA
amongst which let
rA+0 be that with the least index in R
Then m v+l
elements
in
has, as
make
we can
sure, the same ordinal
easily
position with respect to
in
as rA+(7 has with respect to
*
^1> ^2>
in R.
in the
index
Since
m^ m
imaging,
in
respect to
2,
>
^A+<r-l
tn v
have already appeared
m v+i is that element with the smallest
which has
this
ordinal position with
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
127
Consequently, according to our law of correlation,
Thus,
case too, the element in v+ \ appears
is the element of R which
in this
the imaging, and rA+0
correlated to it.
We
in
is
by our manner of correlation,
M is imaged on the whole
and R are similar aggregates,
see, then, that
the whole aggregate
aggregate
which was to be proved.
From the theorem which we have just proved
result, for example, the following theorems
:
[507] The
negative
ordinal type of the aggregate of all
and positive rational numbers, including
zero, in their natural order of precedence,
is
>/.
The
ordinal type of the aggregate of all rational
numbers which are greater than a and less than b,
in their natural order of precedence, where a and b
are any real numbers, and a<b, is rj.
The ordinal type of the aggregate of all real alge
braic numbers in their natural order of precedence is rj.
The
ordinal type of the aggregate of
all real
alge
numbers which are greater than a and less
than $, in their natural order of precedence, where
a and b are any real numbers and a<b, is
For all these ordered aggregates satisfy the three
conditions required in our theorem for M (see
braic
>/.
C relic s Journal, vol. Ixxvii, p. 258).*
If we consider, further, aggregates with
according to the definitions given in
[*
Cf. Section
of the Introduction.]
the types
written
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
128
/>
those three conditions are also
Thus we have the theorems
we
fulfilled
with them.
(7)
(8)
(9)
(10)
(l+j;+
(II)
The repeated application
every finite number v
1)17=17.
of (7) and (8) gives for
i.v =
(12)
(13)
On
the other hand
we
i,
= n-
easily see that, for
v>
I,
the
types 1+17, 77+1, v.tj, i+fj+i are different both
We have
from one another and from y.
*i+i+n =
(14)
but
+v+
Finally,
Yi,
it
for j/>
i,
is
*l,
different
from
?;.
deserves to be emphasized that
%-f.
(15)
10
[508]
The Fundamental
Series contained in a
Transfinite Ordered Aggregate
Let us consider any simply ordered transfinite
Every part of M is itself an ordered
aggregate M.
aggregate.
For the study of the type M, those
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
129
which have the types w and *o> appear to
parts of
be especially valuable we call them " fundamental
series of the first order contained in M," and the
former of type &> we call an " ascending " series,
the latter of type *&> a " descending " one.
Since
;
we
the consideration of funda
limit ourselves to
mental series of the
order (in later investiga
tions fundamental series of higher order will also
occupy us), we
mental series."
series
"
is
first
here simply call them "funda
Thus an "ascending fundamental
will
of the form
{*},
(1)
where
av
<a +i;
v
"
a " descending fundamental series
{},
(2)
The
in
letter
i/,
where
as well as K
bv
and
X,
>b
/m,
of the form
is
v+l
has everywhere
our considerations the signification of an arbitrary
finite cardinal
number
or of a finite type (a finite
ordinal number).
We call two ascending fundamental series
{a
in
"coherent" (zusammengehorig),
(3)
if,
for
II
{*
{a v } and
in signs
},
every element a v there are elements a\ such
that
<*
and also
for
<
<*\,
every element a
there are elements a^
such that
a
-<^.
9
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
130
Two
in
if
descending fundamental series {b v } and {b
are said to be "coherent," in signs
(4)
{<U
for
II
v}
{* ,},
every element b v there are elements b\ such
that
and
every element b
for
there are elements b^ such
that
b
>V
An
ascending fundamental series {a v } and a
descending one {} are said to be "coherent," in
v
signs
[509]
if
K1MM,
(5)
(a) for all values of v
and
//,
and ($) in M exists at most one (thus either only
one or none at all) element ;/2 such that, for all j/s,
Then we have
A.
If
the theorems
two fundamental series
:
are coherent to a
third, they are also coherent to one another.
B.
same
Two
fundamental
proceeding in the
part of the other are
series
direction of which one
is
coherent.
If there exists
in
an element
;^
which has
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
131
such a position with respect to the ascending funda
mental series {a v } that
(a) for every v
every element
(b) for
we
av
^>-
will call
;;/
elemenf) of {a v } in
{Hauptelement) of
y>V
;//
"limiting element (Grenz-
a
"
that precedes
such that
j/
for
m,
of
;;/
number
there exists a certain
then
and also a " principal element
M." In the same way we call
"
a " principal element of
and also " limiting
"
if
element of {b v } in
these conditions are
satisfied
(a) for
(b)
for
every
number
bv
every element
exists a certain
>-
;;/,
of
that follows
;;/
such that
i/
for
i/^
fundamental series can never have more than
one limiting element
in
but
has, in general,
many principal elements.
We perceive the truth of the following theorems
C. If a fundamental series has a limiting element
in
M,
same
in
all
fundamental series coherent to
it
have the
limiting element in M.
D. If two fundamental series (whether proceeding
the same or in opposite directions) have one and
the same limiting element in M, they are coherent.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
132
If
and
two similarly ordered aggregates,
are
so that
M=M
(6)
and we
upon any imaging of the two aggregates,
then we easily see that the following theorems
fix
hold:
[510]
To
E.
fundamental
every
series
in
corresponds as image a fundamental series in M
and inversely to every ascending series an ascending
one, and to every descending series a descending
one
to coherent fundamental series in M corre
spond as images coherent fundamental series in M
and inversely.
F. If to a fundamental series in M belongs a
,
limiting element in
fundamental
and
in
M, then
series in
inversely
to the corresponding
belongs a limiting element
and these two limiting
elements are images of one another
G. To the principal elements of
in the
imaging.
correspond as
and -inversely.
images principal elements of
consists of principal elements,
If an aggregate
so that every one of its elements is a principal
,
element,
we
call it
an
<c
aggregate which
y
mental series
in
dense
is
every funda
Menge)S
is
there
a limiting element in M,
in itself (insichdichte
If to
" closed
a
we call
(abgeschlossene) aggregate."
An aggregate which is both dense in itself" and
" closed" is called a
If an
"perfect aggregate."
aggregate has one of these three predicates, every
similar
aggregate has
the
same predicate
thus
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
133
these predicates can also be ascribed to the corre
"
types
sponding ordinal types, and so there are
which are dense
perfect
in
types,"
types" ( 9).
For example,
itself," and, as
themselves,"
and
is
also
" closed
types,"
every where-dense
a type which
we showed
in
9,
it
is
is
" dense
also
in
"every
where-dense," but it is not "closed." The types
a) and *co have no principal elements, but uo + v and
+ *fc> each have a principal element, and are
" closed"
The type (0.3 has two principal
types.
elements, but is not "closed"; the type w.$ + v
i/
has three principal elements, and
is
"closed."
.1
The Ordinal Type 6 of the Linear
Continuum X
We
turn to the investigation of the ordinal type
of the aggregate
{x} of all real numbers x, such
that x>_o and <.i, in their natural order of pre
cedence, so that, with any two of its elements x
X=
and x
f
,
xx\
Let the notation
[511]
From
for this
if
type be
the elements of the theory of rational
and irrational numbers we know that every funda
mental series {xv } in X has a limiting element XQ in
X, and that also, inversely, every element x of X
134
is
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
a limiting element of coherent fundamental series
X.
Consequently X is a "perfect aggregate"
and 9 is a " perfect type."
But 9 is not sufficiently characterized by that
besides that we must fix our attention on the
in
The aggregate X contains
following property of X.
as part the aggregate R of ordinal type ^ investi
9, and in such a way that, between any
gated in
t\vo elements ;r and x of X, elements of R lie.
We will now show that these properties, taken
together, characterize the ordinal type 9 of the linear
in an exhaustive manner, so that we
continuum
have the theorem
is such that
If an ordered aggregate
(a) it is
"
perfect, and (b) in it is contained an aggregate S
:
= N O and which bears
between any two elements
m Q and m of M elements of S lie, then M 9.
-If S had a lowest or a highest element,
Proof.
these elements, by ($), would bear the same character
we could remove them from S
as elements of M
without S losing thereby the relation to M ex
Thus, we suppose that S is without
pressed in (b).
with the cardinal number S
such a relation to
M that,
lowest or highest element, so that, by
9, it has
For since S is a part of M,
the ordinal type rj.
between any two elements S Q and s l of S other
elements of S must, by (b\
have S
= NO
by
Thus the aggregates S and
lie.
"similar" to one another.
(2)
S oo R.
Besides,
(b)
we
are
OF TRANSFIN1TE NUMBERS
We
that
it
on any " imaging" of R on S, and assert
"
"
in the
imaging of X on
gives a definite
fix
following manner
Let
135
all
elements of
which, at the same time,
belong to the aggregate R correspond as images to
which are, at the same time,
those elements of
elements of S and, in the supposed imaging of
R on S, correspond to the said elements of R.
which does not .belong
But if;r is an element of
to R, x^ may be regarded as a limiting element of
a fundamental series {xv } contained in X, and this
series can be replaced
series
{rKv }
contained
by a coherent fundamental
in
R.
To
this [5 12 ] corre
sponds as image a fundamental series {sKv } in S and
M, which, because of (a), is limited by an element
Let
that does not belong to S (F,
of
/;/
10).
of M (which remains the same, by
;;/
of
and
D
10, if the fundamental series
E, C,
{#} and {rKv } are replaced by others limited by the
same element *Q in X) be the image of .r in X.
Inversely, to every element m of M which does not
occur in S belongs a quite definite element ;r of X
which does not belong to R and of which m Q is the
this
element
image.
In this
manner
bi-univocal
is
set
between X and
to show that it
gives
an
up,
"
correspondence
and we have now
imaging" of these
aggregates.
This is, of course, the case for those elements of
X which belong to R, and for those elements of
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
136
which belong to S.
Let us compare an element r
of R with an element XQ of X which does not belong
to R
let the corresponding elements of M be s
and m
If r<x^ there is an ascending funda
mental series {rKv }, which is limited by ;r and, from
;
a certain
VQ
on,
r<rK
for
The image of {rKv } in
mental series {s\ v }, which
of
s
M, and we have ( 10)
j
for i/^i/
Thus (
Xy
<
an ascending funda
be limited by an m Q
is
will
s Xv
<m
7) s
for
<^
every
y,
and
r>^r we conclude similarly that ^ >- /;/
Let us consider, finally, two elements x^ and x ^
not belonging to R and the elements m Q and ^/
If
then we show, by
corresponding to them in
an analogous consideration, that, if x^<x ^ then
The proof
finished,
of the similarity of
and we thus have
HALLE, March
1895.
and
is
now
CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE
FOUNDING OF THE THEORY OF
TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
[207]
(SECOND ARTICLE)
Weil-Ordered Aggregates
AMONG simply ordered aggregates "well-ordered
"
deserve a special place
their ordinal
aggregates
we
call
which
"ordinal
numbers," form the
types,
natural material for an exact definition of the
;
higher transfinite cardinal
definition
which
is
which was given us
numbers or powers,
for the least transfinite cardinal
number Aleph-zero by the system of
numbers v ( 6).
We
call
a simply
"well-ordered"
if its
There
is
in
finite
all
ordered aggregate F
7)
elements /"ascend in a definite
(
succession from a lowest/^ in such a
I.
throughout conformable to that
an element
/*,_
way
which
that
is
lowest in
rank.
If
II.
many
F
of
follows
is
any part of
F and
if
has one or
elements of higher rank than all elements
of F which
then there is an element
immediately
after
37
the
totality
so
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
138
that no elements in rank between
R*
in
f and
occur
it
In particular, to every single element
of F, if
is not the highest, follows in rank as next
higher
another definite element
condition II
if
for
F we
7
this results
from the
put the single element f.
Further, if, for example, an infinite series of con
secutive elements
is
then, by the second condition, putting
the totality {^}, there must exist an element
such that not only
elements
for
F in such a way, however, that there
F elements of [208] higher rank than all
contained in
are also in
e (v \
f>
for all values of
in
F which
i/,
*<">
but that also there
satisfies
is
no element
the two conditions
g>
for all values of v
Thus, for example, the three aggregates
where
v+l
* This
definition of "well-ordered aggregates," apart from the
in vol. xxi of the
wording, is identical with that which was introduced
Math. Ann.,
p.
keitshhre, p. 4).
548 (Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannichfaltig[See Section VII of the Introduction.]
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
139
The two first have no highest
the
third
has the highest element c3 in
element,
the second and third 6 l immediately follows all
are well-ordered.
the elements a v
the third
in
the elements a v and
all
immediately follows
b^.
we
extend the use of the
7, and there used
explained in
In the following
>,
c^
will
signs -<^ and
to express the ordinal relation of
two elements, to
groups of elements, so that the formulae
M< N,
M>N
are the expression for the fact that in a given order
all the elements of the aggregate
have a lower,
respectively, rank than
or higher,
all
elements of
the aggregate N.
.A.
Every part F t of a well-ordered aggregate F
has a lowest element.
then
element /i of F belongs to
also the lowest element of F le
In
If the lowest
Proof.
Fx
it
is
the other case, let F be the totality of all elements
of F which have a lower rank than all elements F x
,
then, for this reason,
no element of
lies
between
F and F r
then
it
Thus, if/ follows (II) next after F,
belongs necessarily to F and here takes the
lowest rank.
B.
both
simply ordered aggregate F is such that
and every one of its parts have a lowest
If a
element, then
[209] Proof.
the condition I
is
a well-ordered aggregate.
F has a lowest element,
Since
is
satisfied.
Let F be a part of
HO THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
such that there are
which follow
to
fied,
C.
is
more elements
one or
F which
the element of
is
obviously/*
elements and
in
Fx
be the totality of
the lowest element of
let
all
these
F 1?
then
follows next
Consequently, the condition II is also satis
and therefore F is a well-ordered aggregate.
.
Every part F of a well-ordered aggregate F
also a well-ordered aggregate.
By theorem A, the aggregate F as well
part F" of F (since it is also a part of F)
7
Proof.
as every
has a lowest element
thus
is
well-ordered.
is
by theorem
the
B,
aggregate
D. Every aggregate G which is similar to a wellordered aggregate F is also a well-ordered aggregate.
If
Proof.
element,
concept
then,
of
similar to
we
an aggregate which has a lowest
as immediately follows from the
similarity
it
G ro
are to have
every
element.
7),
has a lowest
F,
and
aggregate N
Since, now,
has,
since
is
it
well-ordered aggregate, a lowest element, the same
Thus also every part G of G has a
holds of G.
lowest element for in an imaging of G on F, to
;
the
aggregate
image,
corresponds a part
G
But, by theorem A, F
therefore also G has.
part of
CNJ
of
as
has a lowest element, and
Thus, both G and every
have lowest elements.
consequently,
E.
so that
is
By theorem
B,
a well-ordered aggregate.
If in a well-ordered
aggregate G,
in place of
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
elements
its
aggregates are sub
F^ and F^ are the
well-ordered
stituted in such a
way
141
that, if
aggregates which occupy the places
of the elements g and g and g -< g
then also
well-ordered
then the aggregate H, arising by com
bination in this manner of the elements of all the
F. -^ F^
well-ordered.
is
aggregates F^,
and every part H x of H have
lowest elements, and by theorem B this characterizes
H as a well-ordered aggregate. For, if gt is the
Both
Proof.
lowest element of G, the lowest element of F^
at the same time the lowest element of H.
further,
we have
part
of
is
If,
H, its elements
which form, when
belong to definite aggregates F^.
taken together, a part of the well-ordered aggre
gate {F^}, which consists of the elements F^ and
is similar to the aggregate G.
If, say,
F^ is the
lowest element of this part, then the lowest element
of the part of H l contained in F^ is at the same
time the lowest element of H.
13
[210]
The Segments
If
gate
then
of
or,
of
Weil-Ordered Aggregates
/is any element
F which
we
the
well-ordered aggre
from the
the aggregate
precede /a
fully,
of
different
will call
F which
more
is
"
initial
of
element f19
all
segment (Abschnitt) of F,"
"the segment of F which
by the element/."
On
elements
is
defined
the other hand, the aggre-
H2
gate
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
R
of
all
the other elements of F, including /,
"
" remainder of
F,
and, more fully, "the
remainder which is determined by the element f."
The aggregates A and R are, by theorem C of
8 and
12, well-ordered, and we may, by
12,
is
write
(1)
F = (A,
(2)
R = (/, R
(3)
<
R),
),
R.
is the part of R which follows the initial element
and reduces to o if R has, besides f, no other
element.
For example,
F = (a ly
a 2y
.,
in the well-ordered
av
b^
a,
aggregate
b^
.,
q, c 2
<:
8 ),
the segment
(a v a 2 )
and the corresponding remainder
are determined
by the element a 3
av
(#i>
a v>
>
the segment
and the corresponding remainder
(6 V b z
are determined
.,
6^
by the element
c v c 2) c3 )
and the segment
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
143
and the corresponding segment
^3)
2>
by the element c2
If A and A are two segments of F,/" and/"
determining elements, and
.
f </,
(4)
then
and
their
is
a segment of A.
the " greater
"
We
segment
of
call
the
"
less,"
A <A.
(5)
Correspondingly we
it is "less" than F
may
say of every
of
that
itself:
A<F.
[2Il] A.
F and G
two
similar well-ordered aggregates
imaged on one another, then to every
If
are
segment A of F corresponds a similar segment B of
G, and to every segment B of G corresponds a
similar segment A of F, and the elements / and g
of F and G by which the corresponding segments
A and B are determined also correspond to one
in the
another
If
Proof.
imaging.
we have two
and
similar simply ordered
imaged on one another, ;;/ and
aggregates
n are two corresponding elements, and
is the
of
all
elements
of
which
precede m
aggregate
the aggregate of all elements of N which
and N correspond
then in the imaging
precede
of
to one another.
For, to every element
and
is
that precedes
;;/
must correspond, by
7,
an element
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
144
ri of
If we apply
n, and inversely.
theorem to the well-ordered aggregates
we get what is to be proved.
that precedes
this general
F and G
B.
any of
well-ordered aggregate
segments A.
Let us suppose that
F no
its
Proof.
F on
imagine an imaging of
A
A
A
the segment
of F, so that
A
A
of
7
is
not similar to
A, then we will
up.
By theorem
set
corresponds to the segment
Thus
ou A.
also
we would have
(X) F and A < A.
From A would result, in the
same manner, a smaller segment A" of F, such that
A" oo F and
and so on.
Thus we would
<
A A
obtain an infinite series
A>A
>A".
A<")>A<" +1 >.
of segments of F, which continually become smaller
will
and all similar to the aggregate F.
We
the elements of
denote by f,
f(v \
/",
F which determine these segments then we would
have
.
f>f
We
of
would therefore have an
infinite part
which no element takes the lowest rank.
in
possible.
such parts of F are not
Thus the supposition of an imaging F on
But by theorem
of
segments leads to a contradiction, and
consequently the aggregate F is not similar to any
one of
of
its
its
segments.
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
Though by theorem B
is
is
similar to every
145
a well-ordered aggregate
not similar to any of its segments, yet, if F is
infinite, there are always [212] other parts of F to
which F is similar. Thus, for example, the aggregate
its
remainders
important that we can put by the
it is
Consequently,
side of
one of
theorem B the following
well-ordered aggregate F is similar to no
part of any one of its segments A.
Let us suppose that F is a part of a
Proof.
C.
F and F PO F. We imagine an
then, by theorem A, to a
imaging of F on F
A
of
the
well-ordered
aggregate F corre
segment
the
let this
as
image
segment F" of F
sponds
segment be determined by the element f of F
segment
of
The element
element of A, and de
of A of which F is a part.
also an
is
termines a segment
supposition of a part F of a segment A of F
77
such that F oo F leads us consequently to a part F
77
such that F ro A.
The same
of
of a segment
7
The
manner of conclusion gives us a
segment
thus,
we
77
of
get,
such that
become smaller
oo
part
777
segments of
7/
.
Proceeding
B, an
F which
continually
A>A >A
of
proof of theorem
as in the
infinite series of
777
A<">
> A<" +1
>
.
.,
10
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
146
and thus an
infinite series of
these segments
which
elements determining
no lowest element, and this is impossible
Thus there is no part F
12.
by theorem A of
in
is
of a segment
Two
D.
of
different
such that
F oo
segments
F.
and
of a well-
F are not similar to one another.
A <A, then A is a segment of the
ordered aggregate
If
Proof.
well-ordered aggregate A, and thus, by theorem B,
cannot be similar to A.
Two
E.
can
similar well-ordered aggregates
on one another only
be imaged
in
F and G
a
single
manner.
Let us suppose that there are two
Proof.
different
imagings of F on G, and let /"be an element of F to
which in the two imagings different images g and
Let
determined by/, and
be the segment of F that
and B the segments of G
that are determined by
and g.
in
is
both
correspond.
BouB
F.
oo B [213] and
If
in
oo B
and consequently
contrary to
theorem D.
F and G
two well-ordered aggregates,
can have at most one segment
a segment
By theorem A,
which
is
are
of
similar to
it.
segment A of F could have two
in G which were similar to it, B
similar to one another, which is
impossible by theorem D.
G. If A and B are similar segments of two wellProof.
If the
segments B and B
and B would be
OF TRANSFIN1TE NUMBERS
ordered
aggregates
F and
F there
every smaller
for
G,
147
is a similar segment
A <A of
G and for every smaller segment B < B of
G a similar segment A < A of F.
The proof follows from theorem A applied to the
similar aggregates A and B.
H. If A and A are two segments of a well-
segment
B <B
of
ordered aggregate F, B and B are two segments
similar to those of a well-ordered aggregate G, and
A <A, then B <B.
proof follows from the theorems F and G.
segment B of a well-ordered aggregate G
similar to no segment of a well-ordered aggregate
The
I.
is
F,
If a
then both every segment
B >B
of
K.
If
for
aggregate
any segment
there
is
Proof.
according
If
G, and also
a similar
We
can image
to
the
element f^ of
of G.
of
law
itself
itself.
of another
inversely,
segment
F and G
following
well-ordered
of
a similar segment
well-ordered aggregate
every segment
then F ou G.
and
are similar neither to a segment of F nor
The proof follows from theorem G.
for
of F,
on one another
Let
the
lowest
correspond to the lowest element g^
is
any other element of F, it
/>/i
determines a segment
To
of F.
this
segment
belongs by supposition a definite similar segment
B of G, and let the element g of G which determines
the segment B be the image of F.
And if g is any
element
of
segment B
that
follows
of G, to which
ly
it
determines a
by supposition a
similar
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
H8
segment
of
belongs.
determines this segment
Let the element /which
be the image of g.
It
easily follows that the bi-univocal correspondence of
F and
defined in this manner is an
in the
imaging
any two elements
of F, g and g [214] the corresponding elements of
G, A and A the segments determined by/ and /
B and IT those determined by g and g and if, say,
sense of
For if/
7.
and/
are
then
A <A.
By theorem H,
then,
we have
B <B,
and consequently
L.
If
for
every segment
of a
well-ordered
a similar segment B of another
well-ordered aggregate G, but if, on the other hand,
aggregate
there
is
one segment of G for which there is
no similar segment of F, then there exists a definite
there
is
at least
segment B x of
such that BjOuF.
Consider the totality of segments of G for
Proof.
which there are no similar segments in F. Amongst
them there must be
Br
of
a least segment which
This follows from the
12,
the aggregate of
fact that,
all
we
will call
by theorem
the elements determin
the
lowest element
segments
of G determined by that element is the
least of that totality.
By theorem I, every segment
ing
these
segment B x
has a
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
of
which
is
greater than
Bx
is
149
such that no segment
Thus the segments
present
which
to
B
G
similar segments of F
correspond
must all be less than B a and to every segment
B < B x belongs a similar segment A of F, because
Bj is the least segment of G among those to which
no similar segments in F correspond.
Thus, for
similar to
it
F.
in
is
of
A of F there is a similar segment B of
and
for
every segment B of B x there is a similar
B!,
of
A
F.
By theorem K, we thus have
segment
every segment
M.
aggregate G has at least
which there is no similar segment
If the well-ordered
one segment
for
in the well-ordered
F must have
Let B x
Proof.
of
of
aggregate F, then every segment
a segment B similar to it in G.
be the least of all those segments
for which there are no similar segments in F. *
were segments in F for which there were no
corresponding segments in G, amongst these, one,
which we will call A x would be the least.
For
of
A
would
then
exist
a
similar
every segment
x
segment of B x and also for every segment of B x a
If there
segment of
would have
similar
Ar
Thus, by theorem K, we
B oo
t
Ar
[215] But this contradicts the datum that for
no similar segment of F.
Consequently,
there cannot be in F a segment to which a similar
segment in G does not correspond.
there
is
See the above proof of L.
150
N.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
If
F and G
gates, then either
(a)
F and G
(b) there
is
are
any two well-ordered aggre
are similar to one another, or
B 5 of G to which
a definite segment
similar, or
is
there
is
a definite
is
similar
to
which
and each of these three cases excludes the two
others.
(c)
Proof.
the three
The
segment
of
relation of
to
can be any one of
every segment A of F there belongs a
segment B of G, and inversely, to every
segment B of G belongs a similar one A of F
(b) To every segment A of F belongs a similar
(a)
To
similar
segment B of G, but there is at least one segment
of G to which no similar segment in F corresponds
B of G belongs a similar
(c) To every segment
is at least one
there
but
segment of
segment A of F,
F to which no similar segment in G corresponds.
The case that there is both a segment of F to
which no similar segment in G corresponds and a
segment of G to which no similar segment in F
;
corresponds
not
is
theorem M.
By theorem K,
in
possible
the
F
In the second case there
segment B x
of
first
it-
case
is
excluded
by
we have
c\jG.
is,
by theorem L, a
such that
B 1 rvjF;
definite
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
and
in the
of
third case there
is
151
a definite segment
such that
A! oo G.
We cannot have F oo G and F oo B
for then
we would have G oo
simultaneously,
Bj, contrary to
theorem
B and, for the same reason, we cannot have both
F oo G and G oo A r Also it is impossible that
both F oo B x and G ro A x for, by theorem A,
from F oo Bj would follow the existence of a
segment B^ of B x such that A x oo B^. Thus we
would have G oo B j, contrary to theorem B.
O. If a part F of a well-ordered aggregate F is
not similar to any segment of F, it is similar to F
;
itself.
By theorem C of 12, F is a well-ordered
If F were similar neither to a segment
aggregate.
of F nor to F itself, there would be, by theorem N,
But \
a segment F x of F which is similar to F.
is a part of that segment A of F which [2 1
6] is
Proof.
determined by the same element as the segment F\
Thus the aggregate F would have to be
F
of
similar to a part of one of its segments,
and
this
contradicts the. theorem C.
H
The Ordinal Numbers
of
Well-Ordered
Aggregates
has a
every simply ordered aggregate
this
definite ordinal type
type is the general con-
By
7,
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
152
if we abstract from the
cept which results from
nature of its elements while retaining their order of
precedence, so that out of them proceed units
which stand in a definite relation of pre
All aggregates which are
cedence to one another.
similar to one another, and only such, have one and
(Einseri)
the
same
ordinal type.
a well-ordered aggregate
and
If a
(3
are
We
F
call the ordinal
type of
" ordinal number."
its
any two ordinal numbers, one can
stand to the other in one of three possible relations.
For if F and G are two well-ordered aggregates
such that
by theorem
then,
of
clusive cases are possible
F oo G
(a)
(b)
13,
There
is
a definite
There
is
segment Bj of
FcoB
(c)
three mutually ex
such that
such that
i;
a definite segment
of
Goo A r
if
As we easily see, each of
F and G are replaced by
these cases
still
subsists
aggregates respectively
Accordingly, we have to do with
mutually exclusive relations of the types a
= /?; in
In the first case
to one another.
similar to them.
three
and
/3
the second
that a
> /?.
we say that a</3; in the third we say
Thus we have the theorem
:
OF TRANSFINITE NUMHKKS
A.
If a
and
two ordinal numbers, we
are any
ft
have either a = ft or a<ft or a
From
the
follows easily
B.
if
and
/3
and majority
we have
If
<
> ft.
of minority
definition
153
three ordinal numbers
< y,
then a
a,
ft,
y,
and
< y.
Thus the ordinal numbers form, when arranged
order of magnitude, a simply ordered aggregate
appear later that it is a well-ordered aggre
in
will
it
gate.
The
operations of addition and multipli
cation of the ordinal types of any simply ordered
[217]
aggregates, defined in
8,
to the ordinal numbers.
and
are, of course, applicable
If
a=F
and
= G, where
are two well-ordered aggregates, then
a + /8 = (F, G).
0)
The aggregate
of union (F, G)
thus
aggregate too
well-ordered
theorem
C.
/3
is
obviously a
the
we have
The sum
of
two ordinal numbers
is
also an
ordinal number.
In the
ft
sum
ft,
is
called the
"augend" and
the "addend."
Since
is
a segment of (F, G),
a<a +
(2)
On
the other hand,
is
mainder of (F, G), and
13,
we have always
/3.
not a segment but a re
may
thus,
as
we saw
be similar to the aggregate (F, G).
in
If this
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
154
not the case,
is
to a
is,
by theorem
segment
of
13, similar
Thus
of (F, G).
/3<
(3)
Consequently we have
D. The sum of the two
:
ordinal
numbers
is
always
greater than the augend, but greater than or equal
to the addend.
If we have a + /3 = a +
y, we always
have
,#
= y.
In general a + /3 and ft + a are not equal.
On
the other hand, we have, if y is a third ordinal
number,
(a
(4)
That
to say
is
+ j8) + y = a + (j8 + y).
In the addition of ordinal numbers the associa
E.
law always holds.
tive
we
If
aggregate
every element g of the
an aggregate F^ of type a,
substitute
for
/?
of type
12, a well-ordered
by theorem E of
is
H
whose
aggregate
type
completely determined
by the types a and ft and will be called the product
we
get,
a.jS:
F,= a,
(5)
a./3 = H.
(6)
The product
F.
of two ordinal numbers
is
also
an ordinal number.
In the product a
and
/3
./3,
is
called the
"
<c
multiplicand
the " multiplier."
In general a./3and /3.aare not equal.
have
8)
But we
OF TRANSFINITE NT MINERS
(7)
(a
That
is
to say
y=a
ft).
155
(ft. y).
[218] G. In the multiplication of ordinal numbers
the associative law holds.
The
only
law
distributive
is
form
in the following
valid,
in
general
8),
a.(/8 + y) = a./3 + a.y.
(8)
With reference to the magnitude of the product,
the following theorem, as we easily see, holds
H. If the multiplier is greater than I, the product
of two ordinal numbers is always greater than
:
the multiplicand, but greater than or equal to the
we have
multiplier.
If
follows that
= y.
/3
On
the other hand,
a.
(9)
we
1
a./3
= a.y,
then
it
always
evidently have
1
.o = a.
We
have now to consider the operation of sub
If a and ft are two ordinal numbers, and
traction.
a is less than ft, there always exists a definite
ordinal
number which we
satisfies
the equation
a
(10)
For
we
call
if
G=
/3,
will
+ (j8-a) =
has a segment
call
ft
a,
which
such that
B=u
the corresponding remainder S, and have
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
156
and therefore
)8-a = S.
(ii)
The determinateness
of
/3
the fact that the segment
one (theorem
definite
also
a appears clearly from
of G is a completely
of
13),
and consequently
is
uniquely given.
emphasize the following
We
follow from
and (10)
(4), (8),
formulae,
which
(12)
(13)
important to reflect that an infinity of
ordinal numbers can be summed so that their sum
It
is
is
a definite ordinal
number which depends on the
sequence of the summands.
Pv
is
any simply
/^2>
If
infinite series
P^J
of ordinal numbers, and
we have
A,=G,,
(14)
[219] then, by theorem
G = (G
(IS)
also
is
1,
G2
well-ordered
E
.
of
.
.,
G,,
.)
aggregate whose ordinal
number represents the sum
We
12,
of the
numbers
/?.
have, then,
(16)
and,
as
product,
we easily see from
we always have
the
definition
of a
OF TRANSFINITE NL MlUiKS
y.
(17)
If
we
157
put
(18)
then
(19)
We
<*
= (&!, G 2
G,).
have
a v +i>a v
(20)
and, by (10), we can express the numbers
the numbers a v as follows
/3^
by
(21)
The
fti=ai
+i
= a ,+i
av
series
!,
a2
.,
a,,
thus represents any infinite series of ordinal numbers
which satisfy the condition (20) we will call it a
;
"fundamental series" of ordinal numbers ( 10).
Between it and /3 subsists a relation which can be
expressed in the following manner
:
(a)
i
The number
greater than
because the aggregate (G v
G2
a,,
.,
for
I(
every
whose
),
number is a v is a segment of the aggregate
which has the ordinal number /3
ordinal
(3
is
any ordinal number less than
from a certain v onwards, we always have
(6)
For,
If
/3
since
is
/3
<
/3,
there
is
segment B
/3,
then,
of the
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORV
58
The element of
aggregate G which is of type /3
G which determines this segment must belong to
.
one of the parts G^
then
also a
is
consequently
j3
we
will call this part
G2
segment of (G 1}
<a
.,
VQ
But
G,,
),
and
Thus
av
>P
for V^VQ.
Thus
/3 is
the ordinal
number which
follows next
order of magnitude after all the numbers a v
accordingly we will call it the "limit" (Grenze) of
the numbers a v for increasing v and denote it by
in
Lim
av
(22)
so that,
Lim
0(l,
by (16) and (21)
= a1 + (
aI ) +
+ (a v+
a,)
We may
express what precedes in the
theorem
following
1.
To every fundamental series {c^} of ordinal
numbers belongs an ordinal number Lim a v which
[22O]
follows next, in order of magnitude, after all the
numbers a v it is represented by the formula (22).
;
by y we understand any constant ordinal
number, we easily prove, by the aid of the formulae
(12), (13), and (17), the theorems contained in the
If
formulae
(23)
Lim
V
(24)
We have
Lim y
av
= y Lim
.
already mentioned in
av
7 that all simply
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
159
ordered aggregates of given finite cardinal number
This may
v have one and the same ordinal type.
be proved here as follows.
Every simply ordered
aggregate of
finite cardinal
number
is
a well-ordered
one of its parts, must
it, and every
aggregate
and this, by theorem B
have a lowest element,
;
of
for
characterizes
12,
it
as a well-ordered aggregate.
The types
of finite simply ordered aggregates are
But
thus none other than finite ordinal numbers.
two
numbers and /3 cannot belong
For if, say,
number
different ordinal
same
to the
finite
cardinal
j/.
a</3 and G = /3, then, as we know, there exists a
segment B of G such that B = a. Thus the aggre
gate G and its part B would have the same finite
But this, by theorem C of 6,
cardinal number v.
is
the finite ordinal numbers
Thus
impossible.
coincide in their properties with the finite cardinal
numbers.
The
case
is
quite
different with the transfinite
to
one and the same transfinite
ordinal numbers
cardinal
number
numbers
which
system.
We
class
[a]
of
Z(a),"
7.
a belong an infinity of ordinal
form a unitary and connected
will
and
it
call this
is
The next
system the "number-
a part of the class of types
object of our consideration is
the number-class Z(N O ), which we will call "the
second number-class." For in this connexion we
understand by "the first number-class" the totality
of finite ordinal numbers.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
i6o
[221]
The Numbers
Second Number- Class Z(N O )
of the
The second number-class Z(N O )
of ordinal
is the totality
{a}
a of well-ordered aggregates of
types
the cardinal
number N O
6).
The second number-class
w = Lim v.
has a least number
A.
By
Proof.
we understand
co
the
type of the
well-ordered aggregate
F = (/1
(1)
where
runs through
w=F
6)
w=N
d>
is
number
and indeed the
number
less
a segment of
of the second number-class,
least.
For
it
must
than
o>,
But
if
finite ordinal
By
the
o>,
number
and thus
definition
of
Lim
V
obviously have
co
= Lim
is
any ordinal
14) be the type of
>
v.
fore there are no transfinite
are less than
has only segments
A = C/i, /2>
with
numbers and
(7)
(4)
Thus
ordinal
all finite
(3)
(
.),
/,</,+!
(2)
Therefore
and
...,/,,..
a,
v.
o>
fv)y
Thus y = v. There
ordinal numbers which
is
av
the least of them.
given
in
14,
we
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
161
is any number of the second number-class,
number a -M follows it as the next greater
number of the same number-class.
B. If a
the
Let F be a well-ordered aggregate of
Proof.
the type a and of the cardinal number N O
:
(5)
F=
(6)
We
have, where by
Since
is
is
segment of
understood a new element,
(F, g),
we have
a+ > a,
I
(8)
We
also have
= *o (6).
Therefore the number
a+i
belongs to the second
Between a and a+ I there are no
ordinal numbers
for every number
y [222] which
is less than a-f- i
corresponds, as type, to a segment
of (F, g), and such a segment can only be either
F or a segment of F. Therefore y is either equal
number-class.
to or less than
a.
is any fundamental series
a,,,
numbers of the first or second number-class, then
the number Lim a v ( 14) following them next in
C.
If a v a a
>
>
of
order of magnitude belongs to the second numberclass.
Proof.
By
14 there
results
from the fundaii
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
62
Lim
mental series {<} the number
<*
if
we
set
up
another series
= a1
/5i
/3 19
/3 2 ,
^ = 01
G
then, Gj,
2
gates such that
If,
.an
-,
G^,
.,
#,,
.,
where
.,
&+1 = <*+!
a,,
are well-ordered aggre
3,,
then also
G = (G!, G 2
is
.,
y,
.)
a well-ordered aggregate and
Lim
J/
= G.
i/
It
only remains to prove that
Since the numbers
the
first
/3
G <N
V
to
...,$,,... belong
/3 2 ,
or second number-class,
we have
>
and thus
G:<N O N O = NO.
But, in any case,
so the case
G < NO
is
is
a transfinite aggregate,
excluded.
We will call
of
"
two fundamental series {a v } and
numbers of the first or second number-class (
coherent," in signs
if for every
such that
(10)
10)
K)
(9)
and
II
{;},
there are finite numbers X
a\>a
A^Xo,
and ^o
OF TRANSFINTTE NUMBERS
163
and
a^>a
(ll)
The
[223] D.
M^Mo-
,,
limiting
numbers Lim
av
and Lim a
belonging respectively to two fundamental series
and fa ,,} are equal when, and only when,
{a,,}
(Mil {a
,}.
For
Proof.
Lim a v =
Lim
/3 y
sake
the
a
= y.
l/
we
shortness
of
We
will
first
put
suppose
we
= y.
For
were not equal to y, one of these two numbers
would have to be the smaller.
Suppose that /3<y.
From a certain v onwards we would have a v >/3
(
14), and consequently, by (11), from a certain
onwards we would have a M >/3.
But this is
that
{a,}
II
{a
v}
then
assert
that
/3
if /3
IUL
because
impossible
/3=Lim
Thus
<*.
for
all
/x s
we have
If,
a^</8.
we suppose
we must conclude
inversely,
that
a,,<y>
E.
class
i/
= y,
then, because
that, from a certain \
because a v </3, we must
onwards, a\>a vj and,
conclude that, from a certain
That
/3
is
to say, {a,}
If a is
and
+ a = a,
Proof.
i/
||
/m
onwards, a _>a
fj
{(/}.
any number of the second numberany finite ordinal number, we have
and consequently also a
We
i/
= a.
will first of all convince ourselves of
the correctness of the theorem
when a = w.
have
= (/! A
= (fv *
^o
<*>
*X
>.
Vo)>
We
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
64
and consequently
But
if
ct
>
o>,
we have
a
+a=
i/
If
F.
I/O
ft)
H~
w ) + (a
ft)),
"~
ft>)
= + (a
= a.
number, we have
0).
In order to obtain an aggregate of the
we have to substitute for the single
Pioof.
co
type
elements / of the aggregate (fv
i/
a>)
ft)
ordinal
finite
any
is
i/o
(i/o
= a> + (a
aggregates
(^ v g
Vt
^^
/ ...,/...)
We
8,
of the type
i/
thus obtain the aggregate
which
is
obviously similar to the aggregate
Consequently
VQ
The same
By
(24) of
result
14
CO
CO.
obtained more shortly as follows.
is
we
co=Lim
have, since
v
t/
co
= Lim
i/o
i/.
i>
On
the other hand,
and consequently
Lim
V
so that
i/o
i/
= Lim =
j/
j/,
OF TRANSF1NITE NUMBERS
We
[224] G.
165
have always
.
(a
+y
= aa>,
)a)
where a is a number of the second number-class
and VQ a number of the first number-class.
We have
Proof.
Lim
i/
o>.
By
(24) of
we
14
have, consequently,
But
= av +
Now we
have, as
I/Q.
is
easy to
{ay
+v
||
see,
{ai/},
and consequently
Lim
H.
(a
+ v V Lim
If a is
=:=
any number of the second number7
class, then the totality {a } of numbers a of the
first and second number-classes which are less than
a form, in their order of magnitude, a well-ordered
aggregate of type a.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
66
Let F be a well-ordered aggregate such
If
let/j be the lowest element of F.
any ordinal number which is less than a, then,
Proof.
that
a
is
F = a, and
14, there is a definite
by
segment
of
such
that
and inversely every segment
type
A =a
number
number-class.
since
For,
either a finite cardinal
a<a
determines by its
of the first or second
F = NO
number
or
NO
determined by an element/
is
inversely every element/" ]>-/i of
of F.
Iff and/" are
segment
can only be
The segment
>/i
of F, and
a
F determines
A
two elements of
which follow /j in rank, A and A" are the
segments of F determined by them, a and a" are
F
their ordinal types, and, say/* -*^./"", then,
A <A"
and consequently a
< a".
[225]
by
If,
13,
then,
F = (/i, F we obtain, when we make the
element/" of F correspond to the element a of {a },
we
put
),
Thus we have
an imaging of these two aggregates.
But F
=a
and,
I,
by theorem E, a
i=a.
Con
sequently
{a }=a.
Since a = N
the theorems
I.
first
we
also have {a
=N
thus
we have
The aggregate {a} of numbers a of the
and second number-classes which are smaller
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
167
than a number a of the second number-class has
number N O
K. Every number a of the second number-class
either such that (a) it arises out of the next
the cardinal
is
smaller
number a. l by the addition
a
or
()
there
of the
first
= a_i+
of
I,
is a fundamental series
{a v } of numbers
or second number-class such that
a= Lim
av
a= F.
Let
Proof.
If
g which
g\ where A is
has an element
highest in rank, we have F = (A,
the segment of F which is determined by g.
have then the first case, namely,
is
There
which
But
therefore,
exists,
We
next smaller number
that called a v
is
if
totality {a
has no highest element, consider the
of numbers of the first and second
which are
number-classes
theorem H, the aggregate
magnitude,
is
the numbers a
theorem
I,
the form
out from a
a
lt
smaller
than
arranged
in
similar to the aggregate
},
consequently, none
is
By
a.
order of
;
among
By
greatest.
the aggregate {a | can be brought into
If we set
v } of a simply infinite series.
the next following elements a 2 a 3
. .
which is different from the order of
>
in this order,
magnitude,
but
in
will,
in general,
every case,
in
be smaller than a\
the further course
of the
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
68
process, terms will occur which are greater than a\
a\ cannot be greater than all other terms,
because among the numbers {<* } there is no
Let that number a v which has the least
greatest.
for
index of those greater than a\ be a p
Similarly,
a p be that number of the series {(/} which has the
.
let
least
index of those which are greater than a
proceeding
in this
way, we
By
get an! infinite series of
increasing numbers, a fundamental series in fact,
[226]
We
have
<p < PV
1 <
Pz < Pz <
<
<
a/ P <
i
p
3
V<
< a p, < a
and since obviously
always
v <f
pv
>
if
we always have
^
<a
f
.
Pv
Hence we see that every number a v) and conse
quently every number a <a, is exceeded by numbers
a
for sufficiently great values of
v.
But a
is
the
number which,
follows
all
in respect of magnitude, immediately
the numbers a and consequently is also
,
the next greater number with respect to
therefore,
we
put a
= a1
1
=a v+
Pv
a= Lim
av
i,
all
If,
we have
is
evident
theorems B, C,
., K it
that the numbers of the second number-class result
From
the
NUMBERS
OP TRANSFINITE
169
Some numbers,
from smaller numbers in two ways.
which we call " numbers of the first kind (Art}," are
got from a next smaller number a- l by addition of I
according to the formula
a
=a- +
1
The other numbers, which we call "numbers of the
second kind," are such that for any one of them
there is not a next smaller number a_ 1} but they
from
arise
fundamental
series
as
{a^}
limiting
numbers according to the formula
a
= Lim
av
Here a
is
number which
the
of magnitude to
call these
We
follows next in order
all the numbers a v
two ways in which greater numbers
.
the first and the
proceed out of smaller ones
second principle of generation of numbers of the
second number-class."*
*
l6
The Power
to the
of the Second Number- Class is equal
Second Greatest Transfinite Cardinal
Number Aleph-One
Before
we
turn to the more detailed considera
numbers of
tions in the following paragraphs of the
the
second number-class and of the
rule
them, we
*
will
laws
which
answer the question as to the
[Cf. Section
VII of the Introduction.]
70
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
number which
cardinal
Z(N )={a}
of
all
is possessed by the aggregate
these numbers.
[227] A. The totality {a} of all numbers a of
the second number-class forms, when arranged in
order of magnitude, a well-ordered aggregate.
If we denote by A a the totality
Proof.
of
numbers of the second number-class which are
smaller than a given number a arranged in order
,
of magnitude, then
a is a well-ordered aggregate
of type a
of
This results from theorem
u>.
14.
The aggregate
numbers a of the first and second
number-class which was there denoted by {(/}, is
compounded out of {i/} and A a so that
of
{a
= (M, A a
(a
).
Thus
M+A
and since
{a }=a,
{v}=oo,
we have
Aa = a
Let
co.
be any part of {} such that there are
numbers in {a} which are greater than all the
numbers of J. Let, say, a be one of these numbers.
Then
J is also a part of
part that at least the
than
all
number
the numbers of
ordered aggregate, by
such a
A^+i, and indeed
J.
a of
o
Since
12 a
A ao+1 is
A ao+1 is
number a
greater
a well-
of
and therefore also of {a}, must follow next
Thus the condition II of
the numbers of J.
A ao+
to
12
i,
all
is
OF TRANSFIN1TE NUMBERS
the condition I of
the case of {a}
also fulfilled because {a} has the least number
fulfilled in
is
171
Now,
{a}
the
if
to the well-ordered aggregate
A and C of
12, we get the
theorems
numbers of the
totality of different
Every
and second number-classes has a
C.
to.
we apply
following theorems
B.
12
Every
least
numbers of the
totality of different
and second number-classes arranged
first
number.
in their
first
order of
magnitude forms a well-ordered aggregate.
We
will
now show
number-class
is
is
that the power of the second
different from that of the first, which
NO-
D.
The power
of the totality
a of the second number-class
is
a } of all
numbers
not equal to N O
If {oj were equal to N O we could bring
Proof.
the totality {a} into the form of a simply infinite
,
series
Vi, 72>
such
that
would
{y^}
>
VIM
represent
the
totality of
numbers of the second [228] number-class in an
order which is different from the order of magni
tude, and {y,,} would contain, like {a}, no greatest
number.
Starting from y v let y p be the term of the series
which has the least index of those greater than y x
y p the term which has the least index of those
,
and so on.
greater than y p
of
series
increasing numbers,
,
We
get an infinite
172
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
such that
< P2 < Ps
By theorem C
of
<p < PV+I <
S of the
which
greater than
there would be a definite
15,
number
is
second number-class, namely,
all
numbers yp
Consequently
we would have
But {y v } contains all numbers of the
every v.
second number-class, and consequently also the
for
number
thus
which equation
8
> yv
we would
is
have, for a definite
inconsistent
The supposition
{a}
with the relation
= NO consequently
leads
to a contradiction.
E.
Any
totality
\/3}
of different
the second number-class has,
the cardinal
number N O
if it
is
numbers
/3
of
infinite, either
number
or the cardinal
{a}
of the second number-class.
The aggregate {/3},
Proof.
order of magnitude, is, since it
is
{a},
in its
a part of the wellof
13,
by theorem
segment A a which
ordered aggregate
similar either to a
when arranged
is
the totality
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
of
all
less
173
numbers of the same number-class which are
than a
>
or to the totality {a} itself.
proof of theorem A, we have
Thus we have
either {/3}
=a
a>
or {/3}
equal to
either
is
order of magnitude,
As was shown in the
in their
arranged
consequently
{/?}
But a
either a finite cardinal
a>
is
equal to N O (theorem
here excluded
infinite
because
aggregate.
of
is
Thus the
o>
or {a}.
number or
The first case
15).
{/3}
ct
= { a }, and
is
is
supposed to be an
cardinal
number
{/3}
either equal to N O or {a}.
F. The power of the second number-class {a} is
the second greatest transfinite cardinal number
is
Aleph-one.
[229] Proof.
There
is
no cardinal number
For if
greater than N O and less than {a}.
not, there would have to be, by
2, an infinite part
which
is
of {a} such that {/3]=a.
But by the theorem
the
has
either the cardinal
just proved,
part {/3}
{/3}
number NO or the
cardinal
number
a }.
Thus the
number {a} is necessarily the cardinal
number which immediately follows N O in magnitude
we call this new cardinal number N r
In the second number-class Z(N O ) we possess,
cardinal
consequently, the natural representative for the
second greatest transfinite cardinal number Alephone.
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
174
17
The Numbers
convenient to
It is
Form o>% +
of the
make
fcy
1
i/
+^.
ourselves familiar, in the
place, with those numbers of Z(N O ) which are
first
whole algebraic functions of finite degree of o>.
Every such number can be brought and brought
in only one way
into the form
(
= fc^O H~
where
VQ
^u,
^D ^2>
that
>
are finite
*V
ma y
IJL
HI +
and
a/* v
+ VIM
different
from
zero,
but
This rests on the fact
ke zero.
(2)
if
~
ft/*
+ o/v = ft/v,
<i& and j^>o, j/>o.
For,
by
(8) of
14,
we
have
+ W^ ~ ^
and,
by theorem
E
V
Thus,
in
of
+ O)^
I/),
15,
~^
ft/*
"^
I/.
an aggregate of the form
those terms which are followed towards the right
by terms of higher degree in o) may be omitted.
This method may be continued until the form given
all
in (i) is reached.
(3)
We
will also
emphasize that
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
Compare, now, the number
same kind
the
(4)
If
fji
(2)
\fr
+ \^ =
If
[230]
(i)
pQ +
~
(x)
of
+ p\-
Pl~^~
different and, say, /*<X,
and therefore
*//,
/x
x/r
and X are
<
with a number
<f>
175
= X,
i/
VO<PQ> we have by
</><\{s.
and p are
we have by
different, and, say,
(2)
and therefore
finally,
If,
but
is
i/^
different
from
and,
say,
iv </><,,
we
have by (2)
and therefore again
^<v-.
Thus, we see that only
in the case of
identity of the expressions
represented by
The
result
addition of
</>
\fs
complete
can the numbers
equal.
leads to the following
\fs
and
(a) If
(b)
them be
and
If
/x<X, then, as
yu
= X,
then
we have remarked
we have
above,
THE FOUNDING OF THE THE OR Y
76
If
(c)
w>\, we have
In order to carry out the multiplication of and ^,
that, if p is a finite number which is
we remark
different
from zero, we have the formula
(5)
= co%p + ^-V1 +
+ iv.
from the carrying out of the sum
+ +
consisting of p terms
+0. By means
of the repeated application of the theorem G of
15 we get, further, remembering the theorem F
It easily results
of
iS,
(6)
0a>
and consequently
= a/* +1
also
(7)
By the
we have
distributive
Thus the formulae
result
law,
(4), (5),
numbered
and
(8)
Ifp x
(fr)
If PA
= o, we
is
have
equal to zero,
14,
(7) give the following
(a)
of
we have
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
[231]
We
177
arrive at a remarkable resolution of
the numbers
in
Let
the following manner.
(8)
.where
and
KO
*!,..., K T are
different
=
By
from
zero.
(ft/*
*!
finite
+ ft/% +
+ ft/^
T )(ft/*~
%+
the repeated application of this formula
But, now,
AC
is
a finite
so that
(9)
The
x
(ft>
number which
is
ft>V+
if
numbers which are
Then we have
)-
we
get
i)/c,
different
from zero
= W^/cT (ft)^-
factors
o>
-f-i
which occur here are
all
irre-
can be represented in this
number
If /X T = O, then
product-form in only one way.
is of the first kind, in all other cases it is of the
soluble, and a
(f>
second kind.
The apparent
deviation of the formulae of this
paragraph from those which were given
Ann., vol. xxi, p. 585 (or Grundlagen,
in
Math.
p.
41),
is
merely a consequence of the different writing of the
product of two
numbers
we now
put the multi12
78
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
plicand on the left and the multiplicator on the
right, but then we put them in the contrary way.
18
The Power * y a
in the
Domain
Second
of the
Number- Class
be a variable whose domain consists of the
Let
numbers of the
and second number-classes
first
in
Let y and S be two constants belong
cluding zero.
the
to
same
domain, and let
ing
y>i.
c!>0,
We
can then assert the following theorem
A. There is one wholly determined one-valued
:
function /() of the variable
/(o) = <5.
(a)
(6)
such that
and
If
"
are
any two values of
and
f<f,
then
/(f)</(f)-
is
For every value of
[232]
(c)
(d) If
{,} is any fundamental
and if we have
one
we have
series,
then
also,
=Lim
,,
then
[Here obviously
it is
Potenz and not Mdchiigkeit. }
if
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
By
Proof.
and
(a)
8>o
and, because
(V),
and
179
we have
y>
we have
i,
Thus the function /(() is wholly determined for the
domain <w.
Let us now suppose that the theorem
valid for all values of g which are less than a,
where a is any number of the second number-class,
is
then
first
it
is
kind,
also valid for
we have from
so that the conditions
But
a fundamental
for g<^ a.
if
is
For
<.u.
(c)
if
is
of the
and (d) are satisfied
(<$>), (c)
of the second kind and {a,,} is
y
series such that
follows from (b) that also {/(<*)}
and from (d) that f(a) =
series,
Lim
is
av
=a
then
it
a fundamental
Lim f(a v ).
If
we
take another
Lim
= a,
fundamental series
{(/}
such
that
because of (b\ the two funda-
then,
mental series (f(a v )} and {f(a
thus also /(a)
= Lim
f(a
v }.
v )}
The
are coherent, and
value of f(a) is,
consequently, uniquely determined in this case also.
If a is any number less than a, we easily convince
ourselves that /(
and (d) are also
< /( a ).
The
conditions (), (c\
Hence follows
satisfied for ^<"a.
the validity of the theorem for all values of
For
if there were
values
of
for
which it
exceptional
did not hold, then, by theorem
of
16,
one of
i8o
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
we
them, which
would have to be the
least.
the theorem would be valid for
<a,
but not for g<.a, and this would be in contradiction
with what we have proved.
Thus there is for the
whole domain of
one and only one function f(g)
which satisfies the conditions (a) to (d).
will call a
Then
[233] If
we
attribute to the constant 8 the value
and then denote the function f(g) by
we can formulate
B.
If
is
the following theorem
any constant greater than
:
which
belongs to the first or second number-class, there
is a wholly definite function
y of f such that
:
(a)
(b)
y=i;
f <"theny <y";
If
For every value of we have y +1 = yy
(d) If {,} is a fundamental series, then
such a series, and we have, if =Lim
(c)
is
equation
|y*"}
,,
the
y = Lim y".
V
We
C.
in
can also assert the theorem
I
f()
is
the function of
which
is
characterized
theorem A, we have
we pay
14,
(24) of
we easily convince ourselves that the function &y*
satisfies, not only the conditions (a), ($), and (c)
Proof.
If
of theorem A,
attention
to
but also the condition (d) of this
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
On
theorem.
181
account of the uniqueness of the
must therefore be identical with &y*.
D. If a and /3 are any two numbers of the first
or second number-class, including zero, we have
function /(f),
it
We
consider the function
Proof.
to the fact that, by formula (23)
attention
Paying
of
M,
Lim
(a
,)
= a + Lim
we
,,
recognize that
conditions
(p(g)
satisfies the following four
(a)
(b)
(c)
(aT)
Lim
For every value of we have </,(+ i) =
If {^} is a fundamental series such
= we have
,
that
By theorem C we
have,
when we put
<5
= ya
0(a=yVIf
we
put
E.
If a
= /3
and
in this,
/3
are
we have
any two numbers of the
first
or
second number-class, including zero, we have
Let us consider the
remark
and
that, by (24) of
[234] Proof.
y*
function
14,
we
82
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
always have Lim
a,=o Lim
theorem D, assert the following
0) ^(o)=i
then we can, by
v
:
Iff<r, then^(f)<V<f);
(V)
For every value of f we have \fs(+ i ) = VKOy"
(d) If {,} is a fundamental series, then {^(^)| is
also such a series, and we have, if
=Lim,, the
(c)
equation
VKO
Thus, by theorem C,
and y a
if
we
substitute in
it
for
for y,
On the magnitude of y^ in comparison with
can assert the following theorem
we
F.
If
Proof.
y>
i,
we
have, for every value of
= o and
In the cases
We now
immediately evident.
holds for all values of
is
the theorem
show
that,
if it
^ which are smaller than a
also holds for
=a.
given number a> I, it
If a is of the first kind,
we
have, by supposition,
a-i<y*-\
and consequently
-ir
<y
a~
y=r
a
-
Hence
a
y >
Since both a_ a and y
a-i
I
+ a-i(y~i).
are at least equal to
a_!+ I =a, we have
y
=a
i,
and
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
If,
on the other hand, a
of the second kind and
is
= Lim
183
a vy
then, because a v
< a, we
have by supposition
a
av
.fi
"*
Consequently
Lim
that
is
a v <.
to say,
Lim y a
< ya
now, there were values of ^
If,
one of them, by theorem
be the
If this
least.
would have,
for
",
which
for
of
16,
number
is
would have to
denoted by
a,
we
<a,
^y*;
[235]
but
a>y
a
,
which contradicts what we
Thus we have
have
proved
above.
for all values of
19
The Normal Form of the Numbers
Second Number- Class
of the
Let a be any number of the second number-class.
The power
CD*
will be, for sufficiently great values
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
84
By theorem F
greater than a.
always the case for
of
of
18, this is
>a but in general
happen for smaller values of
By theorem B of 16, there must be,
values of
for
one which
is
will also
among
the
which
We
the least.
will
we easily convince ourselves
number of the second kind.
we would
it
have, since
/3 V
denote
that
If,
it
it
by
/3,
and
cannot be a
indeed,
we had
< /3,
(/v <"
a,
and consequently
Lim oA
<: a.
Thus we would have
co^^a,
whereas we have
a>0
Therefore
f3
is
of the
> a.
first
kind.
We
denote
= a +i,
/3
/3-j
and consequently can
by
is
a wholly determined number a
assert that there
of the first or second number-class which satisfies
the two conditions
a
so
that
( I)
From
<. a,
eo%>
the second condition
> a.
we conclude
that
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
does not hold for
values of
all finite
y,
for
Because of
(i),
if
185
it
did
we would have
Lim
= o)a
ft)%
ft)
<. a.
The
number
least finite
for
a
j/
ce>
will
KQ
be denoted by
>a
i.
we have
>O.
[236] There
number
we
a wholly determined
number-class such that
therefore,
is,
KO of the first
o) oAT
(2)
If
*-
which
put a
a> <>K
^a,
a) o(/c
= a we
,
(3)
-f- I
> a.
have
= o)aoK + a
and
0^
(4)
But a can be represented
in the
form
(3)
under the
conditions (4) in only a single way.
For from (3)
and (4) follow inversely the conditions (2) and thence
But only the number a = /3_i
the conditions (i).
satisfies
(2) the
From
the conditions (i), and by the conditions
number /c is uniquely determined.
finite
(i)
theorem F
and
of
(4) follows,
18, that
Thus we can
by paying attention to
< a,
a 0:fia.
assert the following
theorem
A. Every number a of the second number-class
86
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
can be brought, and brought
the form
+a
o/c
ft)
only one way, into
in
where
and a
is always smaller than a, but a
is smaller
than or equal to a.
If a is a number of the second number-class, we
can apply theorem
(5)
to
ft)
it,
and we have
-!*!
+ a",
where
o^ a" <
a
ft>
i,
< KI <
"
<a
ft>,
and
< a o>
In general
equations
we
get a further sequence of analogous
(6)
(7)
^cw Va + a"
"
a
ft)
3/f
+a
iv
.
sequence cannot be infinite, but must
For the numbers a, a a",
break
off.
necessarily
in
decrease
magnitude
But
this
a> a > a > a
/
^^
ff
fr
If a series of decreasing transfinite
infinite,
numbers were
and this
then no term would be the least
16.
Consequently
impossible by theorem B of
we must have, for a certain finite numerical value T,
is
OF TRANSFINITR NUMBERS
187
we now connect
the equations (3), (5),
(6), and (7) with one another, we get the theorem
B. Kvery number a of the second number-class
If
[237]
can
and represented
be
represented,
way, in the form
a
where a
= a)a
/c
c^
+ o/ *! +
aT
-}-a>
> ax > a2 >
while K O
KV
/C T
T+
Ac T
numbers of the
a T are
second number-class, such that
a
only one
in
are
first
or
>a
>. O,
numbers of the
first
number-class which are different from zero.
The form
which
is
of numbers of the second number-class
here shown will be called their " normal
a
form";
exponent
of
"
degree" and a r the
For T = o, degree and exponent
the
called
is
"
a.
are equal to one another.
According as the exponent a T
is
equal to or greater
than zero, a is a number of the first or second kind.
Let us take another number /3 in the normal
form
:
P = ufi
(8)
The
formulae
(9)
o>
(10)
where
both
K,
for
K,
+ UT K = ftf
V+
V + V = T V,
co
K" here
denote
/c),
finite
the comparison of a with
< a",
numbers,
ft
and
serve
for the
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
88
These are
carrying out of their sum and difference.
of
the
formulae
of
and
17.
generalizations
(2)
(3)
For the formation of the product
formulae
come
into consideration
(11)
a\ = a)a KQ \ + aai K l +
(12)
aw =
(13)
aft
a/3,
O<X<o>;
-f co%: T ,
The exponentiation
can be easily carried out
on the basis of the following formulae
a
(14)
the following
= o)a x +
The terms not
/c
0<X<w.
-i
written on
the right have a lower
Hence follows readily that
degree than the first.
the fundamental series {a*} and {co***} are coherent,
so that
a"
(15)
in
Thus,
have
*>*<>",
>0.
18,
we
we can prove
the
consequence of theorem
of
(i 6)
By
ft)
o,
>o,
the help of these formulae
following theorems
^X
a
of the
[238] C. If the first terms co /c
normal forms of the two numbers a and /3 are not
than /3 according as
equal, then a is less or greater
,
a
a)
/c
and
a
is
is
less or greater
than co^X
But
if
we have
or greater than ft>^ +1 X p +i, then
correspondingly less or greater than /3.
less
if a)ap+l K
p+l is
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
If the
D.
/3
of
ft,
But
is
less
than the degree
we have
= /3
If a
degree a of a
189
then
>
if
then
E.
If ft
= co
a /3
But
is
o+/Jox
if ft is
F.
But
If
if
first
where
/3
can be represented,
(ft v
first
is
kind
(^ >o),
a
+a) o + ^X
= o),
(/3 cr
then
<7
= 0)^
then
>o), then
(^ = 0),
and indeed
of the second kind,
we have:
Every number a of the second number-class
G.
form
kind
of the second kind
of the
is
(T ,
+ w^+frX +
of the
is
ft
ft
of the second kind
in
only one way,
in
the product-
= wy *
Vl
T (ft>
and we have
I)K T -I(CO
+ iK_2
T
<V +
i)/f
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
190
whilst K Q> K^
in the normal
.
have the same denotation as
Kr
The
form.
factors
w y +i are
all
irresoluble.
H. Every number a of the second kind which
belongs to the second number-class can be repre
sented, and represented in only one way, in the
form
where y >o and a
which belongs to the
[239]
I.
is
first
Yo
fc)
number
of the
first
kind
or second number-class.
In order that two numbers a and
/3
of
the second number-class should satisfy the relation
it is
necessary and sufficient that they should have
the form
a
where
/x
and
are
= y/x,
/3
= yv,
numbers of the
first
number-class.
K. In order that two numbers a and f} of the
second number-class, which are both of the first
kind, should satisfy the relation
necessary and sufficient that they should have
the form
it is
where
//,
and
are
= y^
p = Y,
numbers of the
first
number-class.
In order to exemplify the extent of the normal
form dealt with and the product-form immediately
connected with
it,
of the
numbers of the second
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
191
number-class, the proofs, which are founded on
them, of the two last theorems, I and K, may here
follow.
From
we
the supposition
of a must be
conclude that the degree a
first
equal to the degree
of
/3
For
/3.
if,
say, a </8
we
would have, by theorem D,
and consequently
which
is
not possible, since, by (2) of
14,
Thus we may put
a
-ha
(aFujUL
/3
= aAi/ + /3
where the degrees of the numbers a and (3 are less
than a and /x and v are infinite numbers which are
different from zero.
Now, by theorem D we have
>
a,
and consequently
a
o>
By theorem D
Thus we have
(M
of
i/)
+ /3 = w-V + v) + a
14
we have consequently
0W.
a,
=
/
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
192
[240] and
if
we
put
<o
we
have,
by
(i i)
+a =7
= y/x,
P = yv.
Let us suppose, on the other hand, that a and /3 are
two numbers which belong to the second numberclass, are of the first kind, and satisfy the condition
aj8
a,
and we suppose that
a>/3.
We
will
imagine both numbers, by theorem G,
their product-form,
where a and
{$
and
let
common
are without a
i) at the left end.
We
in
factor (besides
have then
and
All the numbers which occur here and farther on
are of the
a and
first
kind, because
this-
was supposed of
/3.
The
when we
last equation,
shows that a and
/3
refer to
theorem G,
cannot be both
transfinite,
because, in this case, there would be a common
Neither can they be both
factor at the left end.
finite
then 8 would be transfinite, and, if K is
factor at the left end of S, we would have
for
the finite
OLK
= j8
/f ,
OF TRANSFINITE NUMKKRS
193
and thus
a
=p.
Thus there remains only the
a>a),
But the
finite
number
(3
possibility that
<w.
must be
/3
=i,
would be contained as part
left end of a
because otherwise
it
the
the
finite factor at
We
in
arrive at the result that
/3
=S
consequently
a** pa,
where a
number belonging
is
number-class, which
be
than a
less
of the
is
first
to
the
kind,
second
and must
a <a.
Between a and
/3
the relation
a/3
= /3a
subsists.
[241] Consequently if also a >/3, we conclude in
the same way the existence of a transfinite number
of the
first
kind a" which
a
and so
a",
less
than a and such that
a" ft = /3a".
greater than /?, there
less than a", such that
If also a"
a"
= /3a",
is
is
The
on.
",
.,
is
series of decreasing
must, by theorem
such a number
numbers,
of
16,
a,
x
,
break
194
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
off.
Thus,
index p Q
for a definite finite
we must
have
<
0<"o
ft.
If
= /3,
a ( *V>
we have
a
the theorem
= /8". +1
P = P;
would then be proved, and we would
have
y = ft,
But
then
if
we
put
and have
Thus there
is
also a finite
=&"&,
In general,
and so
on.
^2> ^s>
off.
If
Thus
we put
then
number
&&=$&,
we have analogously
The
p l such that
pt <&.
numbers /^
series of decreasing
a ^ so must
>
by theorem B of
there exists a
finite
number
16,
break
K such that
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
where
,u
and
195
are numerator and denominator of
the continued fraction.
P*
20
[242]
The e-Numbers
The degree
of a
Second Number- Class
of the
number
evident from the normal form
1
= wa KQ + co
ai
Kl
when we pay attention
as
is,
is
immediately
> ax >
to theorem
of
O < KV <
18,
to,
never
greater than a but it is a question whether there
In such a case
are not numbers for which a = a.
;
the normal form of a would reduce to the
and this term would be equal to o> a that
a would be a root of the equation
,
(2)
On
first
is
term,
to say,
the other hand, every root a of this equation
would have the normal form wa
be equal to
its
degree would
itself.
The numbers
of the second number-class
which
are equal to their degree coincide, therefore, with
It is our problem to
the roots of the equation (2).
determine these
roots
in
their totality.
To
dis
tinguish them from all other numbers we will call
them the "e-numbers of the second number-class."
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
96
That there are such e-numbers
following theorem
A. If y is any number of the
results
from
the
or
first
second
number-class which does not satisfy the equation
(2), it determines a fundamental series {y} by means
of the equations
The
is
limit
Lim y =E(y)
V
of this fundamental series
J/
always an e-number.
Since y is not an e-number, we have
Proof.
w >y, that is to say, 7x >y.
Thus, by theorem B
y
yi
of
1 8, we have also o)"
>(o that is to say, y 2 >7i
Y
in the
on.
The
We
denote
series {y,,}
The number
the least of
all
thus a fundamental series.
is
>6D,
e
Similarly
We
have
o>
in
a function of y,
by
an e-number.
= E(i) = Lim
Let
=e
we have a/>&>w
>co
<*v,
where
be any e-number, so that
</
Since
is
the e-numbers.
[243] Proof.
and so
Consequently E(y)
is
is
which
its limit,
E(y) and have
B.
same way follows that y3 >y 2
and
Wl
,
that
general
is
that
to say,
is
r
to say,
> co2 and
,
>
<JD
so on.
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
197
and consequently
that
Thus
is
to say,
= E(i)
is
the least of
all
e-numbers.
the next greater
any e-number,
e-number, and y is any number which lies between
them
e < y < e">
C.
If e
e"
is
is
then E(y) = e".
From
Proof.
<y<e
//
follows
that
is
to say,
Similarly
we conclude
e
and so
We
on.
< y 2 < e",
have, in general,
e
< y < e",
v
and thus
By theorem
A, E(y)
is
an e-number.
the e-number which follows
E(y) cannot be
must have
nitude,
<?
less
next
in
than
e",
Since e"
is
order of
mag
and thus we
E(y)=".
Since
is
not an e-number, simply because all
from the equation of definition
e-numbers, as follows
198
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
^ = 0^, are of the second kind, e -f- I is certainly less
than e", and thus we have the following theorem
D. If e is any e-number, then E(e + i) is the next
:
greater e-number.
To the least e-number,
greater one:
= E(e
e1
follows, then, the next
+l),
[244] to this the next greater number
generally, we have for the
(j/+ i)th e-number in order of magnitude the formula
of recursion
and so
on.
Quite
= (*-!+
(3)
But that the
I).
infinite series
by no means embraces the totality of e-numbers
results from the following theorem
:
E.
If
e,
...
e",
any
is
infinite
series
of
e-numbers such that
e<e <e".
then
Lim
e (l/)
is
&<&+<.
.,
an e-number, and, in
fact,
the
e-number which follows next
to all the numbers e
in
order of magnitude
(l/)
Proof.
Lim
v
a)
6 <">
= Lim
oo
(|0
= Lim e %
(
OF TRANSFINlfE NUMBERS
That Lini
e(l > is
199
the e-number which follows next
order of magnitude to
from the fact that Lim
in
")
results
number
of the
the numbers
all
e (l/)
the
is
e(
second number-class which follows next
to
magnitude
The
F.
all
the numbers
of
totality
number-class
forms,
order of
e-numbers
when
in
(l/)
of
arranged
the second
order of
in
magnitude, a well-ordered aggregate of the type 2
of the second number-class in its order of magnitude,
and has thus the power Aleph-one.
The totality of e-numbers of the second
number-class, when arranged in their order of magni
16, a well-ordered
tude, forms, by theorem C of
Proof.
aggregate
(4)
*0>
>
e ">
e " + l>
whose law of formation is expressed in the theorems
D and E. Now, if the index a did not successively
take all the numerical values of the second numberclass, there would be a least number a which it did
not reach.
But this would contradict the theorem
D, if a were of the first kind, and theorem E, if a
were of the second kind. Thus a takes all numerical
values of the second number-class.
we denote
If
by
2,
the type of the second number-class
the type of (4)
is
2
[245] But since w + o)
= w2 we
,
have
THE FOUNDING OF THE THEORY
200
and consequently
G.
the
If
first
any number of
or second number-class which is less than e
e is
any e-number and a
is
a<e,
then
the three equations
satisfies
+e=
ae
e,
a6
e,
=e
is the degree of a, we have a
^.a, and
also
of
we
have
because
<
a
a < e.
e,
consequently,
e
=
But the degree of e co is e; thus a has a less
If a
Proof.
degree than
by theorem
Consequently,
e.
19,
a+e
of
and thus
+ e^e.
On
we
the other hand,
19,
ae
= aco =
by formula (13) of
have,
a +e
ct>
= co =
e
e,
and thus
Finally,
paying attention to the formula (16) of
19,
H.
If a
is
= aco = coa
e
co
6.
any number of the second number-class,
the equation
at
has no other roots
greater than
= coa = co =
a.
=t
than the e-numbers which are
OF TRANSFINITE NUMBERS
Proof.
Let
/3
201
be a root of the equation
=
so that
ct=ft.
Then,
in
the
first
from this formula follows
place,
that
On
the other hand,
/?
must be of the second
Thus we have, by theorem F
ae
and consequently
co*o0
[246]
kind,
we would have
since, if not,
By theorem F
of
of
19,
oP.
= /3.
19,
co^>a
we have
/3,
and thus
/3>a
But
/3
/3.
cannot be greater than
/3
consequently
and thus
o/
Therefore
/3
is
HALLE, March
= /3.
an e-number which
1897.
is
greater than
a.
NOTES
IN a sense the most fundamental advance made
in
the theoretical arithmetic of finite and transfinite
numbers
is
the
purely
logical
definition
Whereas Cantor
number-concept.
86, 112 above) defined
(see
the
of
74,
pp.
"cardinal number" and
"ordinal type" as general concepts which
means of our mental activity, that is to
arise
by
say,
as
psychological entities, Gottlob Frege had, in his
Grundlagen der Arithmetik of 1884, defined the
" number
"
(Anzahl) of a class u as the class of all
those classes which are equivalent (in the sense of
&6 above) to u.
Frege remarked that his
" numbers " are the same as what Cantor
(see pp.
PP- 75>
40, 74, 86 above) had called "powers," and that
there was no reason for restricting "numbers" to
be finite.
Although Frege worked out,
volume (1893) of his Grundge seize der
an important part of
arithmetic,
in
the
first
AritJunetik^
with a logical
accuracy previously unknown and for years after
wards almost unknown, his ideas did not become at
all widely known until Bertrand Russell, who had
arrived independently at this logical definition of
"cardinal number," gave prominence to them
in his
NOTES
203
The two chief
Principles of Mathematics of 1903.*
reasons in favour of this definition are that it
avoids,
by a construction
of
"numbers"
out of the
fundamental entities of
there are certain
"numbers"; and
logic, the assumption that
and undefined entities called
new
that
it
allows us to deduce at
once that the class defined
the cardinal
number
not empty, so that
of u "exists" in the sense
is
defined in logic
in fact, since u is equivalent to
the
cardinal
number of u has u at least as a
itself,
:
member.
for
Russell also gave an analogous definition
ordinal types or the more general "relation
numbers. " f
An account of much that has been done
in
the
theory of aggregates since 1897 ma y be gathered
from A. Schoenflies s reports
Die Entwickelung
:
der Lehre von den Punktmannigfaltigkeiten^ Leipzig,
A second edition
1900; part ii, Leipzig, 1908.
of the first part was published at Leipzig and Berlin
in 1913, in collaboration
with H. Hahn, under the
Entwickelung
Mengenlehre und Hirer
These three books will be cited
Anivendungen.
title
der
by their respective dates of publication, and, when
references to relevant contributions not mentioned
these reports are made, full references to the
original place of publication will be given.
in
Pp. 519, 111-116.
Cf. Whitehead, Amer. Journ. of Math., vol.
For a more modern form of the doctrine, see
1902, p. 378.
Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, vol. ii, Cambiidge.
1912, pp. 4, 13.
t Principles, pp. 262, 321 ; and Principia, vol. ii, pp. 330,
473-510.
xxiv,
NOTES
204
Leaving aside the applications of the theory of
numbers to geometry and the theory of
the
most important advances since 1897
functions,
transfinite
are as follows
(1) The proof given
independently by Ernst
Schroder (1896) and Felix Bernstein (1898) of the
theorem B on p. 91 above, without the supposition
that one of the three relations of magnitude must
hold between any two cardinal numbers (1900, pp.
16-18; 1913, pp. 34-41
1908, pp. 10-12).
;
The
giving of exactly expressed definitions
of arithmetical operations with cardinal numbers
(2)
and of proofs of the laws of arithmetic for them by
A. N. Whitehead (Amer. Journ. of Math., vol.
xxiv,
pp.
1902, pp.
117-120.
Whitehead
367-394).
A
and
Cf.
Russell, Principles,
more modern form
is
Russell
vol.
Principia,
given
ii,
in
pp.
66-186.
on the question as to whether
can
be
any aggregate
brought into the form of
a well-ordered aggregate.
This question Cantor
(3) Investigations
1900, p. 49; 1913, p. 170; and p. 63 above)
(cf.
believed could be answered in the affirmative.
The
was
postulate lying at the bottom of this theorem
brought forward in the most definite manner
by E. Zermelo and E. Schmidt in 1904, and
Zermelo afterwards gave this postulate the form of
an " axiom of selection" (1913, pp. 16, 170-184;
Whitehead and Russell have
1908, pp. 33-36).
dealt with great precision with the subject in their
Prindpia,
vol.
i,
Cambridge,
1910, pp.
500-568.
NOTKS
205
It may be remarked that Cantor, in his
proof of
theorem A on p. 105 above, and in that of theorem
C on pp. 161-162. above,* unconsciously used this
axiom of infinite selection. Also G. H. Hardy
in
1903 (1908, pp.
consciously at
22-23) used
this
axiom, un
a proof that it is possible to
of cardinal number N X in the
first, in
have an aggregate
continuum of real numbers.
But there is another and wholly different question
which crops up in attempts at a proof that any
aggregate can be well ordered.
had
Cesare Burali-Forti
1897 pointed out that the series of all ordinal
numbers, which is easily seen to be well ordered,
in
must have the greatest of all ordinal numbers as its
Yet the type of the above series of ordinal
numbers followed by its type must be a greater
type.
ordinal number, for (3+ i
Forti concluded that we
is
greater than
(3.
Burali-
must deny Cantor s funda
mental theorem in his memoir of 1897.
A different
use of an argument analogous to Burali-Forti s was
made by
Philip E. B. Jourdain in a paper written in
1903 and published
6th
in
1904 (Philosophical Magazine,
The chief interest
61-75).
that it contains a proof which is
series, vol. vii, pp.
of this paper
is
but practically identical with, that
discovered by Cantor in 1895, an d of which some
independent
of,
we have
here to prove that any enumerable aggregate of
an enumerable aggregate of the
elements last referred to. To prove that tfo- Ko^Ko, it is not enough to
prove the above theorem for particular aggregates. And in the general
case we have to pick one element out of each of an infinity of classes.
no element in each class being distinguished from the others.
Indeed,
any enumerable aggregates gives
NOTES
206
trace
is
preserved in the passage on
the remark on the theorem
109 above
p.
and
in
This
proof of Cantor s and Jourdain s consists of
In the first part it is established that
parts.
two
of
90.
p.
every cardinal number is either an Aleph or is greater
than all Alephs.
This part requires the use of
Zermelo s axiom; and Jourdain took the " proof"
of this part of the theorem directly from
Cantor
paper of 1903 referred to above.
the result required, and indeed the result
Hardy
assumed
seems very
plausible.
The second
part of the theorem consists in the
the
that
proof
supposition that a cardinal number
is greater than all Alephs is impossible.
By a slight
modification
of Burali-Forti
modification
it
is
proved
that
argument, in which
there cannot be a
greatest Aleph, the conclusion seems to follow that
no cardinal number can be other than an Aleph.
The contradiction discovered by Burali-Forti is
the best
known
contradiction
to
was
mathematicians
discovered *
but the simplest
by Russell
(Principles,
pp. 364-368, 101-107) from an application to "the
"
cardinal number of all things of Cantor s argument
Russell s
of 1892 referred to on pp. 99-100 above.
If
contradiction can be reduced to the following
is the class of all those terms x such that x is not
:
is a member of
of x^ then, if
while
is not a member of
plain that
not a member of w, it is equally plain that
member
member
*
of w.
The treatment and
if
it is
w
is
is
final solution of
This argument was discovered in 1900 (see Monist, Jan. 1912).
NOTES
207
these paradoxes, which concern the foundations of
the logical
logic and which are closely allied to
has been
"the Epimenides,"
attempted unsuccessfully by very many mathe
maticians,! and successfully by Russell (cf. Principles,
known
puzzle
PP-
5 2
3~5 28
as
Principia, vol.
on
p.
pp. 26-31, 39-90)-
i,
required (see theorem
1
08) in the proof that the two definitions
The theorem
on
121-123
pp.
187-298.
105
On
of infinity coincide.
pp.
p.
is
this
Principia, vol.
of
(4) Investigation
i,
point,
pp.
cf.
Principles,
569-666;
number-classes
in
vol.
ii,
general,
and the .arithmetic of Alephs by Jourdain in 1904
and 1908, and G. Hessenberg in 1906^ (1913,
pp. 131-136; 1908, pp. 13-14).
(5) The definition, by Felix Hausdorff in 19041907, of the product of an infinity of ordinal types
This
and hence of exponentiation by a type.
definition is analogous to Cantor s definition of
exponentiation
above.
(6)
Cf.
cardinal
for
1913,
pp.
Theorems due
to
numbers
on
p.
95
75~8o 1908, pp. 42-45.
J.
Konig (1904) on the
;
Epimenides was a Cretan who said that all Cretans were liars.
if his statement were true he was a liar.
The remark of a
man who says, " I am lying," is even more analogous to Russell s w.
t Thus Schoenflies, in his Reports of 1908 and 1913, devotes an
undue amount of space to his "solution " of the paradoxes here referred
to.
This " solution" really consists in saying that these paradoxes do
not belong to mathematics but to "philosophy." It may be remarked
that Schoenflies seems never to have grasped the meaning and extent of
/ermelo s axiom, which Russell has called the "multiplicative axiom.
Obviously
Just as in the proof that the multiplication of Ny by itself gives
the
more general theorem here considered involves the multiplicative
axiom.
Cf. Jourdain, Mess,
of Math.
(2), vol.
xxxvi,
May
1906, pp. 13-16.
NOTES
208
inequality
of certain
cardinal
numbers
of
independent generalization
with one of Cantor
together
above),
these
s
(see
by Zermelo and Jourdain
in
and the
theorems,
pp.
81-82
1908 (1908,
16-17; 1913, PP. 65-67).
(7) HausdorfPs contributions from 1906 to 1908
pp.
to the theory of
pp.
(8)
The
pp. 40-71)-
investigation
multiply ordered
in
linear ordered aggregates (1913,-
185-205; 1908,
1903, and
infinite
Brouwer
in
of
the
types of
by F. Riess
ordinal
aggregates
1913 (1913, pp. 85-87).
INDEX
Abel, Niels Henrike,
Cantor, Georg, v,
10.
Abelian functions, 10, u.
Absolute infinity, 62, 63.
46, 47,
of,
10,
26, 28,
29, 30, 32, 33 34, 35, 36,
37, 38, 41, 42, 45, 46, 47,
48, 49, 51, 52, 53, 54, 55,
56, 57, 59, 60, 62, 63, 64,
68, 69, 70, 72, 73, 74, 76,
81, 82, 202,
77, 79, 80
Actuality of numbers, 67.
Addition of cardinal numbers, So,
91 ff
of ordinal types, 81, 119 ff.
of transfinite numbers, 63, 66,
>53ff., 175 ff., 206.
Adherences, 73.
Aggregate, definition
vi, vii, 3, 9,
13, 18, 22, 24, 25,
204, 205, 206, 208.
Dedekind axiom, 30.
Cardinal number (see also Power),
79 ff., 85 ff., 202.
97 ff.
smallest transfinite, 103 ff.
Cardinal
numbers,
operations
54, 74, 85.
of bindings, 92.
of union, 50, 91.
74,
finite,
Alembeit, Jean Lerond d
Algebraic numbers, 38 ff.
Aquinas, Thomas, 70.
4.
with, 204.
127.
series of transfinite, 109.
Cauchy, Augustin Louis,
Aristotle, 55, 70.
Arithmetic, foundations of, with
Weierstrass, 12.
with Frege and Russell, 202,
203.
2, 3, 4, 6,
8, 12, 14, 15, 16, 17, 22, 24.
Class of types, 114.
Closed aggregates, 132.
types, 133.
Coherences, 73.
Arzela, 73.
Associative
law with transfinite
numbers, 92, 93, 119, 121,
154- 155.
Coherent series, 129, 130.
Commutative law with transfinite
numbers,
92,
66,
93,
119 ff. 190 ff.
Condensation of singularities,
,
Baire, Rene, 73.
Bendixson, Ivar, 73.
Connected aggregates, 72.
Content of aggregates, 73.
Berkeley, George, 55.
Bernoulli, Daniel, 4.
Bernstein, Felix, 204.
Bois-Reymond, Pauldu, 22,34,51.
Bolzano, Bernard, 13,
22,41, 55,72.
Borel, Emile, 73.
Bouquet, 7.
3,
9, 48, 49.
14,
Content-less, 51.
Continuity of a function,
Continuous
Briot, 7.
Brode"n, 73.
Brou \ver, 208.
motion
I.
discon
tinuous space, 37.
Continuum, 33, 37, 41 ff., 47. 48.
17, 21,
64, 70
ff.,
in
96, 205.
Contradiction, Russell s, 206, 207.
Convergence of series, I, 15, 16,
17, 20 24
Cords, vibrating, probl-m
Burali-Forti, Cesare, 205, 206.
2 9
14
nf, 4.
INDEX
2IO
D Alembert
J.
(see
L. d
vii,
23, 41,
47, 49, 73-
Definition of aggregate, 37.
3,
of
Hardy, G. H., 205, 206.
Harnack, Axel, 51, 73.
Hessenberg, Gerhard, 207.
point-aggregates,
3ff-
3, 7, 8, 9, 17,
Hausdorff, Felix, 207. 208.
Heine, H. E., 3, 26, 69.
Helmholtz, H. von, 42, 70, 81.
Democritus, 70.
De Morgan, Augustus, 41.
Density in itself, 132.
Derivatives
Hankel, Hermann,
49, 70.
Dedekind, Richard,
.
Alembert,
).
Hobbes, Thomas,
55.
37-
Descartes, Rene, 55.
Dirichlet, Peter
Gustav Lejeune,
2, 3, 5, 7, 8, 9, 22, 35.
Discrete aggregates, 51.
Distributive law with transfinite
Imaginaries, 6.
Induction, mathematical, 207.
Infinite, definition of, 41, 61, 62.
Infinitesimals, 64, 81.
Infinity,
numbers, 66, 93, 121, 155.
Enumerability, 32, 38ff.,47, 50
ff.,
62.
proper and improper, 55,
79-
Riemann
Integrability,
ditions of, 8.
con
Integrable aggregates, 51.
Inverse types, 114.
Enumeral, 52, 62.
Irrational numbers, 3, 14
analogy of transfinite
Epicurus, 70.
Epimenides, 207.
Equivalence of aggregates,
75, 86 ff.
40,
10.
Euler, Leonhard, 4, 5, 9,
Everywhere-dense aggregates, 33,
ff.
26
ff.
numbers
with, 77 ff.
Isolated aggregate, 49.
point, 30.
of
transfinite
Exponentiation
numbers, 82, 94 ff., 207.
Jacobi, C. G. J., 10.
Jordan, Camille, 73.
Jourdain, Philip E. B., 4, 6, 20,
32, 52, 205, 206, 207, 208.
Fontenelle, 118.
Killing,
35, 37, 123.
types, 133.
Formalism in mathematics,
Fourier, Jean
70, 81.
Baptiste Joseph,
I,
2, 5, 6, 8, 24.
Freedom
in mathematics, 67
6,
7,
10,
n,
12,
13,
Kummer,
2,
22,
8.
E. E.
69.
Lagrange, J. L., 5, 14.
Leibniz, G. W. von, 55.
Leucippus, 70.
73arbitrary, 4, 6, 34.
theory of real, 2, 8, 9, 73*
Fundamental series, 26, 128
1 1
of a point-aggregate, 32.
Kirchhoff, G.,69.
Konig, Julius, 207.
Kronecker, L., 70, 81.
ff.
Frege, Gottlob, 23, 70, 202.
Function, conception of, I.
Functions, theory of analytic,
W.,
Kind
Limitation, principle of, 60.
Limiting element of an aggregate,
I
ff.
3I
Limit-point, 30.
Gauss, Carl Friedrich, 6, 12, 14.
Generation, principles of, 56, 57.
Limits with transfinite numbers,
77 ff., 131 ff., 58 ff.
Gudermann,
Liouville, J., 40.
Lipschitz, R., 6.
10.
Hahn, H., 203.
Haller, Albrecht von, 62.
Locke,
J., 55.
Lucretius, 70.
INDEX
Mach, Ernst,
69.
Maximum
of a function, 22.
Mittag-LetHer, Gosta, 11.
Mutliplicatibn of cardinal num
bers, 80, 91 ff.
of ordinal types 81. 119 ff, 154.
of transfinite numbers, 63, 64,
21
Riess, F., 208.
Russell, Bertrand, 20, 23, 53, 202,
203, 204, 206, 207.
Schepp, A., 117.
Schmidt, E., 204.
Schoenflies, A., 73, 203, 207.
Schwarz,
66, i;6ff.
8, 12.
Second
Newton, Sir Isaac, 15.
Nominalism, Cantor s, 69, 70.
Number-concept, logical definition
number-class, cardinal
of, 169 ff.
epsilon-numbers of the, 195 ff.
exponentiation in, 178 ff.
number
normal form of numbers
of, 202, 203.
183
number
Ordinal
also
(see
Enumeral), 75, 151 ff.
numbers, finite, 113, 158, 159.
type, 75, 79 ff, noff.
type of aggregate of rational
numbers, 122 ff., 202.
types of multiply ordered aggre
gates, 81, 208.
d, W. F., 73.
Peano, G., 23.
of,
ff.
numbers
Segment of
of,
60
ff.
60, 103,
141 ff.
Selections, 204 ff.
Similarity, 76, 112 ff.
Species of a point-aggregate, 31.
Spinoza, B. 55.
Steiner, J., 40.
Stolz, O., 17, 73Subtraction of transfmite numbers,
series,
66, 155, 156.
Perfect aggregates, 72, 132.
types, 133.
Philosophical revolution brought
about
by Cantor
work,
vi.
Physical conceptions and
mathematics,
modern
4,
32,
36,
50 ff., 52 ff.
Trigonometrical developments,
3, 4, 5. 6, 7,
8,24f.,
2,
31.
I.
Point-aggregates, Cantor
work on, v, vi.
theory of, 3, 20 ff., 30
early
ff.,
73Potential, theory of, 7.
Power, second, 64 ff. 169 ff.
of an aggregate, 32, 37,
52 ff., 60, 62.
Prime numbers, transfmite,
51.
Veronese, G., 117, 118.
Weierstrass, Karl,
40,
64, 66.
Principal element of an aggregate,
13 1
Puiseux, V., 7.
-
Reducible aggregates. 71.
Relation numbers, 203.
Riemann, G. F. B., 3, 7, 8,
Unextended aggregates,
Upper limit, 21.
64,
12, 25, 42.
Teubner, B. G., vii.
Transfmite numbers,
9, 10,
n,
vi, vii, 2, 3, 10,
12, 13, 14,
17, 18, 19,
20, 21, 22, 23, 24, 26, 30,
48.
Well-ordered aggregates, 60, 61,
75 ff., 137 ff.
Well-ordering, 204 ff.
Whitehead, A. N., 203, 204.
Zeno, 15.
Zermelo, E., 204, 206, 207, 208.
Zermelo s axiom, 204 ff.
PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY
NKILL AND CO., LTD.,
EDINBURGH
A SELECTION FROM THE
PUBLICATIONS OF THE
OPEN COURT COMPANY
WORKS OF PROFESSOR ERNST MACH.
The Analysis
of Sensations and the Relation of the
Physical to the Psychical. Second edition, translated
by C. M. WILLIAMS and SYDNEY WATERLOW, M.A. Cloth.
Pages
"
xvi, 380.
A wonderfully
6s. 6d. net.
original little book.
Like everything he writes, a
WILLIAM JAMES.
new edition of Mach s Analysis
work
of genius."
This
of Sensations is a book nearly
The eight chapters of
twice as long as the English translation of 1897.
the original edition have all been greatly expanded, and there are six new
"
Relation to Avenarius and other Thinkers,"
Physics
chapters on
and Biology," "The Will," " Biologico-Teleological Considerations as to
"My
Space," "Sensation," "Memory and Association," and "How my Views
have been Received." The author amplifies and brings up to date his
original discussions on points of detail, and explains and justifies his more
general views as to the relation between different branches of science and
as to questions on the borderland between science and philosophy.
Par
ticular interest attaches to the explanations which he now gives of the
in
his
which
views
were
way
developed.
"A
This
is
writer with a reputation like that of
perhaps his best-known publication."
Popular Science Lectures.
by T.
J.
gilt top.
M CORMACK.
6s. net.
Mach needs no
introduction.
Cambridge Magazine.
Translated from the
Third edition.
Pages 41 5.
German
Cloth,
A portrayal of the methods and spirit of science, in lectures on Mechanics,
Sound, Light, Electricity, the Conservation of Energy, Philosophy, and
The thoughts of the master-minds of science are here presented
Education.
in popular form by one of its foremost living representatives.
Space and Geometry in the Light of Physiological,
Psychological, and Physical Inquiry. From the
German by THOMAS J. M CORMACK. Cloth, gilt top.
Pages 143.
45. net.
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
In these essays Professor Mach discusses the questions of the nature,
and development of our concepts of space, from the three points of
view of the physiology and psychology of the senses, history, and physics, in all
which departments his profound researches have gained for him an authorita
tive and commanding position.
While in most works on the foundations
of geometry one point of view only is emphasised be it that of logic,
epistemology, psychology, history, or the formal technology of the science,
here light is shed upon the subject from all points of view combined,
and the different sources from which the many divergent forms that the
science of space has historically assumed are thus shown forth with a
origin,
distinctness
be desired.
and precision
in suggestiveness at least, leave little to
that,
Any reader who possesses a slight knowledge of mathematics may derive
from these essays a very adequate idea of the abstruse yet important
researches of metageometry.
The Science
of Mechanics.
Account of
its
M CoRMACK.
Critical
Development.
Third enlarged
Cloth, gilt top.
Pages xx, 605.
Exhaustive Index,
8s. net.
"
and Historical
Translated by
remarkable work."
edition.
THOMAS
259
J.
cuts.
Marginal Analyses.
Nature.
"Mach s Mechanics is unique. It is not a text-book, but forms a useful
supplement to the ordinary text-book. The latter is usually a skeleton
Mach s book
outline, full of mathematical symbols and other abstractions.
has muscle and clothing, and, being written from the historical standpoint,
introduces the leading contributors in succession, tells what they did and
how they did it, and often what manner of men they were. Thus it is that
the pages glow, as it were, with a certain humanism, quite delightful in a
The book is handsomely printed, and deserves a
scientific book.
warm reception from all interested in the progress of science." The
Physical Review.
.
" The book as a whole is
unique, and is a valuable addition to any library
of science or philosophy.
Reproductions of quaint old portraits and
The numerous marginal titles form
vignettes give piquancy to the pages.
a complete epitome of the work and there is that invaluable adjunct, a good
index. Altogether the publishers are to be congratulated upon producing
Prof. D. W.
a technical work that is thoroughly attractive in its make-up."
.
H BRING,
A
in Science.
.
To anyone who feels that he does not know
.
.
as he ought to about physics, we can commend it most heartily as
a scholarly and able treatise . .
both interesting and profitable."
as
masterly book.
much
A,
M. WELLINGTON,
in
Engineering Neivs.
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
Just published:
The Science
Supplementary Volume
of Mechanics.
Account of
its
Development.
to
Mactts Mechanics.
Critical
and Historical
Supplement
to the third
English edition, containing the author s additions to the
seventh
German
edition,
translated
PHILIP E. B. JOURDAIN, M.A.
2s.
and annotated by
Pages
xiv, 102.
Cloth,
6d. net.
This volume brings up to date the existing third edition of the transla
Mach s greatest work, and thus allows the public to complete the
work at a low price. A portrait of Newton and some notes (approved by
tion of
the author) added by the translator to complete or
Mechanics are included.
rectify parts of the
History and Root of the Principle of the Conserva
tion of Energy. Translated from the German, and
annotated by PHILIP E. B. JOURDAIN, M.A. (Cantab.).
Pages 116.
The
Cloth, 55. net.
pamphlet was first published in 1872, is one of Mach s
and most stimulating writings, and contains the germs of much of
his later work.
Moreover, it contains a reprint of Mach s article of 1868
on the definition of mass, which is, perhaps, his most important contribution
to mechanics
and the discussion of the logical root of the principle of the
conservation of energy is fuller than that in any of his later publications.
Several notes, explanatory, critical, or bibliographical, have been added by
the translator, and the whole book has been revised by the author.
original
earliest
WORKS BY AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN.
"It is only quite recently that mathematicians and logicians have come
to the conclusion that De Morgan was one of the acutest minds of the
nineteenth century and it has been left for the Open Court Company to
arrive at the entirely justifiable decision that everything he wrote is worthy
;
of republication."
On
Cambridge Magazine.
the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics. With
portrait of De Morgan, Index, and Bibliographies of
Modern Works on Algebra, the Philosophy of Mathe
matics,
55. net.
Pangeometry,
etc.
Pages
viii,
288.
Cloth,
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
Elementary Illustrations of the
Differential
and
Integral Calculus. New reprint edition. With sub
headings and bibliography of English and foreign works
on the Calculus. Cloth, 45. net.
c
at helping students to cram for examinations, but to give a
explanation of the rationale of these branches of mathematics.
Like all that De Morgan wrote, it is accurate, clear, and philosophic."
Literary World.
It
aims not
scientific
Work
Essays on the Life and
of Newton. Edited,
with Notes and Appendices, by PHILIP E. B. JOURDAIN,
M.A.
Pages
xiv, 198.
Cloth,
55. net.
Augustus De Morgan s three most important essays on the life and
work of Newton have here been united, with many critical and biblio
These essays are very rare and are unknown to many
graphical notes.
and yet De Morgan s wide reading and broad-minded judgment have lost
none of their value. The essays are: (i) The Life of Newton of 1846;
(2) The account of discoveries in England and Germany relating to the
fluxional controversy of 1852
(3) The review (1855) of Brewster s Memoirs
;
of Newton.
There are three appendices containing
either extracts
from
De Morgan s
other writings or references to important manuscripts of
Newton and Leibniz, and information as to where they may be seen in
In the case of Newton, this is especially important,
print or otherwise.
because no modern work calls attention to the fact that Newton left
important manuscripts on fluxions.
"These essays, written more than half a century ago, are still worth
The editor is to be
reading, both for their matter and their style.
congratulated on a piece of good work." Nature.
.
" No
engineer with any
American Machinist.
scientific training will fail to find
it
of interest."
"The late Professor Augustus De Morgan was one of the few mathe
maticians who have possessed the art of writing with lucidity and point
It was a happy thought which led Mr Philip E. B.
for the general reader.
Jourdain to reprint his three Essays on the Life and Work of Newton from
forgotten periodicals."
Spectator.
"Excellent essays dealing with that perennially interesting
Chicago Journal.
giant Isaac Newton."
Budget of Paradoxes. Revised and
EUGENE SMITH. Two volumes. Cloth,
intellectual
edited by
2 net.
DAVID
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
2*
The Algebra
of Logic. By Louis COUTURAT. Trans
LYDIA G. ROBINSON, B.A. With a Preface by
PHILIP E. B. JOURDAIN, M.A. Pages xiv, 98. Cloth,
lated by
6d. net.
35.
This is a short and lucid account of that branch of algebra which was
sketched out by Leibniz, independently developed by Boole, and completed
by Jevons, Venn, Schroder, Poretsky, and others. In the preface is
explained the connection between the algebra of logic and what is called
" Mathematical
logic,"
which
is
indispensable for the analysis of trains of
reasoning.
"
The translation is well done and the work can safely be recommended
as a good introduction to symbolic logic for students. ... In the preface
the distinction between a propositional function and a proposition is quite
clearly pointed out, and this gives the translation an advantage over the
French original."
Mind.
Essays on the Theory of Numbers, (i) Continuity
and Irrational Numbers (2) The Nature and Meaning
of Numbers.
From the
By RICHARD DEDEKIND.
German by W. W. BEMAN. Pages 115. Cloth, 35. net.
;
These essays mark one of the distinct stages in the development of the
theory of number.
They give the foundation upon which the whole
The first can be read without any
science of numbers may be established.
technical, philosophical, or mathematical knowledge ; the second requires
more power of abstraction for its perusal, but power of a logical nature
only.
"A
model
of
clear
and beautiful reasoning. "Journal of Physical
Chemistry.
" The work of Dedekind
is
very fundamental, and
am
glad to have
it
in this carefully wrought English version.
I think the book should be of
much service to American mathematicians and teachers." Prof. E. II.
MOORE,
"
University of Chicago.
be hoped that the translation will make the essays better known
English mathematicians they are of the very first importance, and rank
with the work of Weierstrass, Kronecker, and Cantor in the same field.
Nature.
It is to
to
A
work
companion volume containing a
is
listed
below
in the
translation of Cantor
"Open Court
Classics."
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
The Foundations
of Geometry.
By DAVID HILBERT,
Ph.D., Professor of Mathematics in the University of
Gottingen. With many new additions still unpublished
German. Translated by E. J. TOWNSEND, Ph.D.,
Associate Professor of Mathematics in the University of
in
Illinois.
Pages viii, 132. Cloth, 43. net.
" Professor Hilbert has become so
well known to the mathematical
world by his writings that the treatment of any topic by him commands the
attention of mathematicians everywhere.
The teachers of elementary
in this country are to be congratulated that it is possible for them
to obtain in English such an important discussion of these points by such
geometry
an authority.
-Journal of Pedagogy.
Non-Euclidean Geometry A Critical and Historical
Study of its Development. By ROBERTO BONOLA,
:
Professor in
late
the
University of
Authorised
Pavia.
English translation with additional Appendices by H. S.
CARSLAW, Professor in the University of Sydney, N.S.W.;
with an Introduction by FEDERIGO ENRIQUES, Professor
in the University of Bologna.
Pages xii, 268. Cloth,
8s. net.
The
subject is taken up mainly in the order of historical development,
beginning with the attempts of the Greeks and Arabs to prove Euclid s
famous Fifth Postulate, and tracing the history of this postulate and the
theory of parallels until it was finally shown that postulates which contradict
the Fifth Postulate may be used as a basis for a logically consistent geo
Three such (non- Euclidean) geometries are given particular
metry.
Numerous references to the literature of the subject make
attention. .
the book particularly valuable to the thorough student of geometry."
E. J. MOULTON, Journal of Western Society of Engineers.
.
"The
recent untimely death of Professor Bonola lends unusual interest
... In a review of the original Italian edition which
appeared in the Bulletin in 1910, I spoke of the desirability of having an
This want is
English edition of so valuable and interesting a work.
now well supplied by Professor Carslaw s translation
which is a very
readable and satisfactory English version of the best historical introduction
we have to the elements of non-Euclidean geometry." ARTHUR RANUM,
Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society.
to
this
book.
" Bonola
Non- Euclidean Geometry
critical studies
is one of the best
on mathematics that has been written.
be particularly useful
Mathematical Gazette.
should
to
teachers
historical
.
and
This book
of elementary geometry."
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
Brief History of Mathematics. By the late KARL
Translated by WOOSTER
FINK, Tubingen, Germany.
WOODRUFF BEMAN, Professor of Mathematics in the
University of Michigan, and DAVID EUGENE SMITH,
Professor of Mathematics in Teachers College, Columbia
University, New York City. With Biographical Notes and
full Index.
Second revised edition. Pages xii, 333.
Cloth, 6s. net.
This is not a book of anecdotes, nor one of biography ; but a clear and
brief statement of the facts of mathematical history.
An invaluable work
for teachers of mathematics.
of Japanese Mathematics.
By DAVID
EUGENE SMITH and YOSHIO MIKAMI. Pages vii, 288.
History
Cloth, i2s. net.
This important and scholarly work gives a survey the first that is com
of the leading features in the development
petently expressed in English
of native Japanese mathematics as distinguished from European mathe
matics.
It is of absorbing interest to see how the Japanese developed,
possibly quite independently of European influence, a form of the infini
tesimal calculus under the name of "circle principle." The Japanese
anticipated us in the discovery of both determinants and what we call
" Homer s method." But on the whole
Japanese mathematics was exquisite
rather than great.
"The
fourteen chapters of this book are all interesting.
and often remarkably beautiful."
trations are always elegant
The
Principle of Least Action.
JOURDAIN. Pages 83. Stiff covers.
The
By PHILIP
Price
is.
illus
Nature.
E.
B.
6d. net.
This historical and critical study consists of three parts. In the first part
a very thorough study, from the original sources, of the work of Maupertuis,
Euler, Daniel Bernoulli, Konig, d Arcy, Louis Bertrand, and others, is
made, and errors of Adolf Mayer, Mach, and Lord Morley corrected. In
the second part the development of views on the principle is traced again
in great detail
through Lagrange, Rodrigues, Jacobi, Ostrogradski, and
Hert/, up to the modern work of Holder, Voss, Rcthy, and the author,
which enables us to solve the problem discussed in the last part, on " The
Nature and Validity of the Principle of Least Action."
Here also the
early memoirs are subjected to criticism, and the outcome is not in all
respects consistent with the traditional view, which view seems partly due
to mistakes that can only be rectified by thorough historical research.
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
"
The discussion of the principle in question involved controversy doubly
or trebly acute, because not only mathematics but
metaphysical theology
and questions of priority were involved. Mr Jourdain refers to
every writer
on the subject, and his work will be indispensable to
subsequent inquirers."
Mathematical
Man
Gazette.
a Machine.
By JULIEN OFFRAY DE LA METTRIE.
Including Frederick the Great s Eulogy on La Mettrie and
Extracts from La Mettrie s "Natural History of the Soul."
Translated, with Notes, by GERTRUDE CARMAN BUSSEY.
French-English edition. With a portrait of La Mettrie.
Pages 226. Cloth, 6s. net.
La
Mettrie was the most extreme writer among the earliest French
His doctrine is an extension to man of Descartes doctrine
that animals are automata.
Both the French corrected original, which is
written in a lively and modern way, and English translation, and an
essay
on the philosophical position of La Mettrie with respect to earlier and
materialists.
subsequent writers, are included.
Problems of Science. By FEDERIGO ENRIQUES.
translation
Authorised
by KATHARINE ROYCE, with an Introduction
by JOSIAH ROYCE.
The volume here
Pages
xvi, 392.
Cloth, los. net.
is a
comprehensive and compendious survey
The
yet to be done in the scientific field.
six chapters deal with the so-called unsolved problems
the squaring of the
circle and perpetual motion ; the various phases of illusion and reality,
different kinds of facts which provide the data for the several sciences,
methods of acquiring knowledge and different degrees attained
the
problems of logic, first pure and then applied ; the principles of geometry
and the relation of geometry to physics ; a discussion of the problems of
time in its various aspects and also force statics, dynamics, mass, inertia ;
and lastly, the extension of mechanics, including the most recent discussion
of the theory of relativity.
This book is, as the Mathematical Gazette says, useful to those interested
either in philosophy or teaching.
of
translated
what has been done and
is
" The most valuable
portion of the work is the masterly analyses of the
fundamental ideas used in the mathematical and mechanical sciences.
.^.
It is for this that we would commend Professor Enriques s Problems of
.
Science to all philosophical students interested in epistomology."
Magazine.
Oxford
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
FOURTH THOUSAND OF MR BERTRAND RUSSELL S
"LOWELL LECTURES" OF 1914.
Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field
for Scientific Method in Philosophy. By BERTRAND
RUSSELL, M.A., F.R.S. Pages x, 245. Cloth, 75. 6d. net.
These eight " Lowell Lectures," delivered at Boston (Mass.) in March
and April 1914, attempt to show, by means of examples, the nature,
capacity, and limitations of the logico-analytical method in philosophy,
which, in the author s opinion, yields whatever scientific knowledge it is
It is because these lectures give the first published
possible to obtain.
indication of the new investigations to which the logical and analytical
school, of which Mr Russell is the most prominent exponent, is now
tending, that they must be read and studied by all who are interested in
science OF philosophy, or scientific philosophy.
They are on "Current
"
Tendencies,"
Logic as the Essence of Philosophy/ "Our Knowledge of
the External World," "The World of Physics and the World of Sense,"
The Theory of Continuity," "The Problem of Infinity considered Histori
cally," "The Positive Theory of Infinity," and "The Notion of Cause,
with Applications to the Free- Will Problem." These lectures are written,
as the Mathematical Gazette says, with that clearness, force, and subtle
humour that readers of Mr Russell s other works have learnt to expect.
" The book of the
year. ... It is in every sense an epoch-making
Cambridge Magazine.
"This brilliant, lucid, amusing book, which, in spite of a few stift
The New Statesman.
passages, everyone can understand."
"His method interests by the success with which it approximates
These able and suggestive lectures will in
philosophy to science.
book."
troduce thoughtful readers to a tract of speculative inquiry not yet much
opened up, which promises good results to men with philosophic interests
and scientific training." Scotsman.
"The author maintains the fresh and brilliant yet easy style which
always makes his writings a pleasure to read." Nature.
" In some
respects the most important contribution that has been made
to philosophy for a long time past.
The whole book is of extreme interest,
and it abounds in good sayings."
The International Journal of Ethics.
Other reprints of classics on, and original works on sciences,
philosophies, and religions are dealt with in the Open Court
Company s Catalogue
(sent
publishes a splendid series
The Company also
post free).
of portraits of philosophers and
men, and two magazines The Open Court (6d. per
copy, 55. 6d. per year, post free), and The Monist (25. 6d. per
copy, 95. 6d. per year, post free), both of which contain
scientific
articles
interest.
by leading
men
of philosophical, scientific, or religious
io
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
A New Series of Important Books published
THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
by
THE OPEN COURT CLASSICS OF
SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY
"
HISTORICAL
of a
studies," says
scientific
problems,
Mach, "are a very
essential part
They acquaint us with other
hypotheses, and other modes of viewing
education.
other
things, as well as with the facts
and conditions
of their origin,
growth, and eventual decay." Again: "They who know
the entire course of the development of science will, as a
matter of course, judge more freely and more correctly of
the significance of any present scientific movement than they
who, limited in their views to the age in which their own
lives
have been spent, contemplate merely the momentary
trend that
the
course of
intellectual
takes
events
at
the
And this is by no means all. Those who
present moment.
have studied any of the great works which have built up the
science and philosophy of to-day have felt their extraordinarily
7
and stimulating power. Perhaps students feel this
with the works of the older masters these works
more
even
suggestive
with departments of knowledge with which the
often
familiar.
He does not yet, perhaps, feel
is
more
student
with
the
familiar
exceedingly specialised aims and
quite
deal
methods of much of the present-day science, and
the need of knowing something of the often more
that were the fathers and grandfathers, so to
views
general
Then there is always
views we hold to-day.
those
of
speak,
a possibility that the masters may suggest to us some new
precise
does
feel
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
and
fruitful
path
that
of investigation
we would otherwise
And
the false and
again, even the errors
untenable hypotheses and so on in the older works stand
out more clearly to the student of to-day, and both prompt
have overlooked.
on modern theories and afford a valuable training
such errors. This
reflection
in sharpness of sight for the detection of
is
perhaps the most valuable aid that history can give to
research.
But we must not neglect the fact that probably because
we have been brought up in surroundings which are almost
wholly due to the conquests made by science and philosophy,
and possibly because we ourselves are so formed physio
logically as to
than
men
be better able to carry out
of past
scientific thinking
some considerations which
generations
were of the greatest importance in the past are comparatively
unimportant at the present time. This is the case with very
many experimental
We
researches.
have become so used
to thinking in terms of certain refinements of apparatus,
and
apparatus is so easily obtainable, that the description of
cruder apparatus is often not only wearisome but really of
no advantage. Of course, this does not apply to the deeply
this
means whereby, for example, Galileo measured
time without the use of those clocks which were only made
interesting
possible by his dynamical results.
When we have once arrived at a scientific proof, the way in
which other people arrived at it loses much of its importance.
We may, and probably do, feel a great interest in such ques
tions,
but the fact that the connections of truths are independ
ent of
to
how people
recognise them is strongly brought home
In a science we are primarily concerned with the
us.
its subject-matter
not with the history of how
discovered
some
of
these
truths.
people
History itself is a
but
in
we
not
are
science,
history
primarily concerned with
truths about
historians
there
is
and how they wrote their histories. But though
no necessary connection between the fact that A
A SELECTION FROM THE PUBLICATIONS
12
some person C found, by the
the
implies B,
knowledge of the fact last
be very often indispensable for us human
beings in rising to the discovery by ourselves of the thing C
The history of a science has a heuristic value
discovered.
B and
implies
the fact that
process D, that
named seems to
This heuristic value
for the student of that science.
is
partly
and suggestions contained in,
works of the masters
and this stimulus and
due
to the stimulus afforded by,
the
original
suggestiveness hardly every finds its way into text books.
Secondly, there are often unworked mines of definite sugges
for new researches in the
tion
by analogy, for example
Thirdly, science
original memoirs of the founders of* science.
often returns in its own progress to older points of view.
Fourthly, historical studies have been shown, by many brilliant
and criticism
works, to afford a valuable basis for criticism
that
is
important for new transformations of science.
Lastly,
students will be relieved and stimulated to find that the great
All mis
discoverers at first made mistakes like themselves.
takes
are
not due
to
stupidity,
and mistakes often
are as
new
important as correctnesses, because they give
the
For this last reason,
considerations.
early manuscripts of
for
worth
Leibniz,
study by beginners in
example, are well
rise
to
the calculus.
In
this
series
of
scientific
classics
the
requirements of
As to the form of
students and teachers are kept in mind.
on
are
these little volumes
good paper, and
printed
they
with margins so wide that notes can be conveniently written
:
upon them by the
students.
They
are
produced
in
such a
go easily into an outside pocket, and are
they
in cloth which is durable, and pleasant to the hand
size that
will
bound
and eye.
The translations are carefully made, thoroughly revised,
Of course, a note to this
and the notation modernised.
effect is added when necessary, because the historical interest
must be kept in view. Any figures are included in the text
OF THE OPEN COURT COMPANY
13
which explain difficult passages or give references
and later important work on the same subject are
added by competent authorities, and it is hoped that by this
Lastly, notes
to earlier
the value of the scientific classics will
Where
be greatly increased.
seems advisable, the places where the pages of the
original publication begin and end are indicated, so that refer
ences to the originals may easily be verified in these editions.
it
The
prices have
been kept as low as
possible, but the
first
consideration has been serviceability and goodness of material.
The series will include memoirs from pure mathematics
and
all
feature
and philosophy; and a special
be the inclusion of quite modern researches.
the authors whose work will be published are
Maxwell,
the natural sciences
will
Among
Helmholtz, Gauss, Volta,
Cauchy,
Dirchlet,
Leibniz,
Descartes,,
Ohm,
Riemann,
Bolzano,
Oersted, KirchhofT, Carnot,
Weierstrass,
Lagrange,
Cantor,
Laplace,
Newton,
Lavoisier,
Mayer, Joule, Neumann, Zeno, Voltaire, Diderot, and
many
others.
The
No.
following volumes have been already published
i. Contributions to the Founding of the
Theory
of Transfinite Numbers.
By GEORG CANTOR.
Translated, and provided with an Introduction and Notes,
by PHILIP E. B. JOURDAIN, M.A. Cloth. 35. 6d. net.
This volume contains a translation of the two very important memoirs
Georg Cantor on transfinite numbers which appeared in 1895 and 1897.
These memoirs are the final and logically purified statement of many of
the most important results of the long series of memoirs begun by Cantor
in 1870.
A very full historical account of this work and the work of others
which led up to it is given in the introduction, and the notes at the end
contain indications of the progress made in the theory of transfinite
numbers since 1897. This book is a companion volume to Dedekind s
Msiays, of which a translation has been issued by the present publishers.
of
No.
Selections from the Scottish Philosophy of
Sense. Edited by G. A. JOHNSTON, M.A.,
Lecturer in Philosophy at Glasgow University.
Cloth.
2.
Common
35. 6d. net.
14
THE OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS
This volume consists of extracts from the works of the chief representa
Common Sense. The selections have
Reid s Inquiry into the Human Mind
on the Principles of Common Sense, and Essays ; but these have been
supplemented by important or typical passages from Stewart, Beattie, and
Most of the selections are metaphysical or psychological, but
Ferguson.
ethical doctrines have not been neglected.
In the introduction an attempt
has been made to estimate Reid s historical importance in connection with
the Locke-Berkeley-Hume development of thought, and in relation to
Kant s "answer to Hume." The Scottish Philosophy contains much that
is interesting and valuable, but it has not been readily accessible to the.
student, partly because the writings of its representatives are prolix to a
These
degree, and partly because their books are not easily obtainable.
And
facts constitute the sufficient justification of such a volume as this.
at a time when much interest is being taken in New Realism, it may not
be out of place that some attention should be paid to the Natural Realism
tives pf the Scottish Philosophy of
been made, for the most part, from
of the Scottish Philosophy.
THE OPEN COURT COMPANY,
149 Strand, London,
W.C.
RETURN
TO:
MATHEMATICS-STATISTICS LIBRARY
1
00 Evans
Hall
51 0-642-3381
All books may be recalled. Return to desk from which borrowed.
To renew online, type "inv" and patron ID on any GLADIS screen.
U. C.
BERKELEY LIBRARIES
STAT.